Skip to main content

Environment

  • Chapter
Life Science Ethics

Abstract

An introduction to environmental ethics with special attention to issues arising from the practice of agriculture and the argument that nature has intrinsic value.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Some philosophers draw a distinction between intrinsic and inherent values, but that is not necessary in order to understand Marie’s basic point. For the most part, we can treat intrinsic and inherent as having the same meaning.

  2. 2.

    There are strong connections between utilitarianism and instrumental value and between intrinsic value and deontological theories (see Chapter 3), but it would be oversmplistic just to assume that these connections hold.

  3. 3.

    Specific references for selected examples of Callicott’s work, and other authors or schools mentioned in the text, can be found in the references.

  4. 4.

    Apparent exceptions to this are the arguments which claim that intrinsic value has some sort of objectivity that intrumental values lack. This claim is highly controversial; see Cheney (1987) and O’Neill (1992) for further discussion.

  5. 5.

    This does not contradict my earlier claim that any system of values requires some foundation in intrinsic value. There would be nothing valuable on such a world, and indeed the whole talk of ethical theory or moral principles would make no sense.

  6. 6.

    My thanks to James Stephens for this suggestion.

  7. 7.

    This phrasing is a bit convoluted, but necessary for accuracy. The second variation on anthropocentrism, if coupled with moral realism, might agree that something could have intrinsic value even if nobody in fact valued it for its own sake: the valuers might simply be wrong about their moral judgments.

  8. 8.

    Generally anthropocentric views will have more options here: they might, for example, appeal to a moral sense, intuition, or natural emotion. Some of these options may be open to the non-anthropocentric, but they fit less well together.

  9. 9.

    All references in this section will be to Leopold (1966). See bibliography for full citation.

  10. 10.

    However, in other essays, ‘land’ is used as a pejorative term: “There is much confusion between land and country. Land is the place where corn, gullies, and mortgages grow. Country is the ­personality of land, the collective harmony of its soil, life, and weather” (p. 177).

  11. 11.

    Indeed, I have argued that it is often the most important consideration, if understood correctly.

  12. 12.

    See Jamieson (1995) and Russow (1995) for discussions of how the concept of ecosystem health is value-laden, and Norton (1996) and Rapport (1995) for dissenting views.

  13. 13.

    Callicott has taken this even further, pointing out that the land ethic “could fairly be called a case of earth chauvinism” (p. 262) – although he thinks it’s a perfectly justified form of chauvinism.

  14. 14.

    However, Comstock (1996, 2001) has raised serious doubts about the scientific currency of this interpretation of ecology.

  15. 15.

    This is taken from Naess’s “Eight Points,” originally formulated in (1979), but widely reprinted in anthologies, including Armstrong and Bolzer (1993), from which this is taken.

  16. 16.

    It is interesting to note in this regard that the largest designated ‘Wilderness Area’ in the U.S., the Boundary Waters Canoe Area (BWCA) was in fact fairly extensively logged up through the early twentieth century.

  17. 17.

    One response to some of these issues has been a split between deep ecology and “social ­ecology,” the latter most closely associated with Murray Bookchin. See Chase (1987).

  18. 18.

    For a more detailed discussion see the essays by Sessions and Plumwood in Warren (1996).

  19. 19.

    Hence Comstock’s (1996) term for such theories: “extensionist environmental ethics.”

  20. 20.

    For a detailed discussion, and a scathing critique of the latter (see Ferry 1995).

  21. 21.

    The second condition is not quite precise enough: X must somehow contribute to the intrinsic value of Y, such that our effect on X diminishes the value of Y. That is, there must be a direct causal link between what we do to X and Y’s diminution of intrinsic value; it can’t just be a coincidence.

  22. 22.

    Although arguments in favor of conservation tillage often follow similar lines of argument as those adduced against clear-cutting of trees.

References

  • Armstrong, S. J., & Bolzer, R. G. (Eds.). (1993). Envirnmental ethics: Divergence and convergence. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chase, A. (1987). Playing god in yellowstone. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheney, J. (1987). Ecofeminism and deep ecology. Environmental ethics, 9, 115–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Comstock, G. (1996). An extensionist environmental ethic. In N. Cooper & R. C. J. Carling (Eds.), Ecologists and ethical judgments (pp. 43–55). London: Chapman & Hall.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Comstock, G. (2001). Vexing nature? On the ethical case against agricultural biotechnology. Boston, MA: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferry, L. (1995). The new ecological order. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jamieson, D. (1995). Ecosystem health: Some preventative medicine. Environmental Values, 4, 333–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leopold, A. (1966). A Sand County Almanac. New York: Ballantine (originally copyrighted by Oxford University Press in 1949).

    Google Scholar 

  • Naess, A. (1979). Self realization in mixed communities of humans, bears, sheep, and wolves. Inquiry, 22, 231–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, B. (1996). Integration or reduction: Two approaches to environmental values (pp. 105–138). In A. Light & E. Katz (Eds.), Environmental pragmatism. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, J. (1992). The varieties of intrinsic value. The Monist, 75, 119–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rapport, D. (1995). Ecosystem health: Exploring the territory. Ecosystem Health, 1, 5–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russow, L. (1995). An objective evaluation? Environmental Values, 4, 363–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, K. J. (Ed.). (1996). Ecological feminist philosophies. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lilly-Marlene Russow .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Russow, LM. (2010). Environment. In: Comstock, G.L. (eds) Life Science Ethics. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-8792-8_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics