Skip to main content

The Second Mystery: Nonlocality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Quantum Sense and Nonsense
  • 1118 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, we shall discuss the second “impossible thing” to believe before or after breakfast or the second quantum mystery: the existence of instantaneous actions at a distance in Nature. But what does “action” mean here? If there are such actions, do they allow an instantaneous transfer of matter? An instantaneous transfer of energy? An instantaneous transfer of messages? An instantaneous transfer of information? Does their existence contradict the idea that “nothing goes faster than light” (which is supposed to be a consequence of the theory of relativity)? Besides, if quantum mechanics shows that the mind acts directly on matter, do such actions at a distance justify telepathy? We have to discuss each of these points carefully and slowly.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    We base ourselves in this section on [134]; See that article or [98] for more details. We emphasize that this, like all “experiments” in this book, is a “thought experiment”, meaning an experiment illustrating the theory, but not necessarily realized in practice. Some experiments described here are realized in laboratories, but when we will speak below of large distances between some subsystems, one should remember that we always assume implicitly that the subsystems under consideration are isolated from outside influences, a condition which is difficult to satisfy in practice if the separation between them is very large.

  2. 2.

    The Morse code is a sequence of short and long signals that allows to code any letter or punctuation mark into a sequence of such signals. One can then also code any sentence into such a sequence. If one associates, say 0 to “short” and 1 to “long”, one then converts any English sentence into a sequence of 0’s and 1’s.

  3. 3.

    If the questions are asked randomly, since there are nine possible pairs of questions, three of which are the same on both side, one expects the same questions to be asked about one third of the time.

  4. 4.

    However, experiments done in 2017 by Chinese scientists show that those correlations can be maintained over more than 1,000 km [5].

  5. 5.

    The actual experiments are made with photons instead electrons, with the polarization of photons replacing the spin of the electrons. It will be easier for us to discuss everything in terms of electrons and spin. Moreover, the original EPR argument (see Sect. 10.1.2) did not use spin variables. This version of the argument is due to David Bohm [23].

  6. 6.

    It is actually easy to realize the “experiment” described in Sect. 7.4.1, with Alice, Bob, and the three questions: send Alice and Bob towards X and Y and let them orient their respective magnetic field in a direction corresponding to the question that they are being asked and send towards both of them a pair of correlated particles with the quantum state described in this section. Alice and Bob can simply give an answer Yes or No depending on the result that they obtain (with our conventions), and they will then reproduce the statistics that are shown by Bell to be impossible without some form of action at a distance.

  7. 7.

    See Aspect’s introduction to the 2004 edition of [14].

  8. 8.

    As we explained in Sect. 7.4.2, because of the (anti)-correlations, one makes the answer “Yes” correspond to the spin being along the direction of the field on one side and in the direction opposite to the field on the other side, and vice-versa for the answer “No”.

  9. 9.

    That is because Alice and Bob have each three possible choices of directions, so there are \(3.3=9\) choices of pairs of directions. Three of these choices will have the same direction for both Alice and Bob and \(\frac{3}{9}= \frac{1}{3}\).

  10. 10.

    The statements in the last two paragraphs are based on standard quantum mechanical calculations, but justifying them would go beyond the scope of this book.

  11. 11.

    For a general N, the number of lists of cities is \(N!= N\times N-1 \times N-2 \dots 3 \times 2 \times 1\).

  12. 12.

    Solving this problem has applications in classical (i.e., non quantum) cryptography, but it would go beyond the scope of this book to explain that in detail.

  13. 13.

    Obviously, if \(N=p\times q\), either p or q must be less than or equal to \(\sqrt{N}\).

  14. 14.

    See Taylor and Wheeler [186] for a rather elementary introduction to that theory and Maudlin [122] for a careful conceptual discussion.

  15. 15.

    See Maudlin [122] for an elaboration of this idea.

  16. 16.

    As we explained in Sect. 7.3 the impossibility of sending a message instantaneously implies the impossibility of sending instantaneously either matter or energy.

  17. 17.

    In formulas, the first law stated here says that

    $$\begin{aligned} F= \frac{GM_1 M_2}{d^2} \end{aligned}$$
    (7.1)

    where F is the force exerted by one body on the other, G is a constant (called Newton’s constant), which will not concern us here, and d is the distance between the two bodies. In reality, the force is a vector and we are indicating here only its length. The same is true for the acceleration below. This law is often called the “inverse square law”, because of the factor \(d^2\) in the denominator of the right hand side of (7.1).

    The second law is:

    $$\begin{aligned} F= M a, \end{aligned}$$
    (7.2)

    where F is the force exerted on the body of mass M, and a is the acceleration of that body.

    Now, let us see what this implies for the acceleration of the body 1. We need to put an index 1 in (7.1) and in (7.2): \(F_1= \frac{GM_1 M_2}{d^2}\) and \(F_1= M_1 a_1\), where \(F_1\) is the force exerted on body 1, of mass \(M_1\), and \(a_1\) is its acceleration. Inserting the first of these formulas into the second one, and dividing both sides by \(M_1\), we get:

    $$\begin{aligned} a_1= \frac{G M_2}{d^2}, \end{aligned}$$
    (7.3)

    namely the acceleration of body 1 depends instantaneously on its distance with respect to body 2.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jean Bricmont .

Appendices

Appendices

7.A Nonlocality in Newton’s Theory

Newton’s theory of gravitation has also a nonlocal aspect, but which is different from the one discussed in Sect. 7.3.

Two of the most famous laws of classical physics are due to Newton. Suppose we have two bodies, labelled 1 and 2 whose masses are denoted \(M_1\) and \(M_2\). Then, they attract each other through a gravitational force proportional to the product \(M_1\times M_2\) of their masses and proportional to the inverse of the square of their distance d. The second law is that “the force is equal to the mass times the acceleration”, the acceleration being the rate at which the velocity changes. So, if we change the position of body 2, we change the value of the distance d between the two bodies in that equation, and therefore the value of the acceleration of body 1. If the acceleration changes, this changes the velocity of that body, and if one changes its velocity, one changes the position of the body.Footnote 17

This makes actions at a distance possible: since the gravitational force depends on the distribution of matter in the Universe, changing that distribution, say by waving my arm, instantaneously affects the motion of all other bodies in the Universe (of course, the effect is minuscule, but we give this simple example to illustrate the principle). That action at a distance has properties 1 and 2 of Sect. 7.3, since it is instantaneous and acts arbitrarily far.

But it does not have the other properties, 3, 4 and 5 of Sect. 7.3: it does not have property 3 because its effect decreases with the distance, since the effect is proportional to the inverse of the square of the distance d. Besides, it affects all bodies at a given distance equally: there is nothing special in body 2 except its distance with respect to body 1. In other words, unlike what happens with the boxes, it is not individuated, so it does not have property 4.

On the other hand, it can in principle be used to transmit messages (so it does not have property 5 of Sect. 7.3): if I decide to choose, at every minute, to wave my arm or not to wave it, one can use that choice of movements to encode a sequence of zeros and ones and, assuming that the gravitational effect due to that movement can be detected, one can transmit a message instantaneously and arbitrarily far (of course, the further away one tries to transmit it, the harder the detection).

Note that all this refers to Newton’s theory. There have been no experiments performed in this framework that could prove that gravitational forces really act instantaneously or at least at speeds faster than the speed of light, and this is a major difference with respect to the situation in quantum mechanics.

7.B Proof of Bell’s Theorem in Sect. 7.4

As we said in Sect. 7.4.1, there are three questions numbered 1, 2, and 3, and two answers Yes and No. If the answers are given in advance, there are \(2^3=8\) possibilities:

$$ \begin{array}{ccc} 1 &{} \qquad 2 &{} \qquad 3 \\ { Yes} &{} \qquad { Yes} &{} \qquad { Yes} \\ { Yes} &{} \qquad { Yes} &{} \qquad { No} \\ { Yes} &{} \qquad { No} &{} \qquad { Yes} \\ { Yes} &{} \qquad { No} &{} \qquad { No} \\ { No} &{} \qquad { Yes} &{} \qquad { Yes} \\ { No} &{} \qquad { Yes} &{} \qquad { No} \\ { No} &{} \qquad { No} &{} \qquad { Yes} \\ { No} &{} \qquad { No} &{} \qquad { No} \end{array}$$

So Alice and Bob could agree, for example to always answer “Yes” to the first question, “No” to the second one and also “No” to the third (let’s call that the YNN strategy). Or they could follow each of the strategies YYN, NYN, and NNN one third of the time. Or they could choose their answers at random among the eight possibilities.

In any case, in each situation there are at least two questions with the same answer. Therefore,

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{l} \text{ Frequency } \text{(answer } \text{ to } \text{1 }\ = \text {answer to 2)}\\ +\ \text{ Frequency } \text{(answer } \text{ to } \text{2 }\ = \text {answer to 3)}\\ +\ \text{ Frequency } \text{(answer } \text{ to } \text{3 }\ = \text {answer to 1)}\ \ge 1\;, \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
(7.4)

since at least one of the identities: answer to 1 \(=\) answer to 2, answer to 2 \(=\) answer to 3, answer to 3 \(=\) answer to 1, holds in every run of the experiment.

But if

$$ \begin{array}{l} \text{ Frequency } \text{(answer } \text{ to } \text{1 } = \text {answer to 2)}\\ =\ \text{ Frequency } \text{(answer } \text{ to } \text{2 } = \text {answer to 3)}\\ =\ \text{ Frequency } \text{(answer } \text{ to } \text{3 } = \text {answer to 1)} = 1/4\;, \end{array} $$

we get \(\frac{3}{4} \ge 1\), which is a contradiction.\(\blacksquare \)

The inequality like (7.4), saying that a sum of frequencies are greater than or equal to 1, is an example of a Bell inequality , i.e., an inequality which is a logical consequence of the assumption of pre-existing values, but which is violated by quantum predictions.

7.C How to Encode Secret Messages?

Suppose that Alice and Bob possess a common key k, namely a random sequence of 0’s and 1’s, and that they want to use that sequence in order to encode a message m which is also a sequence of 0’s and 1’s, but a non random one (messages that have a meaning for us are not random) in such a way that the result looks random.

They can do that by adding “in binary addition” the message to be sent m and the sequence k; binary addition means that one adds each of the corresponding symbols in the two sequences according to the following rules:

  • \(0+0=0\),

  • \(0+1=1\),

  • \(1+0=1\),

  • \(1+1=0\).

It looks like those rules are the ordinary ones except for the last one where we seemingly made a mistake: \(1+1=2\)! But these are just rules that we define to be the valid ones if we deal with only two numbers, 0 and 1. There is no symbol 2 here, by definition.

For example, if the message to be sent is \(m=01101010\) and the common sequence or key is \(k=11011001\), we have \(m+k=10110010\) and that is the sequence which is sent by Alice to Bob through an open channel (and can in principle be obtained by the spy).

Since Bob also has the sequence k, it is very easy for him to obtain the original message m. Indeed, with our binary rules, we have \(0+0=0\) and \(1+1=0\). So, adding twice the same message amounts to adding 0 everywhere, which means that one does not change anything. So, one has \(m+k+k=m\). Just to check, add \(k=11011001\) to \(m+k=10110010\), with the binary rules, and you will obtain back \(m=01101010\).

Now, if the sequence k is sufficiently long and sufficiently random one can use it to encode any given message (we just gave one with eight symbols to illustrate the method) and the regularities in the message m will disappear because of the randomness in k.

To check that the sequence \(m+k\) will be as random as k, no matter what m is, just consider the least random m one can imagine: \(m= 111111111\dots \) that is every symbol of m is 1. Then, with the rules of binary addition, in the sequence \(m+k\) one will simply have each symbol 0 in k replaced by 1 and each symbol 1 in k replaced by 0. But if the sequence k is random, the new sequence \(m+k\) will also be random.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Bricmont, J. (2017). The Second Mystery: Nonlocality. In: Quantum Sense and Nonsense. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-65271-9_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics