Skip to main content

The Axiomatic Approach to the Ranking of Infinite Streams

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Economics of the Global Environment

Part of the book series: Studies in Economic Theory ((ECON.THEORY,volume 29))

  • 918 Accesses

Abstract

The history of the axiomatic approach to the ranking of infinite streams starts with Koopmans (1960) characterization of the discounted utilitarian rule. This rule, however, meets Chichilnisky’s axiom of dictatorship of the present and puts future generations offside. Recently, Lauwers (2010a) and Zame (2007) have uncovered the impossibility to combine in a constructible way the requirements of equal treatment, sensitivity, and completeness. This contribution presents and discusses different axioms proposed to guide the ranking of infinite streams and the criteria they imply. The literature covered in this overview definitely points towards a set of meaningful alternatives to discounted utilitarianism.

I thank Graciela Chichilnisky and Armon Rezai for inviting me to write this chapter. I am also grateful for the comments from a referee, Tom Potoms, and Luc Van Liedekerke.

24 juli 2014.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In his review on intergenerational equity, Asheim (2010, Sect. 3.2) coins this result as the Lauwers-Zame impossibility theorem.

  2. 2.

    I want to mention already here that the combination of continuity with respect to the sup-topology and representability does not guarantee that the ranking rule is constructible. The other way around, the representation of a non-constructible ordering, is in itself a non-constructible object.

  3. 3.

    Ferejohn and Page (1978) have shown that unrestricted domain, Pareto, Arrovian independence, and stationarity results in dictatorship of the first generation. This result has been strengthened by Packell (1980).

  4. 4.

    Section 3 provides a simple example to indicate that paths optimal with respect to a sustainable-equitable approach might differ substantially from optima generated by the discounted utilitarian rule.

  5. 5.

    See also Koopmans (1960, 1965, 1972a) and Koopmans et al. (1964).

  6. 6.

    For simplicity, \(Y=\mathbb {R}\), \(x_t\) is the consumption of generation t, and the set \(\ell _\infty \) of bounded streams takes the role of X.

  7. 7.

    Koopmans considers infinite streams of vectors instead of scalars. The axiom of monotonicity is a one-dimensional version of Koopmans’ axiom.

  8. 8.

    Diamond (1965) follows Debreu (1954) to prove this result.

  9. 9.

    This motivation, however, is wrong in case the continuous social welfare function represents a non-constructible order.

  10. 10.

    See also Fleurbaey and Michel (2003, Sect. 3.4).

  11. 11.

    Different axiomatizations are obtained by Lauwers (1997c), Bleichrodt et al. (2008), and Asheim et al. (2012).

  12. 12.

    The factor \((1-\alpha )\) in the definition of D ensures that \(D(x,x,\ldots ,x,\ldots )=u(x)\). Hence, the weights with which the \(u(x_t)\) are multiplied add up to 1.

  13. 13.

    The map \(x\mapsto (1-\beta )(x_1+\beta \, x_2+\cdots +\beta ^{t-1}x_t+\cdots )\) obtains a maximal value, equal to 0.3025, in one of the streams of type \(t^n\); while the stream \(u^\infty \) obtains a lower value of 0.25.

  14. 14.

    Dubey (2011) and Dubey and Mitra (2011) investigate the role of the set Y of possible utility levels and refine the results of Lauwers (2010a) and Zame (2007).

  15. 15.

    We refer to Suppes (1966), Sen (1971), Hammond (1976), d’Aspremont and Gevers (1977), and Shorrocks (1983). Bossert and Weymark (2004) provide an excellent overview.

  16. 16.

    Note the similarity with the decisive sets in Arrow’s impossibility theorem. See also Fleurbaey and Michel (2003).

  17. 17.

    Basu and Mitra (2007) discuss this example.

  18. 18.

    Demichelis et al. (2010) study axioms of anonymity in combination with strong Pareto and stationarity.

  19. 19.

    A non-Ramsey set is a subset \(\mathcal N\) of the collection \(\mathbb {N}_\infty \) of all infinite subsets of \(\mathbb {N}\) such that for each element J in \(\mathcal N\) the collection of infinite subsets of J intersects both \(\mathcal{N}\) and its complement \(\mathbb {N}_\infty -\mathcal{N}\). The technique developed in Lauwers (2010a) to define non-Ramsey sets has been used by Dubey and Mitra (2013) to show that a complete ranking that combines strong Pareto and Hammond equity (or the strict transfer principle) is non-constructible. See also Dubey (2011), Dubey and Mitra (2011, 2012), and Banerjee and Dubey (2013).

  20. 20.

    Doyen and Martinet (2012) apply the maximin rule in a general dynamic economic model.

  21. 21.

    Asheim and Zuber (2013) study the behavior of the rank-discounted utilitarian rule as \(\beta \) goes to zero and show the convergence of R towards a strongly anonymous leximin relation.

  22. 22.

    Also Banerjee (2006a), Asheim et al. (2007), Alcantud and García-Sanz (2010), Dubey and Mitra (2013) consider Hammond equity for the future.

  23. 23.

    We refer to Yosida and Hewitt (1952), Rao (1958), and Peressini (1967).

  24. 24.

    Dubey and Mitra (2013) provide an example of a non-constructible relation on X that satisfies the Pigou-Dalton transfer principle while its representation has been established by Sakamoto (2012).

  25. 25.

    The map \(\liminf \) violates additivity: let \(x=(1,0,1,0,\ldots )\) and \(y=(0,1,0,1,\ldots )\), then \(\liminf (x)= \liminf (y)=0\) while \(\liminf (x+y)=1\). The map \(\liminf \), however, still fits in the Chichilnisky approach.

References

  • Alcantud, J. C. R., & García-Sanz, M. D. (2010). Paretian evaluation of infinite utility streams: An egalitarian criterion. Economics Letters, 106, 209–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. J. (1999). Discounting, morality, and gaming. In J. P. Portney & J. P. Weyant (Eds.), Discounting and intergenerational equity. Washington DC: Resources for the Future.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asheim, G. B. (2010) Intergenerational equity. In K. J. Arrow & T. F. Breshanan (Eds.), Book series, Annual review of economics (Vol. 2, pp. 197–222).

    Google Scholar 

  • Asheim, G. B., & Banerjee, K. (2010). Fixed-step anonymous overtaking and catching-up. International Journal of Economic Theory, 6, 149–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim, G. B., & Mitra, T. (2010). Sustainability and discounted utilitarianism in models of economic growth. Mathematical Social Sciences, 59, 148–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim, G. B., Mitra, T., & Tungodden, B. (2007). A new equity condition for infinite utility streams and the possibility of being Paretian. In J. Roemer & K. Suzumura (Eds.), Intergenerational equity and sustainability. London: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asheim, G. B., Mitra, T., & Tungodden, B. (2012). Sustainable recursive social welfare functions. Economic Theory, 49, 267–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim, G. B., & Tungodden, B. (2004). Resolving distributional conflicts between generations. Economic Theory, 24, 221–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim, G. B., & Zuber, S. (2013). A complete and strongly anonymous leximin relation on infinite streams. Social Choice and Welfare, 41, 819–834.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson, A. B. (2001). The strange disappearance of welfare economics. Kyklos, 54, 193–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Atsumi, H. (1965). Neoclassical growth and the efficient program of capital accumulation. Review of Economic Studies, 32, 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banerjee, K. (2006a). On the equity-efficiency trade off in aggregating infinite utility streams. Economic Letters, 93, 63–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banerjee, K. (2006b). On the extension of the utilitarian and Suppes-Sen social welfare relations to infinite utility streams. Social Choice and Welfare, 27, 327–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banerjee, K., & Dubey, R. S. (2013). Do all constructive strongly monotonic inter-temporal orders exhibit impatience. Working paper: Florida Atlantic University, Montclair State University, USA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Basu, K., & Mitra, T. (2003). Aggregating infinite utility streams with intergenerational equity: The impossibility of being Paretian. Econometrica, 71, 1557–1563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Basu, K., & Mitra, T. (2007). Utilitarianism for infinite utility streams: A new welfare criterion and its axiomatic characterization. Journal of Economic Theory, 133, 350–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt, H., Rohde, K. I. M., & Wakker, P. P. (2008). Koopmans’ constant discounting for intertemporal choice: A simplification and a generalization. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 52, 341–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bossert, W., Sprumont, Y., & Suzumura, K. (2007). Ordering infinite utility streams. Journal of Economic Theory, 135, 579–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bossert, W., & Weymark, J. A. (2004). Utility in social choice. In S. Barbera, P. J. Hammond, & C. H. Seidl (Eds.), Handbook of utility theory (Vol. 2). Amsterdam: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brock, W. A. (1970). An axiomatic basis for the Ramsey-Weizsäcker overtaking criterion. Econometrica, 38, 927–929.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, C. P. (2009). Intergenerational equity: Sup, inf, lim sup, and lim inf. Social Choice and Welfare, 32, 243–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chichilnisky, G. (1996). An axiomatic approach to sustainable development. Social Choice and Welfare, 13, 231–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chichilnisky, G. (1997). What is sustainable development? Land Economics, 73, 467–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chichilnisky, G. (2009). Avoiding extinction: Equal treatment of the present and the future. Economics, The Open-Access, Open-Assessment E-Journal 3, Article number 200932. http://www.economics-ejournal.org/economics/journalarticles/2009-32.

  • Dasgupta, P. S., & Heal, G. M. (1979). Economic theory and exhaustible resources. Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • d’Aspremont, C., & Gevers, L. (1977). Equity and the informational basis of collective choice. Review of Economic Studies, 46, 199–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G. (1954). Representation of a preference ordering by a numerical function. In R. M. Thrall, C. H. Coombs, & R. L. Davis (Eds.), Chapter XI in Decision processes. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demichelis, S., Mitra, T., & Sorger, G. (2010). Intergenerational equity and stationarity. Working Paper No 1003: Department of Economics, University of Vienna.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, P. A. (1965). The evaluation of infinite utility streams. Econometrica, 33, 170–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doyen, L., & Martinet, V. (2012). Maximin, viability and sustainability. Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 36, 1414–1430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubey, R. S. (2011). Fleurbaey-Michel conjecture on equitable weak Paretian social welfare order. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 47, 434–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubey, R. S., & Mitra, T. (2011). On equitable social welfare functions satisfying the weak Pareto axiom: A complete characterization. International Journal of Economic Theory, 7, 231–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubey, R. S., Mitra, T. (2012). On monotone social welfare orders satisfying the strong equity axiom: Construction and representation. Working paper: Montclair State University, Cornell University Ithaca, USA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dubey, R. S., Mitra, T. (2013). On representation and construction of equitable social welfare orders on infinite utility streams. Working paper: Montclair State University, Cornell University Ithaca, USA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferejohn, J., & Page, T. (1978). On the foundations of intertemporal choice. American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 60, 269–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey, M., & Michel, P. (2003). Intertemporal equity and the extension of the Ramsey criterion. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 39, 777–802.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey, M., Zuber, S. (2012). Climate policies deserve a negative discount rate. Fondation Maison des sciences de l’homme, WP-2012-19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hammond, P. J. (1976). Equity, Arrow’s conditions, and Rawls’ difference principle. Econometrica, 44, 793–804.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hara, C., Shinotsuka, T., Suzumura, K., & Xu, Y. (2008). Continuity and egalitarianism in the evaluation of infinite utility streams. Social Choice and Welfare, 31, 179–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamaga, K., & Kojima, T. (2009). Q-anonymous social welfare relations on infinite utility streams. Social Choice and Welfare, 33, 405–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamaga, K., & Kojima, T. (2010). On the leximin and utilitarian overtaking criteria with extended anonymity. Social Choice and Welfare, 35, 377–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans, T. C. (1960). Stationary ordinal utility and impatience. Econometrica, 28, 287–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans, T. C. (1965). On the concept of optimal economic growth. Pontificiae Academiae Scientiarum Scripta Varia, 28, 225–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans, T. C. (1972a). Representation of preference orderings with independent components of consumption. In C. B. McGuire & R. Radner (Eds.), Decision and organization. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans, T. C. (1972b). Representation of preference orderings over time. In C. B. McGuire & R. Radner (Eds.), Decision and organization. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans, T. C. (1977). Concepts of optimality and their uses. American Economic Review, 67(3), 261–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans, T. C., Diamond, P. A., & Williamson, R. E. (1964). Stationary utility and time perspective. Econometrica, 32, 82–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauwers, L. (1997a). Continuity and equity with infinite horizons. Social Choice and Welfare, 14, 345–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauwers, L. (1997b). Infinite utility, insisting on strong monotonicity. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 75, 222–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauwers, L. (1997c). Rawlsian equity and generalized utilitarianism with an infinite population. Economic Theory, 9, 143–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauwers, L. (2009). A report on Graciela Chichilnisky: Avoiding extinction equal treatment of the present and the future. Economics, The Open-Access, Open-Assessment E-Journal. http://www.economics-ejournal.org/economics/discussionpapers/2009-8#comments.

  • Lauwers, L. (2010a). Ordering infinite utility streams comes at the cost of a non-Ramsey set. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 46, 32–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauwers, L. (2010b). Center for Economic Studies, DPS: Purely finitely additive measures are non-constructible objects. KU Leuven.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lauwers, L. (2012). Intergenerational equity, efficiency, and constructibility. Economic Theory, 49, 227–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitra, T., & Basu, K. (2007). On the existence of Paretian social welfare relations for infinite utility streams with extended anonymity. In J. Roemer & K. Suzumura (Eds.), Intergenerational equity and sustainability. London: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Packell, E. (1980). Impossibility results in the axiomatic theory of intertemporal choice. Public Choice, 35, 219–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peressini, A. (1967). Ordered topological vector spaces. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F. P. (1928). A mathematical theory of savings. The Economic Journal, 38, 543–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rao, R. R. (1958). A note on finitely additive measures. The Indian Journal of Statistics, 19, 27–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice (revised ed.). Cambridge: The Belknap Press of the Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sakai, T. (2010). Intergenerational equity and an explicit construction of welfare criteria. Social Choice and Welfare, 35, 393–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sakamoto, N. (2012). Impossibilities of Paretian social welfare functions for infinite utility streams with distributive equity. Hitotsubashi Journal of Economics, 53, 60–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. K. (1971). Collective choice and social welfare. Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. K. (1977). On weights and measures: Informational constraints in social welfare analysis. Econometrica, 45, 1539–1572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shorrocks, A. F. (1983). Ranking income disctributions. Economica, 50, 3–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sidgwick, H. (1907). The methods of ethics. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1966). Some formal models of grading principles. Synthese, 6, 284–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Svensson, L.-G. (1980). Equity among generations. Econometrica, 48, 1251–1256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szpilrajn, E. (1930). Sur l’extension du l’ordre partiel. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 16, 386–389.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, W. (2001). On the axiomatic method and its recent applications to game theory and resource allocation. Social Choice and Welfare, 18(2), 327–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Liedekerke, L., & Lauwers, L. (1997). Sacrificing the patrol: Utilitarianism, future generations and infinity. Economics and Philosophy, 13, 159–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Weizsäcker, C. C. (1965). Existence of optimal programs of accumulation for an infinite time horizon. Review of Economic Studies, 32, 85–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yosida, K., & Hewitt, E. (1952). Finitely additive measures. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 72, 46–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zame, W. R. (2007). Can intergenerational equity be operationalised. Theoretical Economics, 2, 187–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zuber, S., & Asheim, G. B. (2012). Justifying social discounting: The rank-discounted utilitarian approach. Journal of Economic Theory, 147, 1572–1601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luc Lauwers .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Lauwers, L. (2016). The Axiomatic Approach to the Ranking of Infinite Streams. In: Chichilnisky, G., Rezai, A. (eds) The Economics of the Global Environment. Studies in Economic Theory, vol 29. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-31943-8_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics