Skip to main content

Experimentation as Communication with Nature

  • Chapter
Information and Inference

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 28))

Abstract

There is an obvious analogy between experimentation and communication over a noisy channel. The parameter space of an assumed model plays the role of source or message ensemble from which the input, the true state of nature, is selected. The latter is transmitted by the experiment to the target, the experimenter, who then decodes the message. Noise enters in the form of sampling error, the masking effects of hidden variables, and uncontrolled variation in the experimental materials.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Bibliography

  • Adams, E. W.: 1966, ‘On the Nature and Purpose of Measurement’, Synthese 16, 125 - 168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Attneave, F. J.: 1954, ‘Some Informational Aspects of Visual Perception’, Psych. Review 61, 183 - 193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Attneave, F. J.: 1959, Applications of Information Theory to Psychology, Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, New York. Blackwell, D. and Girshick, M. A.: 1954, Theory of Games and Statistical Decisions, Wiley, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackwell, D. and Girschick, M. A.: 1954, Theory of Games and Statistical Decisions, Wiley, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R. A.: 1922, ‘On the Foundations of Theoretical Statistics’, Phil. Trans. Roy. Soc.. London A222, 309 - 368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R. A.: 1934, ‘Probability, Likelihood, and Quantity of Information in the Logic or Uncertain Inference’, Proc. Roy. Soc., London A146, 1 - 8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foster, M. H. and Martin, M. L. (eds.): 1966, Probability, Confirmation and Simplicity, Odyssey Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garner, W. R.: 1962, Uncertainty and Structure as Psychological Concepts, Wiley, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garner, W. R. and McGill, W. J.: 1956, ‘Relation between Uncertainty, Variance, and Correlation Analyses’, Psychometrika 21. 219 - 228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Good, I. J.: 1968, ‘Corroboration, Explanation, Evolving Probabilities, Simplicity and a Sharpened Razor’, Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 19, 123 - 143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, K. J. J. and Pietarinen, J.: 1966, Semantic Information and Inductive Logicx, in Hintikka and Suppes (1966).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, K.J.J, and Suppes, P.(eds.): 1966, Aspects of Inductive Logic, North-Holland Publ. Co., Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khinchin, A. I.: 1957, Mathematical Foundations of Information Theory, translated from the Russian by R. A. Silverman and M. D. Friedman. Dover, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kullback, S.: 1959, information Theory and Statistics, Wiley, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kullback, S. and Leibleir, R. A.: 1951, ‘On Information and Sufficiency’, Ann. Math. Stat. 22, 79 - 86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehmann, E.: 1959, Testing Statistical Hypotheses, Wiley. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindley, D. V.: 1956, ‘On a Measure of Information provided by an Experiment’, Ann. Math. Stat. 29, 986 - 1005.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGill, W. J.: 1954, ‘Multivariate Information Transmission’, Psychometrika 19, 97 - 116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, G. A.: 1956, ‘The Magic Number Seven, Plus or Minus Two’, Psych. Review 63, 81 - 97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, G. A. and Madow, W. G.: 1954, On the Maximum Likelihood Estimate of the Shannon-Wiener Measure of information, Air Force Cambridge Research Center: Technical Report, 54 - 75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R.: 1935, Logik der Forschung, Julius Springer, Wien. Engl, transl. with notes and appendices under the title The Logic of Scientific Discovery, Hutchinson, London, 1959.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raiffa, H. and Schlaifer, R.: 1961, Applied Statistical Decision Theory, Harvard Business School, Boston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L. J.: 1954, The Foundations of Statistics, Wiley, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shannon. C. E. and Weaver. W.: 1949. The Mathenuitical Theory of Communication, Univ. of Illinois Press, Urbana, I II.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sneed, J.: 1967, ‘Entropy, Information and Decision’, Synthese 17, 392 407.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P.: 1966, P.: 1966, ‘A Bayesian Approach to the Paradoxes of Confirmation’, in Hintikka and Suppes (1966).

    Google Scholar 

References

  1. Notation: a tilde distinguishes a random variable - qua function - from its generic value. In conjunction with an expectation sign a tilde indicates the random variable being expected, while subscripts ω, ‘ω/z’, ‘z/e’ etc., appended to an expectation sign indicate the measuresπ(ω), π(ω/z), Pz/e, etc., with respect to which the expectation is taken. Finally, a single prime indicates expectation against a prior distribution; a double prime, expectation against a posterior distribution. The notation is that of Raiffa and Schlaifer (1961) and is adhered to throughout. The present section, up to the discussion of Neyman-Pearson theory, is little more than a summary of their more detailed exposition.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Khinchin (1957), p. 9f.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Shannon and Weaver (1949), p. 49f.

    Google Scholar 

  4. An appropriate counterexample appeared for the first time in Sneed (1967).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Specimen articles (by Ackermann, Barker, Goodman and Rudner) may be found in Philosophy of Science 28; cf. also Foster and Martin (1966).

    Google Scholar 

  6. For an interesting motivation of this measure which turns on regarding information as an ‘epistemic utility’, see Hintikka and Pietarinen (1966), p. 108. Popper himself has proposed an analogous measure.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1970 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht-Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rosenkrantz, R. (1970). Experimentation as Communication with Nature. In: Hintikka, J., Suppes, P. (eds) Information and Inference. Synthese Library, vol 28. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-3296-4_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-3296-4_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-3298-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-3296-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics