Skip to main content

Consequentialism and Virtue

  • Living reference work entry
  • First Online:
Handbuch Tugend und Tugendethik

Abstract

We examine the following consequentialist view of virtue: a trait is a virtue if and only if it has good consequences in some relevant way. We highlight some motivations for this basic account, and offer twelve choice points for filling it out. Next, we explicate Julia Driver’s consequentialist view of virtue in reference to these choice points, and we canvass its merits and demerits. Subsequently, we consider three suggestions that aim to increase the plausibility of her position, and critically analyze them. We conclude that one of those proposed revisions would improve her account.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Some consequentialists may opt for eliminativism about virtue. After all, Jeremy Bentham (1843), a prominent consequentialist, eliminates “natural rights” from his broader moral theory calling them “nonsense upon stilts” precisely because his moral theory does not offer a good account of them. Why not think the same about virtue? We thank Folke Tersman for this question. In our view, there is a theoretical cost for consequentialists who eliminate virtue, because they ignore a central part of our moral experience.

  2. 2.

    Philosophers in the consequentialist tradition including Francis Hutcheson, David Hume, Jeremy Bentham, Henry Sidgwick, and G. E. Moore have embraced ideas that resemble the BCV to varying degrees. Those interested in this tradition should see the chapters on Hutcheson, Hume, and Mill in this volume; also see Bradley (2017) for a nice discussion of Moore’s account of virtue.

  3. 3.

    Thomas Hurka’s (2001: 3–4) account of virtue as an intrinsically good attitude toward an intrinsic good is not essentially consequentialist: “It [this account of virtue] can be accommodated within … consequentialism. The account … can be extended in a deontological setting.” Furthermore, Driver’s view is purely consequentialist in a way that others are not. For example, Rosalind Hursthouse (1999) and Linda Zagzebski (1996) offer views of virtue that have a consequentialist necessary condition alongside at least one non-consequentialist necessary condition.

  4. 4.

    See Halbig’s contribution in this volume.

  5. 5.

    If the claims made by some social psychologists and philosophers that character traits do not exist (“We need to abandon all talk of virtue and character, not find a way to save it by reinterpreting it” (Harman 2000: 224)) or that external circumstances wholly swallow the influence of character traits are true claims, then there would be no virtues or vices on Driver’s view. We, however, are skeptical about the truth of those claims; and most social psychologists and philosophers are skeptical about them too (see Miller 2014: 199–200). In fact, most acknowledge that we at least have local character traits that make a difference to behavior (Doris 2002: 64); more recently, Gilbert Harman (2003: 92) has agreed: “people may differ in certain relatively narrow traits”.

  6. 6.

    Driver (2012) does not think that luck can affect every aspect of the moral life; for example, she argues that even the consequentialist can consistently hold the view that two identical reckless drivers are equally blameworthy even though one of them kills a pedestrian. The idea is that the killer driver’s wrongdoing is more serious than the merely reckless driver’s wrongdoing, but they deserve the same degree of blame. For an introduction to the problem of moral luck and various attempts to solve it, see Hartman (2017: ch 1).

  7. 7.

    For an argument that counterfactual consequences are practically significant, see Hartman (2015: 89–92).

  8. 8.

    We thank Erik Carlson for pressing this point.

  9. 9.

    At one point, Driver (2001: 95) equates “systematically” with “overall,” which we do not think is representative of her position on this issue.

  10. 10.

    Hurka’s (2001) theory of virtue and vice is compatible with act consequentialism, and it makes virtue and vice intrinsically good and bad in ways that avoid the two counterintuitive implications and this theoretical objection.

  11. 11.

    There is an analogous objection in the moral responsibility literature to views that collapse the intuitive distinction between being bad and being blameworthy (see Hartman 2020: 109).

  12. 12.

    Driver’s view functionally collapses into the view that only the consequences produced by a particular trait count toward its virtue status if there is only one instance of each type of trait instantiated in an actual context. This collapse may be the case given the complex nature of our character traits if traits are individuated in very fine-grained ways (see Miller 2014).

  13. 13.

    This move is not available to consequentialists who specify the good in a way that precludes the prevention of suffering from being good. We thank Vuko Andrić for this point.

  14. 14.

    We can, however, see other motivations for contrastivism. For example, one might adopt it to circumvent our objection that Driver’s account cannot make the intuitive distinction between a meager good producing trait and a virtue. One might also adopt it to circumvent an objection raised in conversation by Krister Bykvist: if someone’s being a good or bad person is determined by their virtues and vices, then everyone in Horribleland is a bad person, which is a counterintuitive result.

  15. 15.

    For explication of various conceptions of luck, see Church and Hartman (2019).

  16. 16.

    We thank the participants of higher seminars at the University of Gothenburg, Stockholm University, and Uppsala University for questions and comments, and we especially thank Felix Timmermann, Vuko Andrić, and Krister Bykvist for extensive comments.

References

  • Adams, Robert Merrihew. 1976. Motive utilitarianism. The Journal of Philosophy 73: 461–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, Robert Merrihew. 2006. A theory of virtue: Excellence in being for the good. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 2002. Nicomachean ethics. Trans. Christopher Rowe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, Jeremy. 1843. Anarchical fallacies. In The works of Jeremy Benthem, vol. 2, ed. John Bowring. Edinburgh: Simpkin, Marshall, & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, Ben. 2005. Virtue consequentialism. Utilitas 17: 282–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, Ben. 2017. Character and consequences. In Questions of character, ed. Iskra Fileva, 78–88. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, Ben. 2018. Contemporary consequentialism theories of virtue. In The Oxford handbook of virtue, ed. Nancy Snow, 398–413. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calder, Todd. 2007. Against consequentialist theories of virtue and vice. Utilitas 19: 201–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Church, Ian M., and Robert J. Hartman, eds. 2019. The Routledge handbook of the philosophy and psychology of luck. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doris, John. 2002. Lack of character: Personality and moral behavior. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Driver, Julia. 2001. Uneasy virtue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Driver, Julia. 2004. Response to my critics. Utilitas 16: 33–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Driver, Julia. 2006. Virtue theory. In Contemporary debate in moral theory, ed. James Dreier, 113–123. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Driver, Julia. 2012. Luck and fortune in moral evaluation. In Contrastivism in philosophy: New perspectives, ed. Martijn Blaauw, 154–172. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Driver, Julia. 2016. Minimal virtue. The Monist 99: 97–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, Adam, and Edward T. Cokely. 2012. The virtues of ignorance. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 3: 335–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, Adam, and Edward T. Cokely. 2013. Virtue or consequences: The folk against pure evaluational internalism. Philosophical Psychology 26: 702–717.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, Owen. 1990. Virtues and ignorance. The Journal of Philosophy 87: 420–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foot, Philippa. 1978. Virtues and vices. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, Gilbert. 2000. The nonexistence of character traits. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100: 223–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, Gilbert. 2003. No character or personality. Business Quarterly Ethics 13: 87–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, Robert J. 2015. Utilitarian moral virtue, admiration, and luck. Philosophia 43: 77–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, Robert J. 2017. In defense of moral luck: Why luck often affects priaseworthiness and blameworthiness. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, Robert J. 2020. Against the character solution to the problem of moral luck. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 98(1): 105–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, Thomas. 2001. Virtue, vice, and value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, Rosalind. 1999. On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1996. The metaphysics of morals. In Practical philosophy, ed. and trans. Mary J. Gregor, 35–604. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, Neil. 2011. Hard luck: How luck undermines free will and moral responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John. 1979. Virtue and reason. The Monist 62: 331–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Chrisitan B. 2014. Character and moral psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha C. 2001. The fragility of goodness: Luck and ethics in Greek tragedy and philosophy. Updated edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, Onora. 2004. Consequences for non-consequentialists. Utilitas 16: 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peels, Rik. 2019. The mixed account of luck. In The Routledge handbook of the philosophy and psychology of luck, ed. Ian M. Church and Robert J. Hartman, 148–159. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, Duncan. 2019. Modal accounts of luck. In The Routledge handbook of the philosophy and psychology of luck, ed. Ian M. Church and Robert J. Hartman, 115–124. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Luke. 2007. What even consequentialists should say about the virtues. Utilitas 19: 466–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandler, Ronald. 2005. Ignorance and virtue. Philosophical Papers 34: 261–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter. 2015. Consequentialism. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta. URL https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consequentialism/

  • Slote, Michael. 2004. Driver’s virtues. Utilitas 16: 22–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winter, Michael Jeffrey. 2012. Does virtue require knowledge? A response to Julia Driver. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15: 533–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, Linda Trinkaus. 1996. Virtues of the mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert J. Hartman .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Fachmedien Wiesbaden GmbH, ein Teil von Springer Nature

About this entry

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this entry

Hartman, R.J., Bronson, J.W. (2021). Consequentialism and Virtue. In: Halbig, C., Timmermann, F.U. (eds) Handbuch Tugend und Tugendethik. Springer VS, Wiesbaden. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-658-24467-5_20-1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-658-24467-5_20-1

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer VS, Wiesbaden

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-658-24467-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-658-24467-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Referenz Sozialwissenschaften und Recht

Publish with us

Policies and ethics