Skip to main content

Questions of Logic: Writing, Dialectics and Musical Strategies

  • Chapter
Mathematics and Music

Abstract

What is logic in music? Is there any practice in music that can be called logic? Is the nature of this possible logic in music musical or mathematical?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. See Löwenheim-Skolem theorem, to be discussed later.

    Google Scholar 

  2. It did not imply that the ear should follow the coherence of the eye, just like there is no semantic transcription of the syntactic model in mathematical logic; the only purpose was to show that the ear can find its own way to follow what has been organised by the eye according to a coherence that remains singular to it.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Cf. L’Être et l’événement (Seuil).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Even if the logic of music is a musical one, musical thought cannot demonstrate, infer or even define it, as we have noticed above. This musical logic is a data with which music makes and creates. It is something like an axiom which musical thought decides, without demonstrating it of course, and then puts to the tests of its consequences. Prom this point of view, musical logic is no more defined than the concept of set or the concept of membership in set theory.

    Google Scholar 

  5. The idea of absolute music (translated by Roger Lustig), Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 1989 (pp. 104–105).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Aristotle asserts it as follows: “The same cannot simultaneously belong and not belong to the same, according to the same” (3, 1005 b 19–20 — translated to French by Barbara Cassin in “La décision du sens. Le livre Gamma de la Métaphysique d’Aristote”, Paris, Vrin, 1989, p. 125).

    Google Scholar 

  7. See my article against Xenakis: Le monde de l’art n’est pas le monde du pardon (Entretemps, n° 5, February 1988): http://www.entretemps.asso.fr/Nicolas/textesNic/Xenakis.html

    Google Scholar 

  8. See my essay in the concept of theme: Cela s’appelle un thème (Cf. Analyse musicale n° 13, October 1988): http://www.entretemps.asso.fr/Nicolas/TextesNic/Theme.html

    Google Scholar 

  9. Relevés d’apprenti, p. 268.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Boulez opposes this treatment to his own, which he describes as follows: “[Complexes] are derived one from the other in a strictly functional way, they obey a logical coherent structure” (Penser la musique aujourd’hui, p. 41).

    Google Scholar 

  11. For a more detailed discussion on this point, see Une écoute à l’œuvre: D’un moment favori dans La chute d’Icare (de Brian Ferneyhough) Compositeurs d’aujourd’hui: Brian Ferneyhough (éd. Ircam-L’Harmattan, 1999).

    Google Scholar 

  12. In an etymological sense: ne-utrum.

    Google Scholar 

  13. One could refer to Claude Imbert’s philosophical works. For example: Pour une histoire de la logique (PUF, 1999).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Unfortunately, I am not aware of any attempts to work the other way round, from music to mathematics. [Note of the translator: an interesting counterexample is given by the problem of construction of musical rhythmic canons, as formalised by the Rumanian mathematician Dan Tudor Vuza. It leads him naturally to non trivial results in the domain of factorisation of cyclic groups. In particular Vuza provides a method of constructing all factorisations of a given cyclic group into non-periodic subsets, by clarifying the properties of the so-called non-Hajós groups. Rhythmic canons associated with such a factorisation have the very fascinating property to “tile” the musical space (that is, no superposition between different voices or holes). Vuza’s algorithme has been recently implemented in OpenMusic by IRCAM’s Equipe des Représentations Musicales (http://www.ircam.fr/equipes/repmus/)].

    Google Scholar 

  15. Cf. Court Traité d’ontologie transitoire (Seuil, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  16. For reasons that I will not develop here, this function can be philosophically named the concept of transcendental, following the very precise meaning that Alain Badiou originally introduced in his philosophical interpretation of mathematical topos theory.

    Google Scholar 

  17. In philosophical terms, the writing measures the there of sonic being-there, the da of the Dasein.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Although one might be tempted to criticise the idea of what is conceived as an adequacy between what is shown [montré] and proved [démontré], in music the category of perception is very close to the philosophical concept of apperception.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Cf. Les moments favoris: une problématique de l’écoute musicale, Cahiers Noria n° 12 (Reims, 1997) : http://www.entretemps.asso.fr/Nicolas/TextesNic/momentsfavoris.html

    Google Scholar 

  20. I will not analyse here the chain of propositions in detail. One may refer to my contribution to the Colloquium Ars Musica (Bruxelles — 2000) : Qu ‘espérer des logiques musicales mises en œuvre au XXe siècle? (forthcoming).

    Google Scholar 

  21. See Gödel’s well known theorem.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See later, Löwenheim-Skolem theorem.

    Google Scholar 

  23. See Henkin’s theorem. This third thesis tends to validate the serial statements that we have mentioned before (as: “perception has to follow the writing”), once one has noticed what follows: if perception has to follow (serialisme), the “real” model does not follow the logical mathematical theories (model theory), for deductions by the latter have no semantic translations in the model; consistency of the model and coherence of the theory are not isomorphic to each other. This means that musical listening does not work by following the writing (listening is not a perception of written structures) but by deploying according to its own rules.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Cf. Charles Rosen’s works, e.g. The Classical Style (The Viking Press, 1971).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Cf. Célestin Deliège’s works, in particular Invention musicale et idéologies (éd. Christian Bourgois).

    Google Scholar 

  26. Of an incognito, in Kierkegaard’s terminology.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Its opposite would be the Hegelian redoublement, when polarisation shows the two divisions of a primary unity (the redoublement concretises the two faces of a same thing).

    Google Scholar 

  28. Cf. La singularité Schoenberg, éditions Ircam-L’Harmattan (Paris, 1997).

    Google Scholar 

  29. Cf. La singularité Schoenberg, op. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  30. More precisely: of the world of music that we are concerned with and which is, as we must keep in mind, just one of the many real or virtual musical worlds (there are such examples as the different worlds of oral music tradition, of popular or of improvised music).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2002 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Nicolas, F. (2002). Questions of Logic: Writing, Dialectics and Musical Strategies. In: Assayag, G., Feichtinger, H.G., Rodrigues, J.F. (eds) Mathematics and Music . Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-04927-3_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-04927-3_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-642-07836-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-662-04927-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics