Skip to main content

The Clarification of the Concept of Phenomenon: Ontological Monism

  • Chapter
The Essence of Manifestation

Abstract

Phenomenology is the science of phenomena. This means that it is a description anterior to all theory and independent of all presuppositions, of everything that presents itself to us as existant, regardless of order or domain. Understood as a description, phenomenology implies the rejection of all hypotheses, of all principles having some unifying value, whether real or supposed, with regard to some area of knowledge, and finally, the rejection of a sector of reality which would contain in it a rule of intelligibility as a necessary condition for its existence. Science, it is true, is concerned with going beyond the facts and coordinates them into systems of explanation. But in all cases, the scientific element and the totality, to which it belongs, necessarily refer to a phenomenological datum without which they could have no meaning whatever. Moreover, these elements and these systems themselves exist for us only under the rubric of data. They are juxtaposed in the phenomenological milieu within the very reality which they pretend to explain. [60] By consequence, this reality will never be capable of total reduction, any more than the scientific reality itself in all its forms will be capable of total reduction. Once their explanatory value is put between parentheses (and remains in this condition), these theories penetrate our environment as data.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 259.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Edmund Husserl, Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology, tr. W.R. Boyce Gibson. (New York: Humanities Press Inc., 1969) 84.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Max Scheler, “Die Idole der Selbsterkenntnis” in Vom Umsturz der Werte, in Gesammelte Werke, III. (Bern: Franke, 1955) 215.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Cf. Ibid. 225.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Edmund Husserl, Cartesian Meditations, tr. Dorion Cairns. (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1969) 48.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cf. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, tr. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. (New York: Harper and Row, 1962) 272.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Martin Heidegger, Holzwege. (Frankfurt-am-Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1950) 129.

    Google Scholar 

  8. G.W.F. Hegel, The Phenomenology of Mind, tr. J.B. Baillie. (New York: Humanities Press Inc., 1966) 134.

    Google Scholar 

  9. M. Heidegger, Being and Time. 62.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Logos (1913), cited by Scheler in Idole. 246.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Gassendi in “objections Against the Meditations of Descartes”, in The Philosophical Works of Descartes, II, tr. Elizabeth S. Haldane and G.R.T. Ross. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1967) 162–63.

    Google Scholar 

  12. L. Malverne, “La condition de l’être”, in La Revue de la Métaphysique et Morale, January 1949, p. 42.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, tr. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. (New York: Harper and Row, 1962) 139.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Martin Heidegger, The Essence of Reasons, tr. Terrence Malick. (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1969) 131.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Edmund Husserl, Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology, tr. W.R. Boyce Gibson. (New York: Humanities Press Inc., 1969) 194.

    Google Scholar 

  16. J.G. Fichte, Die Anweisung zum Seligen Leben, in Sämmtliche Werke, V. (Berlin: Veit; 1845) 440.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid. 441.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid. 462.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid. 442.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid. 480.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid. 509.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid. 402.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid. 512. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  25. Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness, tr. Hazel E. Barnes. (New York: Philosophical Library, 1956) 77.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  27. M. Dufrenne, “Heidegger et Kant”, in La Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, January 1949, p. 16. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  28. Fichte, Die Anweisung…, 402. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  29. Friedrich Hölderlin, Ausgewählte Werke, ed. Schwab. (Stuttgart: 1874) 284.

    Google Scholar 

  30. F. Alquié, “L’Etre et le Néant de Jean-Paul Sartre”, in Cahiers du Sud, XXIII (1945), p. 654.

    Google Scholar 

  31. F. Jeanson, Le problème moral et la pensée de Sartre, (Paris: Editions du Myrte, 1947) 233.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Martin Heidegger, Holzwege. (Frankfurt-am-Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1950) 161.

    Google Scholar 

  33. J.G. Fichte, Die Anweisung zum Seligen Leben, in Sämmtliche Werke, V. (Berlin: Veit, 1845) 440. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ibid. 441. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Friedrich von Schelling, System der Transcendentalen Idealismus in Sämmtliche Werke, III. (Stuttgart-Augsburg: Cottascher; 1858) 600. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid. 602. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ibid. 500.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ibid. 506.

    Google Scholar 

  40. W. Jankelevitch, L’Odyssie de la conscience dans la dernière philosophie de Schelling. (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1933) 159.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Cf. Infra, Appendix.

    Google Scholar 

  42. This becomes obvious in Sartre, for example, when he sees in the “rupture in the identity-of-Being…” in “a withdrawal by Being in relation to itself and the appearance of presence to self or consciousness.” Being and Nothingness, tr. Hazel E. Barnes. (New York: Philosophical Library, 1956) 620.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Renouvier speaks of “this splitting of representation which is consciousness.” Traité de Psychologie rationelle d’après les principes du criticisme, I. (Paris: Colin, 1912) 286.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Fichte, Die Anweisung…, 441. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ibid. 440. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  46. Heidegger, Holzwege. 133. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  47. Ibid. 134. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  48. Schelling, System des Transcendentalen Idealismus. 506.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Renouvier, Traité, II. 56. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  50. Schelling, System des Transcendentalen Idealismus. 391.

    Google Scholar 

  51. G.W.F. Hegel, Differenz des Fichte’schen und Schelling’schen Systems der Philosophie, in Gesammelte Werke, IV, ed. H. Buchner und O. Pöggeler. (Hamburg: F. Meiner, 1968) 41.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, tr. Colin Smith. (New York: Humanities Press Inc., 1962) 540.

    Google Scholar 

  53. “Consciousness is an abstraction.” Sartre, Being and Nothingness. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Ibid. 618. “The deeper reasons for this affirmation and hence its true significanie will become progressively more evident to us.” Cf. Infra Chapter 28.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Ibid. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  57. This definition of consciousness is accepted by Heidegger. Cf. Being and Time, tr. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. (New York: Harper and Row, 1962) 170.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Sartre, Being and Nothingness. 177.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Ibid. 179.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  61. G.W.F. Hegel, The Phenomenology of Mind, tr. J.B. Baillie. (New York: Humanities Press Inc., 1966) 426.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Edmund Husserl, Cartesian Meditations, tr. Dorion Cairns. (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1969). “In this connexion furthermore, it must by no means be accepted as a matter of course that, with our apodictic pure ego, we have rescued a little tag-end of the world.” (p. 24) And further on: “This Ego, with his Ego-life… is not a piece of the world.” (p. 25)

    Google Scholar 

  63. Heidegger, Being and Time. 252.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Ibid. 418.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Heidegger, Holzwege. 134.

    Google Scholar 

  66. “The commentators who have penetrated the thought of Heidegger have perceived this identity of subjectivity with the world as such, an identity which constitutes the most profound aspect of ontological monism.” Cf. J. Beaufret: “It is in the closest intimacy that the bursting forth of light is produced which concerns everyone in his most intimate being.” “Heidegger et le problème de la vérité”, in La Revue Fontaine, November 1947, p. 770.

    Google Scholar 

  67. H. Birault also speaks of “light which is at one and the same time both that of Being and that of a being which we are”, in La Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, January-March, 1951, p. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Sartre, Being and Nothingness. 11. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  69. Cf. J.P. Sartre, Being and Nothingness. 73. This “new conception” is actually the setting free of a very ancient concept pushed to the limit.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception. 377. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  71. Ibid. 293. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  72. Lachelier, Psychologie et Métaphysique. (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1949) 54. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  73. Ibid. 56.

    Google Scholar 

  74. John B. Watson, The Ways of Behaviorism. (New York: Harper and Brothers, 1928) 7.

    Google Scholar 

  75. This appeal appears as the leitmotif of the behaviorist critique leveled against philosophy, of consciousness. For example, here is another text aimed more precisely at the classical meanings of memory and image, namely, as fects of consciousness. “But the behaviorist, having made a clean sweep of all the rubbish called conscious ness, comes back at you: ‘Prove to me’, he says, ‘that you have auditory images, visual images, or any other kinds of disembodied processes. So far I have only your unverified and unsupported word that you have them’ “Ibid. 75. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  76. No less naïve and contradictory was the position of CI. Bernard in the last century when he confronted philosophy as an empty if not harmful science, a mere exercise in mental gymnastics, with his fundamental proposition according to which “there is nothing outside of experience.” Philosophy is precisely the science of experience as such. It is necessary, once again, to see that experience constitutes a problem. To bring oneself to understanding this problem is to be a philosopher.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Sartre, Being and Nothingness. 73.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Heidegger, Holzwege. 134.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Cf. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, tr. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. (New York: Harper and Row, 1962) 85.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Martin Heidegger, Holzwege. (Frankfurt-am-Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1950) 161. [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  81. Ibid. 172–73 [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  82. Heidegger, Being and Time. 264.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Ibid. By the ‘world’ Heidegger here means the totality of existents. This is why he puts the word ‘world’ in quotes.

    Google Scholar 

  84. “Descartes,” writes Heidegger, “explicitly switches over philosophically from the development of traditional ontology to modern mathematical physics and its transcendental foundations.” Being and Time. 129.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Ibid. 131.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Concerning this, cf. Heidegger, Being and Time. 266 sqq.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Being and Time. 418.

    Google Scholar 

  88. “This nothing is human reality itself.” Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness, tr. Hazel E. Barnes. (New York: Philosophical Library, 1956) 181.

    Google Scholar 

  89. G.W.F. Hegel, The Phenomenology of Mind, tr. J.B. Baillie. (New York: Humanities Press Inc., 1966) 115.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Martin Heidegger, Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, tr. James S. Churchill. (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1962) 174.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Martin Heidegger, Holzwege. (Frankfurt-am-Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1950) 190.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Cf. Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness, tr. Hazel E. Barnes. (New York: Philosophical Library, 1956) 81–2.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Ibid. 618.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Ibid. xlix.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Ibid. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Ibid. 216.

    Google Scholar 

  97. G.W.F. Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of History, tr. J. Sibree. (London: George Bell and Sons, 1888) 181.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Ibid. 198–99.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Kierkegaard says that in Greece sensuality (sensibility) is not culpability but enigma. According to Kierkegaard, the meaning of Greek plasticity resides in the enigmatic character of the sensual (sensible). Cf. The Concept of Dread, tr. W. Lowrie, 2 ed. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1957) 58.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Cf. Appendix, Chapter 76.

    Google Scholar 

  101. A. Koyré, La Philosophie de Jacob Boehme. (Paris: Vrin, 1929) 303–414.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Friedrich von Schelling, System des Transcendentalen Idealismus, in Sammtliehe Werke, III. (Stuttgart-Augsburg: Cottascher; 1858) 365.

    Google Scholar 

  103. Ibid. 390.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Ibid. 380.

    Google Scholar 

  105. W. Jankelevitch, L’Odyssie de la conscience dans la dernière philosophie de Schelling. (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1933) 183.

    Google Scholar 

  106. G.W.F. Hegel, The Phenomenology of Mind, tr. J.B. Baillie. (New York: Humanities Press Inc., 1966) 806.

    Google Scholar 

  107. G.W.F. Hegel, The Spirit of Christianity and its Fate, in Early Theological Writings, tr. T.M. Knox. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1948) 293–94.

    Google Scholar 

  108. Ibid. 295.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Hegel, The Phenomenology of Mind. 760.

    Google Scholar 

  110. J.G. Fichte, Die Anweisung zum Seligen Leben in Sammtliche Werke, V (Berlin: Veit; 1845), 455–56.

    Google Scholar 

  111. Ibid. 456 [Henry’s italics]

    Google Scholar 

  112. Ibid. 457.

    Google Scholar 

  113. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  115. Ibid. 471.

    Google Scholar 

  116. Friedrich von Schelling, System des Transcendentalen Idealismus, in Sammtliche Werke, III (Stuttgart-Augsburg: Cottascher; 1858) 391.

    Google Scholar 

  117. Ibid. 396.

    Google Scholar 

  118. Ibid. 345.

    Google Scholar 

  119. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  120. “The only immediate object of the transcendental point of view is the subjective [namely, the pure essence, the transcendental, the absolutely non-objective element] the only organ of this philosophy is the inner sense”, Ibid. 350.

    Google Scholar 

  121. Koyré, La Philosophie de Jacob Boehme. 243.

    Google Scholar 

  122. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, tr. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. (New York: Harper and Row, 1962) 170.

    Google Scholar 

  123. Ibid. 255.

    Google Scholar 

  124. Karl Marx, Critique of Hegel’s Dialectic and General Philosophy, in Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts, tr. T.B. Bottomore, in Erich Fromm, Marx’s Concept of Man. (New York: Frederick Ungar Co., 1966) 188.

    Google Scholar 

  125. Martin Heidegger, Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, tr. James S. Churchill. (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1962) 229.

    Google Scholar 

  126. Martin Heidegger, The Essence of Reasons, tr. Terrence Malick (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1969) 127.

    Google Scholar 

  127. Edmund Husserl, Erfahrung und Urteil. (Hamburg: Classen und Coverts, 1948) 159.

    Google Scholar 

  128. Ibid. 259.

    Google Scholar 

  129. Martin Heidegger, What is Metaphysics?, in Existence and Being, tr. R.F.C. Hull and Allan Crick. (London: Vision Press Ltd., 1949) 378.

    Google Scholar 

  130. Martin Heidegger Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, tr. James S. Churchill. (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1962) 230.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1973 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Henry, M. (1973). The Clarification of the Concept of Phenomenon: Ontological Monism. In: The Essence of Manifestation. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2391-7_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2391-7_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-247-1350-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-2391-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics