Skip to main content

Sources of the Self in the Arabic Tradition: Remarks on the Avicennan Turn

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Subjectivity and Selfhood in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy

Part of the book series: Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind ((SHPM,volume 16))

Abstract

Within the long history of Aristotelian psychological theorization, Avicenna stands out for his tightly argued and conceptually rich understanding of self-awareness. For Avicenna, a primitive and immediate form of self-awareness is explanatory of a range of phenomena, from the unity of our psychic functions to our very existence as cognizing individuals. The extent of Avicenna’s influence is beginning to be recognized in the scholarship: it remains an open question what, if anything, might have influenced him. In this essay I point to Islamic theological discussions regarding immediate self-knowledge as a possible relevant parallel. The Muslim theologians’ interests lay elsewhere, however, and their ontology of the soul diverged sharply from the Aristotelian, being atomist and occasionalist. Through evoking earlier Sufi attempts to flesh out a formal presentation of the soul to match their commitment to character reformation, I suggest that the Avicennan presentation of self-awareness provided an access point for religious writers to begin employing an Aristotelian psychology, given that it responded to existing theoretical concerns.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See, e.g., Sebti (2000), 102–111, Kaukua (2007), Black (2008); Alwishah’s results from his 2006 UCLA PhD dissertation remain unpublished to the best of my knowledge.

  2. 2.

    Note that the psychological part of the Healing was available since the late twelfth century in Gundissalinus’s Latin translation, but that the Latin scholastic authors knew neither about Avicenna’s remarks on the “Flying man” in the late Pointers and Reminders nor – crucially – his comments in the Glosses regarding our self-awareness as the grounds of our very existence.

  3. 3.

    For Bahmanyār see Sebti (2005–2006), also Sebti (2012), 532–539; for Abū al-Barakāt, see Kaukua’s contribution to this volume; related research has also been presented by Lukas Muehlethaler on several occasions, although I am not aware of a publication; Pines (1954) offers a valuable earlier look.

  4. 4.

    Muehlethaler (2009) sketches out some of the earlier history leading up to Ibn Kammūna, while Kaukua (2014) canvasses the major figures of Avicenna, al-Suhrawardī, and Mullā Ṣadrā. See also Marcotte (2006) for al-Suhrawardī and Kaukua (2010) for the somewhat anomalous place occupied by the enormously influential Muḥyī al-Dīn Ibn al-ʿArabī (d. 1240) in the discussions.

  5. 5.

    Shihadeh (2012), 475–476.

  6. 6.

    See note 1 for references.

  7. 7.

    For a careful comparison of non-human and human forms of self-awareness in Avicenna’s works see López-Farjeat (2012).

  8. 8.

    As has been noted by commentators from Druart (1988, 34) onwards, there is a crucial terminological elision here, inasmuch as the Arabic dhāt which is recognized and whose existence is affirmed can denote either a thing’s essence or its ‘self’ in the indexical sense of that term.

  9. 9.

    The last term is khulq kāmil, which I take to refer to the putative test subject’s capacity for passing sound judgement; Al-Shifāʾ: al-Nafs I.1, 15–16 Rahman.

  10. 10.

    On this title and its dating and positioning within Avicenna’s authorship see Gutas (2014), 472–477.

  11. 11.

    Risāla aḍḥawiyya, 141–145. Presumably, the point made in evoking the special status of the heart and the brain is that a philosophical examination of the essence (dhāt) of one’s soul or self (nafs – another inherently polyvalent term, see section “Sufi Self-Examination” below) does not reduce to mere physiological facts, regardless of whether those are construed in accordance with Aristotelian or Galenic principles.

  12. 12.

    On this point see, e.g., Kaukua (2007), 72–74. Important here is the fact that the possibility of the Flying Man appears to be entertained by the estimative faculty: on the role of estimation in thought experiments see Kukkonen (2014).

  13. 13.

    See, e.g., al-Shifāʾ: al-Nafs V.7 and Ishārāt, 119. The primary importance of psychic unity is stressed especially by Deborah Black (2008).

  14. 14.

    Kaukua (2007), 79–80, referring to Al-Shifāʾ: al-Nafs V.3, 226–227 Rahman.

  15. 15.

    Taʿlīqāt, 161.

  16. 16.

    This is to say that the dhāt in Avicenna’s sentence construction is to be understood in the reflexive sense: in every perception and thought, and even in the absence of either, is carried the affirmation of ourselves as the subject of this presence or absence.

  17. 17.

    Sebti (2000), 117–120 points to a passage in the Plotinian Theology of Aristotle (mīmar 1, paraphrasing Plotinus, Enneads IV.8.1) and another in the Hermetic Kitāb muʿādhala al-nafs, each of which is interesting in the present context. I would contend, however, that the Theology’s description of casting the body aside only shares surface similarities with Avicenna’s Flying Man, while the Hermetic treatise is of marginal importance historically. Sebti further mentions Jāḥiẓ’s brief report on the Muʿtazilite theologian Muʿammar Ibn ʿAbbād al-Sulamī (d. 830 CE): this seems to me more apposite, as it connects up with the narrative I sketch out below.

  18. 18.

    See Wisnovsky (2003), Madelung (2006) offers further materials.

  19. 19.

    See Hubler (2005) and for a selection of primary sources Sorabji (2005), 145–158.

  20. 20.

    Kaukua and Kukkonen (2007), 101.

  21. 21.

    Kitāb al-irshād, 14.

  22. 22.

    It is not impossible that al-Juwaynī would have drawn inspiration from Avicenna – he certainly did so in the domain of metaphysics – but as we shall see, the Ashʿarite line about necessary self-knowledge predates Avicenna, and the evidence points to al-Juwaynī operating within the kalām tradition of psychology, not the Avicennan one.

  23. 23.

    Kitāb uṢūl al-dīn, 8.

  24. 24.

    One should not mistake what is being said here: al-Bāqillānī claims that sensory knowledge, too, is necessary. This breaches the conventional requirement that necessary knowledge be immediate rather than arrived at through an intermediary (here, sensation); it appears, therefore, that for al-Bāqillānī, as opposed to many of his theologian colleagues, the criterion of indubitability is the overriding concern when it comes to determining what is necessary knowledge and what is not.

  25. 25.

    Kitāb al-tamhīd, 29–30. Al-Bāqillānī follows up these psychological examples by other standard examples of a priori knowledge such as the knowledge that every predicative proposition is either true or false, and that two diametrically opposed statements cannot both be true simultaneously (or for that matter false).

  26. 26.

    For the kalām doctrine of acquisition see Wolfson (1976), 663–719.

  27. 27.

    Tamhīd, 30–31.

  28. 28.

    See Vasalou (2009).

  29. 29.

    A Rāfiḍite theologian by the name of Ṣāliḥ al-Ṣāliḥī draws the obvious epistemological conclusion that all knowledge is necessary knowledge in the final analysis, given how created beings have no capacity for doubting it when it is created in them. See Abrahamov (1993), 24.

  30. 30.

    See Abrahamov (1989), Abrahamov (1993), 27–28.

  31. 31.

    Kitāb al-lumaʿ, section 92, 41.16–17 McCarthy.

  32. 32.

    This difficult aspect of Ashʿarite ontology – that is, a double agency of sorts combined with a single author of all acts – is discussed in Frank (1966), with the emphasis precisely on al-Ashʿarī’s treatise cited.

  33. 33.

    In terms of grammar, as the mutakallimūn analyzed it, such acts are typically those assigned to the whole human being, meaning the whole composite body, rather than some part of it.

  34. 34.

    Vasalou (2008), 132–148.

  35. 35.

    Vasalou (2008), 136.

  36. 36.

    See Peters (1976), 159.

  37. 37.

    Vasalou (2008), 157.

  38. 38.

    Vasalou (2008), 133.

  39. 39.

    There is an immense body of literature on the Sufi tradition, much of which also addresses Sufi treatments of the soul and the ideal of self-mortification in some way. Knysh (2000) presents a comprehensive overview; for the early period and al-Muḥāsibī (d. 857) in particular, see Picken (2011), Chaps. 4–5; for Qurʾānic uses of nafs, Picken (2011), 129–139.

  40. 40.

    Al-Tustarī, Tafsīr, 91.

  41. 41.

    On al-Tustarī’s complex theory of the soul and self, see Böwering (1980), 185–261.

  42. 42.

    Al-Qushayrī, Risāla, 86–87.

  43. 43.

    On Ashʿarite atomist premises, there may be a discrete number of atoms corresponding to each evocation of nafs, rūḥ, etc., but we remain ignorant of the number.

  44. 44.

    Al-Qushayrī, Risāla, 88.

  45. 45.

    See Iḥyāʾ ʿulūm al-dīn, 5:13–20 (XXI, bayān 1).

  46. 46.

    The one clear precedent to al-Ghazālī in this regard is the work of his near-contemporary al-Rāghib al-IṢfahānī (d. 1108), whom al-Ghazālī indeed follows in his approach, as shown by Madelung (1974), Janssens (2008), Mohamed (2011).

  47. 47.

    See Iḥyāʾ, 5:199–207 (XXII, bayān 3).

  48. 48.

    See Kukkonen (2008), Kukkonen (2012), Kukkonen (2015a); the weightiest contribution on al-Ghazālī’s cognitive psychology is Treiger (2012), while Sherif (1975) canvasses moral psychology; to these one may add individual studies by Jules Janssens, Frank Griffel, M. Afifi al-Akiti, and others.

  49. 49.

    Al-Shifāʾ: al-Nafs I.5, 47 Rahman.

  50. 50.

    See Kukkonen (2008).

  51. 51.

    Al-Shifāʾ: al-Nafs I.5, 46–47 Rahman and V.1, 207–209 Rahman. Avicenna’s weightiest contribution on ethics, a short treatise On Governance, is translated in McGinnis and Reisman (2007), 224–237, but even here it is remarkable how little space is given over to introspection.

  52. 52.

    See Tahāfut XVIII. 11–12 Marmura; Marmura (1988).

  53. 53.

    Kīmiyā-yi saʿādat, 1:16.

  54. 54.

    I make the case for why Peripatetic faculty psychology in general proved attractive to later kalām authors in Kukkonen (2015b).

  55. 55.

    Ishārāt, 56; I owe the reference to Jari Kaukua.

  56. 56.

    Rāzī (1968).

Bibliography

Primary Sources

  • Ashʿarī, Abū al-Ḥasan ʿAlī Ibn Ismāʿīl al- (1953). Kitāb al-lumaʿ. In R. J. McCarthy (Ed.), The theology of al-Ashʿarī. Beirut: Imprimerie Catholique. [= Glimmerings].

    Google Scholar 

  • Baghdādī, ʿAbd al-Qāhir Ibn Ṭāhir al- (1928). Kitāb uṢūl al-dīn. Istanbul: Madrasa al-ilāhīya bi dār al-funūn al-Turkīya. [= Fundamentals of Faith].

    Google Scholar 

  • Bāqillānī, Muḥammad Ibn al-Ṭayyib al- (1987). In ʿI. A. Ḥaydar (Ed.), Kitāb al-tamhīd al-awāʾil wa talkhīṢ al-dalāʾil. Beirut: Muʾassasat al-kutub al-thaqāfīya. [= Introduction].

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghazālī, Abū Ḥāmid Muḥammad al- (1983). In Ḥ. Khadīvjam (Ed.), Kīmiyā-yi saʿādat. Tehran: Markaz-i Intishārāt-i ʿIlmī va Farhangī. [= Alchemy].

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghazālī, Abū Ḥāmid Muḥammad al- (2000). Tahāfut al-falāsifa. In Ed. after M. Bouyges, trans. M. E. Marmura, The incoherence of the philosophers. Provo: Brigham Young University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghazālī, Abū Ḥāmid Muḥammad al- (2011). Iḥyāʾ ʿulūm al-dīn (Vol. 10). Jeddah: Dār al-minhāj. [= Revival].

    Google Scholar 

  • Ibn Sīnā, Abū ʿAlī (Avicenna). (1892). In J. Forget (Ed.), al-Ishārāt wa-l-tanbīhāt. Leiden: E.J. Brill. [= Pointers and Reminders].

    Google Scholar 

  • Ibn Sīnā, Abū ʿAlī (Avicenna). (1959). al-Shifāʾ: al-Nafs. In F. Rahman (Ed.), Avicenna’s De Anima. Being the psychological part of Kitāb al-Shifāʾ. London: Oxford University Press. [= Healing: the Soul].

    Google Scholar 

  • Ibn Sīnā, Abū ʿAlī (Avicenna). (1969). Risāla al-aḍḥawīya fī l-maʿād. In F. Lucchetta (Ed.), Epistola sulla vita future. Padua: Antenore. [= Immolation Destination].

    Google Scholar 

  • Juwaynī, ʿAbd al-Malik Abū al-Maʿālī al- (1950). In M. Y. Mūsā and ʿĀ. ʿA. ʿA. Kabīr (Eds.), Kitāb al-irshād. MiṢr: Maktaba al-Khānjī. [= Guidance].

    Google Scholar 

  • Qushayrī, Abū al-QāṢim al- (1990). In M. Zurayq & ʿA. BalṬahjī (Eds.), Al-risāla al-Qushayrīya. Beirut: Dār al-Jīl. [= Epistle].

    Google Scholar 

  • Rāzī, Fakhr al-Dīn Muḥammad al- (1968). In M. S. Ḥ. Maʿsūmī (Ed.), Kitāb al-nafs wa al-rūḥ wa-sharḥ quwāhumā. Islamabad: Islamic Research Institute. [= Soul and Spirit].

    Google Scholar 

  • Tustarī, Sahl Ibn ʿAbd Allāh al- (1329 a.H./1911 CE). Tafsīr al-Qur’ān al-‘aẓīm. Cairo: Dār al-kutub al-ʿArabīya al-kubrā. [= Commentary].

    Google Scholar 

Secondary Sources

  • Abrahamov, B. (1989). A re-examination of al-Ashʿarī’s theory of kasb according to Kitāb al-lumaʿ. Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society, 2, 210–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Abrahamov, B. (1993). Necessary knowledge in Islamic theology. British Journal of Middle Eastern Studies, 20(1), 20–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black, D. L. (2008). Avicenna on self-awareness and knowing that one knows. In S. Rahman et al. (Eds.), The unity of science in the Arabic tradition. Science, logic, epistemology, and their interactions (pp. 63–87). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Böwering, G. (1980). The mystical vision of existence in classical Islam. Berlin/New York: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Druart, T.-A. (1988). The soul and body problem: Avicenna and Descartes. In T.-A. Druart (Ed.), Arabic philosophy and the west. Continuity and interaction (pp. 27–48). Washington, DC: Center for Contemporary Arab Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eichner, H. (2011). Knowledge by presence, apperception, and the mind-body relationship. Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī and al-Suhrawardī as representatives and precursors of a thirteenth-century discussion. In P. Adamson (Ed.), In the age of averroes. Arabic philosophy in the sixth/twelfth century (pp. 117–140). London: The Warburg Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R. M. (1966). The structure of created causality according to al-Ašʿarī. An analysis of the Kitāb al-lumaʿ, pars. 82–164. Studia Islamica, 25, 13–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gutas, D. (2014). Avicenna and the Aristotelian tradition. Introduction to reading Avicenna’s philosophical works (2nd ed.). Leiden: E.J. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasse, D. N. (2000). Avicenna’s De Anima in the Latin west. London: The Warburg Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hubler, N. J. (2005). The perils of self-perception: Explanations of apperception in the Greek commentaries on Aristotle. The Review of Metaphysics, 59, 287–311.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janssens, J. (2008). Al-Ghazālī’s Mīzān al-ʿAmal: An ethical summa based on Ibn Sīnā and al-Rāghib al-IṢfahānī. In A. Akasoy & W. Raven (Eds.), Islamic thought in the middle ages: Studies in text, transmission and translation, in honour of Hans Daiber (pp. 123–137). Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaukua, J. (2007). Avicenna on subjectivity. Jyväskylä: University of Jyväskylä. [Also available online at URL: https://jyx.jyu.fi/dspace/handle/123456789/13299]

  • Kaukua, J. (2010). I in the eye of God: Ibn ʿArabī on the divine human self. Journal of the Muhyiddin Ibn ʿArabī Society, 47, 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaukua, J. (2011). I in the light of God: Selfhood and self-awareness in Suhrawardī’s Ḥikmat al-ishrāq. In P. Adamson (Ed.), In the age of averroes. Arabic philosophy in the sixth/twelfth century (pp. 141–157). London: The Warburg Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaukua, J. (2014). Self-awareness in Islamic philosophy. Avicenna and beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaukua, J., & Kukkonen, T. (2007). Sense-perception and self-awareness: Before and after Avicenna. In S. Heinämaa, V. Lähteenmäki, & P. Remes (Eds.), Consciousness. From perception to reflection in the history of philosophy (pp. 95–119). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knysh, A. (2000). Islamic mysticism. A short history. Leiden: E.J. Brill.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kukkonen, T. (2008). The self as enemy, the self as divine: A crossroads in the development of Islamic anthropology. In J. Sihvola & P. Remes (Eds.), Ancient philosophy of the self (pp. 205–224). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kukkonen, T. (2012). Receptive to reality: Al-Ghazālī on the structure of the soul. The Muslim World, 102(3–4), 541–561.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kukkonen, T. (2014a). Ibn Sīnā and the early history of thought experiments. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 52(3), 433–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kukkonen, T. (2015a). Al-Ghazālī on the emotions. In G. Tamer (Ed.), Islam and rationality. The impact of al-Ghazālī (pp. 138–164). Leiden: E.J. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kukkonen, T. (2015b). Faculties in classical Arabic philosophy. In D. Perler (Ed.), Faculties (pp. 66–96). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • López-Farjeat, L. X. (2012). Self-awareness (al-shuʿūr bi-al-dhāt) in human and non-human animals in Avicenna’s psychological writings. In A. G. Vigo (Ed.), Oikeiosis and the natural bases of morality. From classical stoicism to modern philosophy (pp. 121–139). Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Madelung, W. (1974). Ar-Rāġib al-Isfahānī und die Ethik al-Ġazālīs. In R. Gramlich (Ed.), Islamkundliche Abhandlungen. Fritz Meier zum sechzigsten Geburtstag (pp. 152–163). Wiesbaden: Franz Steiner Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Madelung, W. (2006). Abū l-Ḥusayn al-BaṢrī’s proof for the existence of God. In J. E. Montgomery (Ed.), Arabic theology, Arabic philosophy. From the many to the one: Essays in celebration of Richard M. Frank (pp. 273–280). Leuven: Peeters Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcotte, R. D. (2006). L’aperception de soi chez Shihāb al-Dīn al-Suhrawardī et l’héritage avicennien. Laval théologique et philosophique, 62, 529–551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marmura, M. E. (1986). Avicenna’s ‘Flying Man’ in context. The Monist, 69, 383–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marmura, M. E. (1988). Ghazali and the Avicennan proof from personal identity to an immaterial self. In R. Link-Salinger, J. Hackett, et al. (Eds.), A straight path. Studies in medieval philosophy and culture. Essays in honor of Arthur Hyman (pp. 192–205). Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinnis, J., & Reisman, D. C. (Eds.). (2007). Classical Arabic philosophy. An anthology of sources. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohamed, Y. (2011). The ethics of education: Al-IṢfahānī’s Al-Dharīʿa as a source of inspiration for al-Ghazālī’s Mizān al-‘Amal. The Muslim World, 101(4), 633–657.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muehlethaler, L. (2009). Ibn Kammūna on the argument of the Flying Man in Avicenna’s Išārāt and al-Suhrawardī’s Talwīḥāt. In Y. T. Langermann (Ed.), Avicenna and his legacy: A golden age of science and philosophy (pp. 179–203). Turnhout: Brepols.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, J. (1976). God’s created speech. Leiden: E.J. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Picken, G. (2011). Spiritual purification in Islam. The life and works of al-Muḥāsibī. London/New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pines, S. (1954). La conception de la conscience de soi chez Avicenne et chez Abu’l-Barakāt al-Baghdādī. Archives d’Histoire Doctrinale et Littéraire du Moyen Age, 21, 21–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sebti, M. (2000). Avicenne. L’âme humaine. Paris: PUF.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sebti, M. (2005–2006). Intellection, imagination et aperception de soi dans le Livre du Résultat (kitāb al−TaḥṢīl) de Bahmanyār Ibn al−Marzūbān. Chôra, 3–4, 189–210

    Google Scholar 

  • Sebti, M. (2012). The ontological link between body and soul in Bahmanyār’s Kitāb al-TaḥṢīl. The Muslim World, 102(3–4), 525–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sherif, M. (1975). Ghazali’s theory of virtue. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shihadeh, A. (2012). Classical Ashʿarī anthropology: Body, life and spirit. The Muslim World, 102(3–4), 433–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sorabji, R. (Ed.). (2005). The philosophy of the commentators. Volume 3: Psychology with ethics and religion. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Treiger, A. (2012). Inspired knowledge in Islamic thought. Al-Ghazālī’s theory of mystical cognition and its Avicennian foundation. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasalou, S. (2008). Moral agents and their deserts. The character of Muʿtazilite ethics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vasalou, S. (2009). ‘Their intention was shown by their bodily Movements’: The BaṢran Muʿtazilites on the institution of language. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 47(2), 201–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wisnovsky, R. (2003). Avicenna’s metaphysics in context. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wolfson, H. A. (1976). The philosophy of the Kalam. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Taneli Kukkonen .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kukkonen, T. (2016). Sources of the Self in the Arabic Tradition: Remarks on the Avicennan Turn. In: Kaukua, J., Ekenberg, T. (eds) Subjectivity and Selfhood in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind, vol 16. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-26914-6_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics