Skip to main content

Art and Objectivity

  • Chapter
Speaking of Art
  • 91 Accesses

Abstract

This book has been, to a large degree, polemical. It has presented a thesis, but has occupied itself more, perhaps, with defense than with exposition. There is some justification for this besides the disputative disposition of its author.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Plato, Ion, trans. W. R. M. Lamb, 535.

    Google Scholar 

  2. ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Ibid., 533.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ibid., 536.

    Google Scholar 

  5. For a defense of the Ion as an examination of criticism, see Craig La Drière, “The Problem of Plato’s Ion,”Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, X (1951).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ion, 536. It is important to observe that Plato is concerned here only with the way we talk about poetry. In fact, he contrasts poetry-talk sharply with the way we talk about painting, sculpture, and music (532–533). One who knows painting, sculpture, or music can make knowledgeable judgments about all painting, sculpture, or music. But Ion can only say sensible things about one poet: Homer. And this is supposed to show, according to Socrates, that talking well about painting, sculpture, and music gives evidence of knowledge, whereas speaking well only of Homer does not give evidence of knowledge at all — hence the “inspiration” theory of the rhapsode. But as the modern system of the arts developed, Socrates’ conclusion about poetry was extended to all of the other “fine arts” as well.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Elizabethan Critical Essays, ed. G. Gregory Smith (London: Oxford University Press, 1904), vol. II, p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid., vol. I, p. 195.

    Google Scholar 

  9. “Of Beauty,” Essays, Advancement of Learning, New Atlantis, and Other Pieces, ed. R. F. Jones (New York: Odyssey Press, 1937), p. 125.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Critical Essays of the Seventeenth Century, ed. J. E. Spingarn (London: Oxford University Press, 1957), vol. I, pp. 4–5.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Republic, trans. F. M. Cornford, 596.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid., 597.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ibid., 598.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid., 600.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Marcia Cavell, “Critical Dialogue,” The Journal of Philosophy, LXVII (1970), p. 340.

    Google Scholar 

  16. George Santayana, The Sense of Beauty (New York: Random House, 1955), p. 50.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Toulmin, op. cit., p. 10.

    Google Scholar 

  18. G. E. Moore, Ethics (London: Oxford University Press, 1958), pp. 63–64.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Critique of Aesthetic Judgement, p. 206.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid., pp. 51–52.

    Google Scholar 

  21. “Wittgenstein On Aesthetics,” p. 386.

    Google Scholar 

  22. J. D. Mabbott, “Freewill and Punishment,” Contemporary British Philosophy, Third Series, ed. H. D. Lewis (London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: Macmillan, 1961), pp. 306–307.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Sibley and Tanner, “Objectivity and Aesthetics,” p. 34.

    Google Scholar 

  24. “Of the Standard of Taste,” p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Sibley and Tanner, op. cit., p. 66. The remark quoted is Tanner’s.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Cf. R. B. Brandt, Ethical Theory (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1959) pp. 99–101.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Eduard Hanslick, The Beautiful in Music, trans. Gustav Cohen (New York: Liberal Arts Press, 1957), p. 29.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Edmund Gurney, The Power of Sound (London: Smith, Elder, and Co., 1880), pp. 339–340.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Charles Hartshorne, Philosophy and Psychology of Sensation (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1934), p. 186.

    Google Scholar 

  31. “The Concept of Expression in Art,” pp. 42–43.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Sibley and Tanner, op. cit., p. 38.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Tanner, “Objectivity and Aesthetics,” Ibid., p. 35.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Tanner, “Objectivity and Aesthetics,” Ibid. p. 63.

    Google Scholar 

  35. See, for example, Marcia P. Freedman, “The Myth of the Aesthetic Predicate,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, XXVII (1968).

    Google Scholar 

  36. Cf. Dorothy Walsh, “Aesthetic Descriptions,” The British Journal of Aesthetics, X (1970).

    Google Scholar 

  37. Eva Schaper and Frank Sibley, “Symposium: About Taste,” The British Journal of Aesthetics, VI (1966), p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1973 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kivy, P. (1973). Art and Objectivity. In: Speaking of Art. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2412-9_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2412-9_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-247-1491-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-2412-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics