Skip to main content

Ideo- and Auto-reflexive Quotation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Semantics and Pragmatics of Quotation

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 15))

Abstract

I focus on the two uses of quotation marks illustrated by The word ‘car’ expresses the idea “automobile,” in which the single quotation marks are used “auto-reflexively” to mark reference to the word quoted and the double quotation marks are used “ideo-reflexively” to mark reference to the idea expressed by the word quoted. I account for the difference between auto- and ideo-reflexive reference within my theory of meaning and indexical reference. Meaning consists in the expression of mental states, principally thoughts and their parts. Indexicals express a type of thought part that links to another mental state that determines its referent. Determinants can be other concepts (as in the anaphoric use of indexicals) or presentations (as in their deictic use). On my account, the idea “automobile” expresses the indexical concept expressed by the idea (a definite noun phrase used restrictively) linked to an introspective presentation of the idea expressed by the word in quotes. The word ‘car’ expresses the indexical concept expressed by the word linked to a perceptual presentation of the word in quotes. The quotation marks are optional punctuation marks, with no referents of their own. I observe that a word ‘w’ can also be used elliptically to mean “the word ‘w.’” I show that my deictic indexical theory avoids the defects of other accounts, including the demonstrative theory and Davidson’s theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    So in the act sense, thoughts and beliefs are different. But in the object sense, beliefs are thoughts (though not all thoughts are beliefs).

  2. 2.

    For more on conventions in this sense, see Davis (2003: chapter 9).

  3. 3.

    The terms ‘anaphoric,’ ‘demonstrative,’ and ‘deictic’ are common in linguistics, but there is little consensus on their usage.

  4. 4.

    I focus on ‘I’ elsewhere (2013, 2017a, b).

  5. 5.

    Since seeing-that entails knowing-that, Dretske (1969) called it “epistemic” perception. Seeing a lemur is “non-epistemic” perception.

  6. 6.

    See Davis (2017b) for more on sortal components.

  7. 7.

    I discuss these well-known Binding Rules (Chomsky 1995: section 1.4.2) in Davis (2017b).

  8. 8.

    Cf. Strawson (1950: 14–5), Donnellan (1968, 1977), Evans (1977, 1980), Wettstein (1981), Salmon (1982), Soames (1986), Bach (1987: Sect. 6.4), Recanati (1989a: 232–3, b: 314), Neale (1990: Sect. 3.7), Bezuidenhout (1997a, b), Reimer (1998a, b), and Powell (2001: 80ff).

  9. 9.

    Background facts: Washington and Jefferson were both Virginians; Adams was from Massachusetts.

  10. 10.

    Note that thought is not the same as inner speech. Tom said to himself “All cars is vehicles” is grammatical and may be true.

  11. 11.

    ‘Say’ differs markedly from ‘utter’ in having an illocutionary as well as locutionary sense. In the former, Sue said “A car is a vehicle” is equivalent to Sue said that a car is a vehicle, and does not entail that Sue uttered an English sentence. If my grasp of French is correct, ‘prononcé’ corresponds to ‘uttered,’ ‘dit’ and ‘declaré’ to ‘said.’

  12. 12.

    As noted in Sect. 3, the idea “φ” and the idea of φ may not be synonymous when ‘φ’ is an indexical like him. Note too that (b) can be used transparently, as in The idea of a sedan is the idea of an automobile. When it is transparent, it is not synonymous with (a), which has no transparent interpretation. For further complexities, see Davis (2003: section 7.6).

  13. 13.

    ‘Automobile’ means “of or pertaining to cars” (as an adjective) as well as “car” (as a noun).

  14. 14.

    I develop a theory of saying reports based on my account of auto- and ideo-reflexive designators in Davis (2016a).

  15. 15.

    ‘Idea of a car’ is a general term, however, when ‘idea’ means “conception” rather than “thought part.” There are many conceptions of a car.

  16. 16.

    Cf. Clark and Gerrig (1990), Wertheimer (1999: 515), Recanati (2001: 639), and Green (2007).

  17. 17.

    The parallel for ‘expression’ implies that the expression ‘car’ is ambiguous in English, most commonly referring to the word for automobiles, but also possibly referring to the expression consisting of that word surrounded by single quotation marks. Whereas ‘car’ (a word in quotation marks) is not a word, it is an expression.

  18. 18.

    Each token of the sentence type contains eight word tokens but no word types. The sentence type contains eight occurrences of word types, but no word tokens. Occurrences are subtypes, not tokens. Occurrences of types in types are often mistaken for tokens. See Wetzel (2009: chapter 7) and Davis (2014).

  19. 19.

    Cf. Cappelen and Lepore (2012: 7, 29). See also Washington (1992: 592–4).

  20. 20.

    Cf. Christensen (1967: 362), Wertheimer (1999: 515–6, 518), Saka (2011: 312, 314), and Cappelen and Lepore (2012: 7). Contrast Saka (2011: 309).

  21. 21.

    Wertheimer (1999: 518–9) observes the appositive interpretation of (47), but erroneously thinks that it is the only interpretation.

  22. 22.

    Cf. Wertheimer (1999: 515).

  23. 23.

    See also Prior (1971: 60ff), Partee (1973), Davidson (1979: 90), Goldstein (1984: 4), Garcia-Carpintero (1994, 2017), Reimer (1996: 135), and Cappelen and Lepore (1997, 1999, 2012).

  24. 24.

    See Clark and Gerrig (1990: 765, 801), Washington (1992: 588), Reimer (1996: 133–5), Saka (1998: 118–19, 2006: 463–67), and Recanati (2001: 653–6).

  25. 25.

    See also Washington (1992: 605), whose assumption that “naming, describing, and demonstrating . . . exhaust the standard ways of mentioning non-linguistic objects” (1992: 582) is true only if ‘demonstrating’ covers all forms of indexical reference.

  26. 26.

    Christensen (1967: 363–4), Goldstein (1984: 4), Bennett (1988: 403), Washington (1992: 595–7, 599–601), Garcia-Carpintero (1994), Cappelen and Lepore (1997: 441, 1999, 2012: 22–3), Saka (1998: 124ff, 2011: 315), and Wertheimer (1999: 519).

  27. 27.

    Wertheimer (1999: 516), Saka (2006: 459–63), and Cappelen and Lepore (2012: 22).

  28. 28.

    Compare Burge (1986), Stainton (1999), and Cappelen and Lepore (1999, 2012: 14).

  29. 29.

    Contrast Goldstein (1984: 4) and Saka (1998: 123ff). What sentence type [A] contains is an occurrence of the sentence ‘Alice swooned.’ Recall fn. 14.

References

  • Bach, K. (1987). Thought and reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. (1988). Quotation. Noûs, 22, 399–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bezuidenhout, A. (1997a). The communication of de re thoughts. Noûs, 31, 197–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bezuidenhout, A. (1997b). Pragmatics, semantic underdetermination and the referential/attributive distinction. Mind, 106, 375–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1986). On Davidson’s ‘Saying that’. In E. Lepore (Ed.), Truth and interpretation (pp. 190–208). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H., & Lepore, E. (1997). Varieties of quotation. Mind, 106, 429–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H., & Lepore, E. (1999). Reply to Saka. Mind, 108, 741–750.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H., & Lepore, E.. (2012). Quotation. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (pp. 1–56). Stanford. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2012/entries/quotation/

  • Chomsky, N. (1995). The minimalist program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, N. (1967). The alleged distinction between use and mention. Philosophical Review, 76, 358–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, H. H., & Gerrig, R. J. (1990). Quotations as demonstrations. Language, 66, 764–805.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1979). Quotation. Theory and Decision, 11, 27–40. Reprinted in Inquiries into Truth & Interpretation (pp. 79–92). Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2003). Meaning, expression, and thought. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2005). Nondescriptive meaning and reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2013). Indexicals and de se attitudes. In N. Feit & A. Capone (Eds.), Attitudes ‘De Se’: Linguistics, epistemology, metaphysics (pp. 29–58). Palo Alto: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2014). On occurrences of types in types. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 92, 349–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2016a). A theory of saying reports. In A. Capone, F. Kiefer, & F. Lo Piparo (Eds.), Indirect reports and pragmatics: Interdisciplinary studies (pp. 291–332). Cham: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2016b). Irregular negatives, implicatures, and idioms. Cham: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2017a). The property theory and de se attitudes. In K. Korta, & M. de Ponte (Eds.), Reference and representation in thought and language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2017b). Pronouns and implicature. In P. Cap, & M. Dynel (Eds.), Implicitness: From lexis to discourse. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. (1968). Putting humpty dumpty together again. Philosophical Review, 77, 203–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. (1977). The contingent a priori and rigid designators. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 2, 6–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1969). Seeing and knowing. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1977). Pronouns, quantifiers, and relative clauses (I). Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 7, 467–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1980). Pronouns. Linguistic Inquiry, 11, 337–362.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1998). Concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1892). On sense and reference. Zeitschrift fur Philosophie und Philosophische Kritik, 100, 25–50. In P. Geach and M. Black (Eds.), Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege (pp. 56–78). Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garcia-Carpintero, M. (1994). Ostensive signs: Against the identity theory of quotation. Journal of Philosophy, 91, 253–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garcia-Carpintero, M. (2017). Reference and reference-fixing in pure quotation. In P. Saka & M. Johnson (Eds.), The semantics and pragmatics of quotation. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, L. (1984). Quotation of types and other types of quotation. Analysis, 44, 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, M. S. (2007). Self-expression. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1957). Meaning. Philosophical Review, 66, 377–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1977). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1978). Dthat. In P. Cole (Ed.), Syntax and semantics, 9, pragmatics (pp. 221–253). New York: Academic. In P. Yourgrau (Ed.), Demonstratives. (pp. 11–49). Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1972). Naming and necessity. In D. Davidson & G. Harman (Eds.), Semantics of natural language (pp. 253–355., 763–69). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Neale, S. (1990). Descriptions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. (1973). Some structural analogies between tenses and pronouns in English. Journal of Philosophy, 70, 601–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (1979). The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs, 13, 3–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Powell, G. (2001). The referential-attributive distinction – a cognitive account. Pragmatics and Cognition, 9, 69–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. N. (1971). Objects of thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1940). Mathematical logic. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (1989a). Referential/attributive: A contextualist proposal. Philosophical Studies, 56, 217–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (1989b). The pragmatics of what is said. Mind & Language, 4, 293–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2001). Open quotation. Mind, 110, 637–687.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1947). Elements of symbolic logic. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reimer, M. (1996). Quotation marks: Demonstratives or demonstrations? Analysis, 56, 131–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reimer, M. (1998a). The Wettstein/Salmon debate: Critique and resolution. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 79, 130–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reimer, M. (1998b). Donnellan’s distinction/Kripke’s test. Analysis, 58, 89–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saka, P. (1998). Quotation and the use-mention distinction. Mind, 107, 113–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saka, P. (2006). The demonstrative and identity theories of quotation. Journal of Philosophy, 103, 452–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saka, P. (2011). The act of quotation. In E. Brendel (Ed.), Understanding quotation (pp. 303–322). Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, N. (1982). Assertion and incomplete definite descriptions. Philosophical Studies, 42, 37–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (1986). Incomplete definite descriptions. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 27, 349–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stainton, R. J. (1999). Remarks on the syntax and semantics of mixed quotation. In K. Murasugi & R. Stainton (Eds.), Philosophy and linguistics (pp. 259–278). Boulder: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1950). On referring. Mind, 59, 320–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Washington, C. (1992). The identity theory of quotation. Journal of Philosophy, 89, 582–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, R. (1999). Quotation apposition. The Philosophical Quarterly, 49, 514–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wettstein, H. K. (1981). Demonstrative reference and definite descriptions. Philosophical Studies, 40, 241–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wetzel, L. (2009). Types and tokens: On abstract objects. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wayne A. Davis .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Davis, W.A. (2017). Ideo- and Auto-reflexive Quotation. In: Saka, P., Johnson, M. (eds) The Semantics and Pragmatics of Quotation. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 15. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-68747-6_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics