Skip to main content

Can Terrorism Ever Be Morally Justified?

  • Chapter
Terrorism

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 101))

Abstract

It is disappointing that much of what has been written that purports to deal with terrorism ends up not pertaining to terrorism at all, but only to particular forms of violent activity-either state or individual. Perhaps this is due at least in part to writers not devoting sufficient attention to the exploration of the definitional conditions of terrorism. For example, in Leon Trotsky’s work, Terrorism and Communism? “terrorism” is not defined. Nor is terrorist activity contrasted with other significant forms of violence such as revolution, assassination, etc. Although Trotsky argues that the communist revolution does not “logically” require the revolutionaries’ employment of terrorism, it does require that any means necessary are to be used to secure revolutionary power, even by terrorism. Terrorism, for Trotsky, is a form of justified violence when it is a matter of self-defense and is an act of intimidation by revolutionary forces against an oppressive state:

If human life in general is sacred and inviolable, we must deny ourselves not only the use of terror, not only war, but also revolution itself. … As long as human labor power, and, consequently, life itself, remain articles of sale and purchase, of exploitation and robbery, the principle of the “sacredness of human life” remains a shameful lie, uttered with the object of keeping the oppressed slaves in their chains.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. For an interesting and informative discussion of state terrorism, see Jonathan Glover, “State Terrorism,” in R. G. Frey and Christopher Morris, Editors, Violence, Terrorism, and Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 256–75.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  2. Leon Trotsky, Terrorism and Communism (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1961). This work was originally published in the United States as Dictatorship vs. Democracy and in Great Britain as The Defence of Terrorism.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Even though Trotsky, in his 1935 Preface to the Second English Edition, admits that it was the Editor’s idea to include “terrorism” in the book’s title, and that Trotsky’s own concern is “not at all the defence of ‘terrorism’ as such,” it leads to much confusion when he devotes an entire chapter to terrorism without either defining it or providing its justification (moral or otherwise).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Trotsky, Terrorism and Communism, p. pp58; Walter Laqueur, Terrorism (Boston: Little, Brown and Company, 1977), pp. 67–8.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Trotsky, Terrorism and Communism, pp. 58–9.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Trotsky, Terrorism and Communism, p. 62.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Trotsky, Terrorism and Communism, p. 58.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Trotsky, Terrorism and Communism, pp. 62–3.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Laqueur, Terrorism, p. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Laqueur, Terrorism, p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Walter Laqueur, A History of Terrorism (New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 2002), p. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  12. There is some recognition that the questions of the definition of “terrorism” and its justification need to be considered separately. For example, Virginia Held states that the definitional question is often confused with the matter of the legal justification of terrorism as a practice of political change [Virginia Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” in R. G. Frey and Christopher Morris, Editors, Violence, Terrorism, and Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 59]. But this is not the same as pointing to the conflating of the questions of the definition of “terrorism” and its moral justification, as I argue. Moreover, R. G Frey and Christopher Morris recognize that there exist two such separate questions, but they state that “they are hard to separate” (Frey and Morris, Violence, Terrorism, and Justice, p. 1). They do not, however, insist that the two questions be separated as a matter of analyzing terrorism, as I do. Finally, Terrence L. Moore argues that if we construe “terrorism” as by definition immoral, then inevitable disagreements about the morality of terrorism will surely lead to disagreements about what in fact terrorism amounts to [Terrence L. Moore, “The Nature and Evaluation of Terrorism,” Ph.D. dissertation, University of Pittsburgh, 1987, p. 59]. My point, of course, is not simply that sneaking the harming of non-combatants or innocents into the definition of “terrorism” leads to further disagreements in discussing terrorism, but that doing so begs the moral question against terrorism. This point is recognized by G. Wallace. However, while Wallace attempts to avoid the problem of conflating the nature and justification of terrorism by “doing without a formal definition of terrorism,” [G. Wallace, “Terrorism and the Argument From Analogy,” Internationaljournal of Moral and Social Issues, 6 (1991), p. 150], I set forth and explicate a definition of “terrorism” in distinguishing the questions of the nature, moral justification, and possible role of terrorism.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  13. C. A. J. Coady, “The Morality of Terrorism,” Philosophy, 60 (1985), p. 65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Igor Primoratz, “What is Terrorism?” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 7 (1990), p. 133. It is noteworthy that in his critique of Igor Primoratz’s definition of “terrorism,” Walter Sinnott-Armstrong does not challenge Primoratz’s idea that targeting the innocent is essential to terrorism [Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, “On Primoratz’s Definition of Terrorism,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 8 (1991), pp. 115–120]. For another critique of Primoratz’s definition of “terrorism,” see Tony Dardis, “Primoratz on Terrorism,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 9 (1992), pp. 93–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1980), p. 145. Held argues that not only has ordinary language use wreaked havoc in defining the nature of terrorism, but it has also tended to build into such definitions of terrorism a moral (prejudgment against it. Such biases make it impossible to even question, philosophically, whether or not terrorism can ever be morally justified. Even thinkers as well respected as Michael Walzer have assumed that terrorism is morally wrong without offering arguments against its immorality (See Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” p. 65).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Another position against the moral justification of terrorism is articulated in Haig Khatchadourian, “Terrorism and Morality,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 5 (1988), pp. 131–45; The Morality of Terrorism (New York: Peter Lang Publishing, 1998), Chapters 2–4. It is noteworthy, however, that even if intentionally harming innocent persons turns out to be essential to terrorism, it is not obvious that terrorism would always be morally unjustified, as is argued in Gerry Wallace, “Area Bombing, Terrorism and the Death of Innocents,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 6 (1989), pp. 3–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Coady, “The Morality of Terrorism,” p. 52. Another of those who seeks to conflate the two questions of the definition of “terrorism” and the moral justification of terrorism is Martin Hughes, “Terrorism and National Security,” Philosophy, 57 (1982), p. 5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Loren Lomasky, “The Political Significance of Terrorism,” in R.G. Frey and Christopher Morris, Editors, Violence, Terrorism, and Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 100, 104.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Jan Narveson, “Terrorism and Morality,” in R. G. Frey and Christopher Morris, Editors, Violence, Terrorism, and Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 119.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Carl Wellman, “On Terrorism Itself,” in Joe P. White, Editor, Assent/Dissent (Dubuque: Kendall/Hunt Publishing Company, 1984), pp. 254–5.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Noam Chomsky, 9/11 (New York: Seven Stories Press, 2001), p. 57.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Furthermore, Chomsky’s definition of “terrorism” wrongly ignores the fact that terrorism can be aimed at military targets, such as the cases of the 11 September 2001 attack on the U.S. Pentagon Building, the Jewish resistance (terrorist) attacks on the Nazi military during World War II, or even Native American terrorist attacks on the U.S. military during the U.S. military anti-Indian campaigns during the 19th Century.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Burleigh Taylor Wilkins, Terrorism and Collective Responsibility (London: Routledge, 1992), p. 6. Coady agrees that one of the distinctive points of terrorism is to destabilize social relations (Coady, “The Morality of Terrorism,” p. 53). However, Coady sees this as a matter of the sociology of terrorism, rather than as a point about the definition of “terrorism.”

    Book  Google Scholar 

  24. Annette Baier, “Violent Demonstrations,” in R.G. Frey and Christopher Morris, Editors, Violence, Terrorism, and Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 33–7.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  25. Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Alan Ryan, “State and Private: Red and White,” in R. G. Frey and Christopher Morris, Editors, Violence, Terrorism, and Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 230–55; Frey, R. G and Christopher Morris. “Violence, Terrorism, and Justice,” in R.G. Frey and Christopher Morris, Editors, Violence, Terrorism, and Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 15.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  27. Gregory S. Kavka, “Nuclear Hostages,” in R. G. Frey and Christopher Morris, Editors, Violence, Terrorism, and Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 276–95.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  28. Gordon Graham argues that “terrorists are enemies of the established state” and are “aimed against the state” [Gordon Graham, “Terrorism and Freedom Fighters,” Philosophy and Social Action, 11 (1985), p. 46]. However, as Bat-Ami Bar On states concerning the etymology of “terrorism,” ‘terrorism’ as a negative term was coined in 1795 by the French Directory to refer specifically to the repressive measures practiced by Robespierre’s government. It was later used to describe the activities of nineteenth-century clandestine oppositional groups in Russia. Not surprisingly, because these groups were considered revolutionary, ‘terrorism’ retained its negative connotations in the dictionaries of the time even though these groups were different from the French revolutionaries, and their ends differed also [Bat-Ami Bar On, “Why Terrorism is Morally Problematic,” in Claudia Card, Editor, Feminist Ethics (Lawrence: University of Kansas Press, 1991), pp. 109–110].

    Google Scholar 

  29. Compare this definition of “terrorism” to Jenny Teichman’s: Terrorism consists of violent actions carried out for political or other social purposes, including some large-scale mercenary purposes, by individuals or groups, having an aim which might be good or bad, but carried out by means of either or both of the following: 1, attacks on innocent or neutral or randomly chosen people, or 2, using means which involve atrocities, e.g., torture, cruel killings, or mutilation of the living or the dead, committed against randomly or non-randomly chosen people who may be innocent or not [Jenny Teichman, “How to Define Terrorism,” Philosophy, 64 (1989), p. 513]. Note that Teichman’s definition, unlike (f), does not count certain threats of violence as terrorism. Nor does her definition allow for one party to commit an act of terrorism on behalf of another. Finally, Teichman’s definition does not allow that property can be used as an object of terrorism to address a person or set of persons as the primary target of terrorism. On Teichman’s definition of “terrorism,” then, if a political group secured a quite valuable artifact of a government (perhaps some “top-secret” documents, “national treasures,” etc.), threatening to destroy it unless that government released certain political prisoners all of whom constitute a third party to this act, this act would not be a terrorist one. Whether or not this sort of action is in the end effective, there is little question that Teichman’s definition has failed to capture some important features of the nature of terrorism. Nonetheless, (f) shares the following commonalties with Teichman’s definition of “terrorism.” First, both are what Teichman refers to as “narrow stipulative definitions” of “terrorism.” Secondly, (f) and Teichman’s definition agree that one “ought not to begin by defining terrorism as a bad thing” (Teichman, “How to Define Terrorism,” p. 507). Also note the stated goals of terrorism as being political, social, economic or religious. Such goals are discussed as possible motivations in Jessica Stern, The Ultimate Terrorists (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999), Chapter 5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. G. Wallace, “The Language of Terrorism,” International Journal of Moral and Social Issues, 8 (1993), p. 125.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Kai Nielsen, “Political Violence and Ideological Mystification,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 13 (1982), p. 25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Wellman, “On Terrorism Itself,” pp. 254–5.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Wellman, “On Terrorism Itself,” p. 253.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Joel Feinberg, “Civil Disobedience in the Modern World,” Humanities in Society, 2 (1979), pp. 37–68; Richard Wasserstrom, “The Obligation to Obey the Law,” UCLA Law Review, 10 (1963).

    Google Scholar 

  35. Elsewhere Wellman minimizes the strength of the moral rights objection to terrorism because of related considerations. See Carl Wellman, “Terrorism and Moral Rights,” in John Howie, Editor, Ethical Principles and Practice (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1987), pp. 128–53.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysical Elements of Justice, John Ladd, Translator (London: Macmillan, 1965); Jeffrie G. Murphy, “Does Kant Have a Theory of Punishment?” Columbia Law Review, 87 (1987), pp. 510–32; “Kant’s Theory of Criminal Punishment,” in Jeffrie G. Murphy, Editor, Retribution, Justice and Therapy: Essays in the Philosophy of Law (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1979), pp. 82–92; Kant’s Philosophy of Right (New York: St. Martin’s, 1970); J. Angelo Corlett, “Foundations of a Kantian Theory of Punishment,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 31 (1993), pp. 263–83; Responsibility and Punishment (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2001), Chapter 4.

    Google Scholar 

  37. R.M. Hare, “On Terrorism,” in Joe. P. White, Editor, Assent/Dissent (Dubuque: Kendall/Hunt Publishing Company, 1984), pp. 247f. An alternative consequentialist analysis of the moral status of terrorism is found in Stephen T. Davis, “Is Terrorism Ever Morally Justified?” in Terrorism, Justice and Social Values, Creighton Peden and Y. Hudson, Editors (Lewiston: The Edwin Meilen Press, 1990), pp. 385–90.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Wilkins, Terrorism and Collective Responsibility, pp. 33–41.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Hare, “On Terrorism,” p. 248.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Michael Walzer, Obligations (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1970), p. 67.

    Google Scholar 

  41. The analysis of morally justified terrorism provided in this section is not set forth as an analysis of certain historical cases of morally justified terrorism. One difficulty with either defending or condemning particular historical instances of terrorism is the media’s biases in presenting the “facts” of a given terrorist act or event. Much of what counts as news reports on terrorism amounts to little more than propaganda and is of little use to philosophers in their attempts to judge the moral status of such terrorist actions. Few, if any, reports of terrorism will attempt to provide information about the possibility that the action or event was a response to significant injustice, or that the terrorists were conscientious in selecting targets, and so forth. In light of these factors, then, the following analysis is set forth and defended as one pertaining to the possibility of morally justified terrorism. Its significance lies in the fact that it stands as a challenge to what Wallace calls “non-neutral” definitions of “terrorism,” ones which “either assert or recommend that moral wrongness is built into the definition of terrorism” ( Wallace, “The Language of Terrorism,” p. 127).

    Google Scholar 

  42. Wilkins, Terrorism and Collective Responsibility, p. 7. Wilkins admits that he is offering a partial analysis of morally justified terrorism.

    Google Scholar 

  43. “Terrorism is different, both conceptually and morally, from violence employed in self-defense” ( Primoratz, “What is Terrorism?” p. 133).

    Google Scholar 

  44. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), p. 373.

    Google Scholar 

  45. This point is directed at Michael Walzer’s concern that the employment of terrorism is unjustifiable in that it fails to distinguish between combatants and non-combatants [Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars, Third Edition (New York: Basic Books, 2000)].

    Google Scholar 

  46. Although Robert Young’s defense of the use of terrorism is, like mine, based for the most part on the “just war” tradition, our respective accounts differ in significant respects. First, I do not require that terrorism’s moral justification be a tactic of final resort, as Young’s account does. Nor does my view make use of an economic analysis of terrorism as Young’s does. Finally, my analysis of morally justified terrorism is far more dependent on the notion of a terrorist’s not harming innocents than is Young’s [Robert Young, “Revolutionary Terrorism, Crime, and Morality,” Social Theory and Practice, 4 (1977), pp. 287–302].

    Google Scholar 

  47. Hare, “On Terrorism,” p. 249. For a similar view of terrorism, see Paul Wilkinson, Terrorism and the Liberal State, Second Edition (New York: NYU Press, 1986), p. 56, where “terrorism” is defined as “the systematic use of murder and destruction, and the threat of murder and destruction, to terrorise individuals, groups, communities or governments into conceding to the terrorists’ political aims…. terroristic violence is characterized by its indiscriminateness, inhumanity, arbitrariness and barbarity.”

    Google Scholar 

  48. For an alternative account of the rationality of terrorism, see Robert Holmes, “Terrorism and Violence: a Moral Perspective,” in Issues in War and Peace: Philosophical Inquiries, J. C. Kunkel and K. H. Klein, Editors (Wolfeboro: Longwood, 1989), p. 116.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Primoratz, “What is Terrorism?” p. 130. Also see Jenny Teichman, “How to Define Terrorism,” p. 510: “Modern terrorism is not necessarily arbitrary in its choice of victims.” Perhaps the modern terrorist’s (sometimes) choice of specific victims is yet another sign of her sometimes rational behavior.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Wilkins, Terrorism and Collective Responsibility, Chapter 7.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Joel Feinberg, Doing and Deserving (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970), p. 249.

    Google Scholar 

  52. J. Angelo Corlett, “Collective Moral Responsibility,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 32 (2001), pp. 573–84. Also see J. Angelo Corlett, Responsibility and Punishment (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2001), Chapter 7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. The helpful distinction between primary and secondary targets of terrorism is made by Wellman. A primary target of terrorism is the person who is or is perceived to be the main political addressee of the terrorist activity, while a secondary target is a person or thing which is used as a means to address the primary target. See Wellman, “On Terrorism Itself.”

    Google Scholar 

  54. Albert Camus, “The Just Assassins,” in Caligula and Three Other Plays, Translated by Stuart Gilbert (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1958), p. 258. That terrorists can and do discriminate between possible targets is discussed in Che Guevara, Bolivian Diary, translated by Carlos P. Hansen and Andrew Sinclair (London: Jonathan Cape/Lorrimer, 1968); and Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars (London: Allen Lane, 1978), p. 199.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Moral rights are sometimes referred to as “natural” or “human” rights. They are, unlike legal rights, non-conventional in nature. They are grounded in human reason quite independently of conventional norms [See Carl Wellman, A Theory of Rights (Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 1985)].

    Google Scholar 

  56. Joel Feinberg, Social Philosophy (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1970); Rights, Justice, and the Bounds of Liberty (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980); Freedom and Fulfillment: Philosophical Essays (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992).

    Google Scholar 

  57. Wallace, “The Language of Terrorism,” p. 126.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Primoratz, “What is Terrorism?” pp. 129, 135.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Primoratz, “What is Terrorism?” p. 136.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Primoratz, “What is Terrorism?” p. 131.

    Google Scholar 

  61. As noted earlier, Wellman brings this concern to the fore ( Wellman, “On Terrorism Itself,” pp. 156–60).

    Google Scholar 

  62. For an enlightening treatment of this sort of objection, see the critique of the respective consequentialist views of Hare, Kai Nielsen, and Ted Honderich in Wilkins, Terrorism and Collective Responsibility, Chapter 2; Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” p. 70f; and Frey and Morris, “Violence, Terrorism, and Justice.”

    Google Scholar 

  63. Kai Nielsen, “On Terrorism and Political Assassination,” in Joe P. White, Editor, Assent/Dissent (Dubuque: Kendall/Hunt Publishing Company, 1984), p. 312.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Wilkins, Terrorism and Collective Responsibility, p. 48.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” pp. 60–1.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Jan Narveson admits that terrorism need not employ violence, but the threat thereof [See Jan Narveson, “Terrorism and Morality,” in R. G. Frey and Christopher W. Morris, Editors, Violence, Terrorism, and Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 117. In fact, a serious threat of terrorism is sufficient for it on Narveson’s account.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Coady, “The Morality of Terrorism,” p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” p. 64; “Violence, Terrorism, and Moral Inquiry.”

    Google Scholar 

  69. Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” p. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” p. 65.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” p. 69.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” p. 71.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” p. 72.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Wellman, “On Terrorism Itself,” pp. 250–58.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” p. 72.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” p. 73.

    Google Scholar 

  77. See Chapter 3 of this book.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” p. 76.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” p. 80.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” p. 80.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Held, “Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals,” p. 81.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Joel Feinberg, Freedom and Fulfillment (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992), Chapters 8–10.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Narveson, “Terrorism and Morality,” pp. 130–31.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Narveson, “Terrorism and Morality,” p. 138.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Narveson, “Terrorism and Morality,” p. 140.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Narveson, “Terrorism and Morality,” p. 144.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Narveson, “Terrorism and Morality,” p. 147.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Narveson, “Terrorism and Morality,” p. 151.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Narveson, “Terrorism and Morality,” p. 150.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Corlett, J.A. (2003). Can Terrorism Ever Be Morally Justified?. In: Terrorism. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 101. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0039-0_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0039-0_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4020-1695-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-0039-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics