Skip to main content

Extending the Boundaries of Economics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Uncertainty in Economics

Part of the book series: Contributions to Economics ((CE))

Abstract

The latest financial and economic crises have undermined the confidence in the economic science and its methods, fundamentally. Now, the discipline of economics is looking for a new methodological guiding principle. Neuroeconomics, or Imperfect Knowledge Economics, emerged from this search for a New Economic Paradigm. Both schools of economic thought are highly methodology driven and limited in scope. Therefore, they cannot be used as a blueprint for a new philosophy of economics, which is able to replace the Positivist Research Paradigm. Even worse, the analysis of this thesis and the economic turbulences of the last decade, have shown that pure positive economics is impossible. This, however, does not also imply that only normative economics is possible. Nor does it imply that economics is not a science. Rather it is the case that the methodology and particularly the aims and the expectations concerning the generality of economic conclusions have to be revised.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    E.g.: Soros (2013: 317): “In natural sciences, the outside observer, is engaged only in the cognitive function, and the facts provide a reliable criterion by which the truth of the observers’ theories can be judged. So the outside observer can obtain knowledge about the natural phenomena she is observing. Based on that knowledge, nature can be successfully manipulated. That manipulation can change the state of the physical world, but it does not change the laws that govern that world.”

  2. 2.

    Economic reality is thought of as a reflexive system that consists of natural unchangeable parts and human changeable parts.

  3. 3.

    George Soros (2013) had argued that reflexivity is one of the major sources of uncertainty in economics that causes the unpredictability of economic outcomes. Elena Esposito (2011, 2013), sharing the view that reflexivity is an important force driving economic progress, however, argues that reflexivity can be used to better understand economic phenomena or even exploit reflexivity in order to foresee fundamental changes.

  4. 4.

    The label ‘objective reality’ is from my point of view misleading, as it suggests that there is some real and true objective reality. I fear this is not the case. There is something like a purely observer-independent and therefore objective natural reality. This natural reality is unattainable for us human beings, as we always perceive it with some subjective colour. Consequently, objectivity is always out of reach. Nevertheless, we can agree on facts and knowledge about this reality, which are in some way objective, and yet not universal. In the course of time our agreement about the facts and knowledge may change, due to new observations, interpretations or changed subjective realities. Thus, Soros’ objective reality, should not be confused with nature and furthermore, it is constantly changing and highly dependent on our subjective realities.

  5. 5.

    By strategically I mean that humans are able to act against their natural instincts and decide consciously which action to take. Nevertheless, human actions are also driven by natural instincts and emotions. Yet, humans have an opportunity to turn against these instincts and emotions.

  6. 6.

    Rosenberg (2013: 439) critically reflects Soros human uncertainty principle in the following way: “In the biological domain, uncertainty and reflexivity are held in check by environments that change with geological slowness. This produces long-lived local equilibrium outcomes. In the human domain, the environment is cultural. It is composed of nested sets of strategies that are all affected by both reflexivity and uncertainty. The result of their operation is at most short-lived local equilibria, broken up by radical environmental change. The source of this radical environmental change in human cultural processes is obvious. It is the iterated, unsynchronised combinations of reflexivity and uncertainty in strategy variation. As the rate of change in the cultural environment increases, the lifetimes of local equilibria shorten, until in many cases they disappear altogether. Human affairs appear chaotic because many of them are far from equilibrium, even if there are any equilibria to which they may temporarily be heading.”

  7. 7.

    This conclusion is not new. However, during the last decade’s economists pushed this insight aside. E.g.: Box and Draper (1987: 424): “Essentially, all models are wrong, but some are useful.”

  8. 8.

    Cf. Beinhocker (2013: 338): “I should also briefly note that while complex reflexive systems present a challenge due to their Knightian uncertainty, there is also an upside-their inherent indeterminacy creates space for novelty and creativity. In a perfectly deterministic system, there is no room for novelty to emerge. In a perfectly random system, there is insufficient coherence for novelty to matter. Complex reflexive systems are somewhere in between—they are hard to forecast and fallibility is inevitable, but there is nonetheless pattern and structure. This creates a space for novelty, experimentation, and in human systems creativity. One may even argue that there is a link between reflexivity and free will—reflexivity makes free will both possible and necessary.”

  9. 9.

    Friedman (1953: 5–6) defines: “A theory is “simpler” the less the initial knowledge needed to make a prediction within a given field of phenomena; it is more “fruitful” the more precise the resulting prediction, the wider the area within which the theory yields predictions, and the more additional lines for further research it suggests. Logical completeness and consistency are relevant but play a subsidiary role; their function is to assure that the hypothesis says what it is intended to say and does so alike for all users—they play the same role here as checks for arithmetical accuracy do in statistical computations.”

References

  • Arrow KJ (1978) The future and the present in economic life. Econ Inq 16:157–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ (2013) Knowledge, belief and the economic. WIFO Monatsberichte 12:943–951

    Google Scholar 

  • Beckert J (2008) Fictional expectations in the economy. Working Papers, pp 1–32

    Google Scholar 

  • Beckert J (2011) Imagined futures fictionality in economic action. Max-Planck-Institut für Gesellschaftsforschung Discussion Paper 8, pp 1–30

    Google Scholar 

  • Beinhocker ED (2013) Reflexivity, complexity, and the nature of social science. J Econ Methodol 20(4):330–342

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bianchi M (2014) The magic of storytelling: how curiosity and aesthetic preferences work. Economics Discussion Papers Kiel Institute for the World Economy 23

    Google Scholar 

  • Boldizzoni F (2011) Poverty of Clio. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Box GEP, Draper NR (1987) Empirical model building and response surfaces. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne RMJ (2007) The rational imagination. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Campe R (2002) Spiel der Wahrscheinlichkeit. Literatur und Berechnung zwischen Pascal und Kleist. Wallstein Verlag, Göttingen

    Google Scholar 

  • Chick V, Dow SC (2005) The meaning of open systems. J Econ Methodol 12(3):363–381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colander D (2002) Complexity and the history of economic thought. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Damásio AR, Damásio H, Christen Y (1996) Neurobiology of decision-making. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Eco U (1994) Im Wald der Fiktionen: Sechs Streifzüge durch die Literatur. Deutscher Taschenbuchverlag, München

    Google Scholar 

  • Esposito E (2011) The future of futures: the time of money in financing and society. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Esposito E (2013) The structures of uncertainty: performativity and unpredictability in economic operations. Econ Soc 42(1):102–129

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (1953) The methodology of positive economics. In: Friedman M (ed) In positive economics. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G, Gaissmaier W (2011) Heuristic decision making. Annu Rev Psychol 62:451–482

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman DM (1992) The inexact and separate science of economics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heinzelman K (1980) The economics of the imagination. University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst

    Google Scholar 

  • Herrmann-Pillath C (2011) Economics of identity and creativity. University of Queensland Press, Brisbane

    Google Scholar 

  • Herrmann-Pillath C (2013) Foundations of economic evolution: a treatise on the natural philosophy of economics. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Keynes JM (1936) The general theory of employment, interest and money. Palgrave Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirman A (2011a) The crisis in economic theory. Rivista Italiana degli Economisti, SIE—Societa’ Italiana degli Economisti 16(1):9–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirman A (2011b) Complex economics: individual and collective rationality. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Klamer A (2007) Speaking of economics: how to get in the conversation. Routledge, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kleeberg B (2009) Gewinn maximieren, Gleichgewicht modellieren. Erzählen im ökonomischen Diskurs. In: Klein C, Martínez M (Hgs) Wirklichkeitserzählungen. Felder, Formen und Funktionen nicht-literarischen Erzählen. Metzler, Stuttgart, pp 136–159

    Google Scholar 

  • Künzel C (2014) Imaginierte Zukunft: Zur Bedeutung von Fiktion(en) in ökonomischen Diskursen. In: Balin I, Zilles S (Hrsg) Literarische Ökonomik. Fink, Paderborn

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKenzie D (2006a) Is economics performative? Option Theor Construct Derivat Market 28:29–55

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKenzie D (2006b) An engine, not a camera: How financial models shape markets. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey DN (1983) The rhetoric of economics. J Econ Lit 21(2):481–517

    Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey DN (1985) A conversation with Donald N. McCloskey about rhetoric. East Econ J 11(4):293–296

    Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey DN (1997) The rhetoric of economics, revisited. East Econ J 23(3):359–362

    Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey DN (1998) The rhetoric of economics (Rhetoric of the human sciences). University of Wisconsin Press, Madison

    Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey DN (2009) Rhetoric matters: ethical standards in a humanistic science of economics. Challenge 52(4):25–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan J (2013) Forecasting, prediction and precision: a commentary (Ch. 12). In: Kabalak A, Priddat BP (Hrsg) Ungewissheit als Herausforderung für die ökonomische Theorie: Nichtwissen, Ambivalenz und Entscheidung. Metropolis, Marburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Pentland A (2014) Social physics: how good ideas spread—the lessons from a new science. Penguin Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (1934) The logic of scientific discovery. Taylor & Francis, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Priddat BP (2014a) Economics of persuasion. Ökonomie zwischen Markt, Kommunikation und Überredung, Metropolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Priddat BP (2014b) Prognose als narrative Plausibilität. In: Cevolini M (Hrsg) Die Ordnung des Kontingenten. Springer, Berlin, pp 251–280

    Google Scholar 

  • Rist G (2011) The delusions of economics: the misguided certainties of a hazardous science. Zed Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg A (2013) Reflexivity, uncertainty and the unity of science. J Econ Methodol 20(4):429–438

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter JA (1954) History of economic analysis: with a new introduction. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Soros G (2013) Fallibility, reflexivity, and the human uncertainty principle. J Econ Methodol 20(4):309–329

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (2009) Credible worlds, capacities and mechanism. Erkenntnis 70(3):3–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Virlics A (2013) Emotions in economic decision making: a multidisciplinary approach. Procedia Soc Behav Sci 92(10):1011–1015

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Köhn, J. (2017). Extending the Boundaries of Economics. In: Uncertainty in Economics. Contributions to Economics. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-55351-1_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics