Skip to main content

Justice in Renaissance Philosophy

  • Reference work entry
  • First Online:
Encyclopedia of Renaissance Philosophy
  • 15 Accesses

Abstract

The classical ideal of justice remained vibrant in the Middle Ages because it was embodied in the surviving texts of Roman law, the Corpus Iuris Civilis. From there, it entered canon law, where it gained strength from its association with the divine giver of justice. Justice in the classical tradition was an ideal of distributive justice, a socially fair allocation of things, rendering to each his due. It was an ideal ostensibly linked to outcomes, independent of process. Ideal and practice were never necessarily coincident, however, and it was along that fissure that humanist critiques of law and its practitioners, beginning with Petrarch (20 July 1304–19 July 1374), launched largely ethical arguments. Justice, itself an ethical construct, was being lost, said humanists, in procedural delays and cascades of citations and references, and in bad Latin, that seemingly served only to line the pockets of lawyers, judges, and notaries. By the sixteenth century, the ethical arguments had spilled over into epistemological attacks as well. The quasi-sacred quality of the classical legal texts was confronted by a more thoroughly historical construction of those texts, most frequently associated with the Italian jurist Andrea Alciato (8 May 1492–12 January 1550). This gave birth to such a different method of reading the texts of the Corpus that it came to be called the mos gallicus, in contrast to the older mos italicus, associated in many minds with the fourteenth-century jurist Bartolus of Sassoferrato (1313–1357). Against the assertion that no professional jurist could operate in any other fashion (nemo iurista nisi bartolista), lay the argument that justice lays in appropriate laws that served a people in their peculiar historical context. The legislator (most prominently a king, such as that of France), rather than the academically educated interpreter, was looked to as the font of justice. Justice could thus be reconceived, as it was by figures, such as Jean Bodin (1530–June 1596) and John Locke (29 August 1632–28 October 1704), in terms of a particular state and its ruler and its people, and natural law became unhinged from the realm of objective patterns of behavior and bound to subjective rights instead.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 1,399.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 1,599.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

Primary Literature

  • Baldo, Ubaldi. 1585. In primam Digesti veteris commentaria. Venice: Lyon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartolus. 1560. In primam Digesti veteris partem commentaria. Lyon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gratian. 1993. The treatise on laws with the ordinary gloss. Trans. A. Thompson and J. Gordley. Washington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Justinian. 1987. Justinian’s Institutes. Trans. P. Burks and G. McLeod. Ithaca.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mommsen, T. H., W. Kroll, P. Krueger, and R. Schoell, eds. 1928–29. Corpus iuris civilis. 3 vols. Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scala, B. 2008. Essays and dialogues. Trans. R. N. Watkins. Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

Secondary Literature

  • Ascheri, M. 1999. Le fonti e la flessibilità del diritto comune: il paradosso del consilium sapientis. In Legal consulting in the civil law tradition, ed. M. Ascheri, I. Baumgärtner, and J. Kirshner, 11–53. Berkeley: The Robbins Collection.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bellabarba, M. 2008. La giustizia nell’Italia moderna. Bari.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bellomo, M. 1995. The common legal past of Europe, 1000–1800. Trans. L. G. Cochrane. Washington, DC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berman, H.J. 1983. Law and revolutions: The formation of the Western legal tradition. Vol. 1. Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cerutti, S. 1995. Normes et pratiques, ou de la legitimité de leur opposition In Les formes de l’expérience: une autre histoire sociale, ed. B. Lepetit, 127–49. Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cortese, E. 2000. Le grandi linee della storia giuridica medievale. Rome.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fantini, M. G. 1998. La cultura del giurista medievale: Natura, causa, ratio. Milan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grossi, P. 1995. L’ordine giuridico medievale. Bari.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janin, H. 2004. Medieval justice: Cases and laws in France, England, and Germany, 500–1500. Jefferson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelley, D. 1976. Vera Philosophia: The philosophical significance of renaissance jurisprudence. Journal of the History of Philosophy 14: 267–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelley, D. 1988. Jurisconsultus Perfectus: The lawyer as Renaissance man. Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes 51: 84–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirshner, J. 1999. Consilia as authority in Late Medieval Italy: The case of Florence. In Legal consulting in the civil law tradition, 107–140. Berkeley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krantz, F. 1971. “Florentine humanist legal thought, 1375–1450”. PhD. Diss., Ithaca.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuehn, T. 2006. The renaissance consilium as justice. Renaissance Quarterly 59: 1058–1088.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langer, U. 1999. The renaissance novella as justice. Renaissance Quarterly 52: 311–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manzin, M. 1994. Il petrarchismo giuridico: Filosofia e logica del diritto agli inizi dell’umanesimo. Padua.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prodi, P. 2000. Una storia della giustizia: Dal pluralismo dei fori al moderno dualismo tra coscienza e diritto. Bologna.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quaglioni, D. 2004. La giustizia nel Medioevo e nella prima età moderna. Bologna.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sbriccoli, M. 2001. Giustizia negoziata, giustizia egemonica: riflessioni su una nuova fase degli studi di storia della giustizia criminale. In Criminalità e giustizia in Germania e Italia: pratiche giudiziarie e linguaggi giuridici tra tardo medioevo et età moderna, ed. Bellabarba, M., G. Schwerhoff, and A. Zorzi, Bologna.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaffern, R. W. 2009. Law and justice from antiquity to enlightenment. Lanham.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaw, James E. 2006. The justice of Venice: Authorities and liberties in the urban economy, 1550–1700. Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vallerani, M. 2012. Medieval public justice. Trans. S. R. Blanshei. Washington, DC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zorzi, A. 1994. The judicial system in Florence in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries. In Crime, society and the law in renaissance Italy, ed. Dean, T. and K. J. P. Lowe, 40–58. Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas J. Kuehn .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Section Editor information

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this entry

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this entry

Kuehn, T.J. (2022). Justice in Renaissance Philosophy. In: Sgarbi, M. (eds) Encyclopedia of Renaissance Philosophy. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-14169-5_201

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics