Skip to main content

From Euclid to Descartes: Algebra and its Relation to Geometry

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Mathematics Education Library ((MELI,volume 18))

Abstract

Algebra is not solely the product of the evolution of arithmetic. It owes much to geometry. Some algebraic reasoning is present in Greek geometry. Geometric analysis, as well as the theory of proportions, played an important role in the development of algebra in the Renaissance. Until Viète’s algebraic revolution at the end of the 16th century, geometry was a means to prove algebraic rules, and, likewise, algebra was a means to solve some geometrical problems. In this chapter, I discuss some of the relations which, from Euclid to Descartes, bound algebra to geometry.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   229.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   299.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   299.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Quoted in Unguru (1975, p. 77). Quotation translated from Mahoney (1971, pp. 16–17). See also Mahoney (1972, p. 372) and Mahoney (1980, p. 142).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Descartes (1637/1954, pp. 2, 9).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Euclid (1925/1956, vol. 2, Book III, pp. 71–72).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ptolemy (1984, pp. 48–56).

    Google Scholar 

  5. This has been challenged in Unguru (1975). A strong reaction to this article has been written by van der Waerden (1976).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Euclid (1925/1956, vol. 1, Book II, p. 372).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Euclid (19251956, vol. 1, Book II, p. 382).

    Google Scholar 

  8. van der Waerden (1961).

    Google Scholar 

  9. Euclid (1925/1956, vol. 1, Book II, pp. 402–403, 409–410).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Euclid (1925/1956, vol. 2, Book V, p. 114).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Idem.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Euclid (1925/1956, vol. 1, Book I, p. 155).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Euclid (1925/1956, vol. 2, pp. 112–113).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Boyer (1956, p. 28–29).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Mahoney (1968, p. 322).

    Google Scholar 

  16. It is an example made famous by Hankel at the end of 19th century. It has been reproduced by Heath in his introduction to The Elements, in Euclid (1925/1956, vol. 1, pp. 141–142). Euclid has only figure 4a. Figures 4b and 4c have been added here to facilitate the understanding of the reasoning. Euclid does not specify the name of the point H (Figure 4c).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Cardano (1968, p. 82). The problem has been translated into a modern form by Witmer.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cardano (1968, pp. 96–99). This is in chapter XI.

    Google Scholar 

  19. It would have been very interesting to study Fibonacci. Luis Radford pointed out to me that in the Liber Abbaci (1202), the passage from geometry to algebraic reasoning is not as straightforward as in Chuquet.

    Google Scholar 

  20. The rule of “first terms” refers to rules of manipulation of the first (prime) power of the unknowns. See Chuquet (1880, part III) and Flegg, Hay, & Moss (1985, pp. 144–191). La Géométrie was first published in 1979, with an extensive introduction by Hervé l’Huillier in Chuquet (1979). A partial English translation of the whole Chuquet manuscript has been published by Flegg, Hay, & Moss (1985).

    Google Scholar 

  21. I use the translation by Flegg, Hay, & Moss (1985, p. 266).

    Google Scholar 

  22. Regiomontanus (1533/1967). The 1967 book contains a reproduction of the original publication and an English translation.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid. p. 31.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid p. 31

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid. p. 35.

    Google Scholar 

  26. This filiation has been revitalized by Mahoney (1973, p. 26; 1980, pp. 147–150). See also Van Egmond (1988, pp. 142–3).

    Google Scholar 

  27. On the difficult task of correctly defining the Poristics, see Viète (1983, pp. 12–13, note 6) and Ferrier (1980, pp. 134–158).

    Google Scholar 

  28. Descartes (1637/1954, p 6). This quotation is immediately followed by the second paragraph of the previous quotation from La Géométrie given at the beginning of my chapter.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1996 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Charbonneau, L. (1996). From Euclid to Descartes: Algebra and its Relation to Geometry. In: Bernarz, N., Kieran, C., Lee, L. (eds) Approaches to Algebra. Mathematics Education Library, vol 18. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-1732-3_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-1732-3_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-0-7923-4168-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-1732-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics