Skip to main content

Perceiving

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Aristotle's Theory of Abstraction

Part of the book series: The New Synthese Historical Library ((SYNL,volume 73))

  • 907 Accesses

Abstract

In an act of perceiving the attributes of the substance are abstracted from it. Likewise sense organs have abstract functions: an eyeball sees not qua eye but qua seeing; it feels the eyelash not qua seeing but qua touching.

The properties special to a particular sense are all accidents of their substances: the shapes and colors of seeing; the sounds of hearing etc. When they are in the relation of perceiving, they are relata abstracted from these accidents and are not fully determinate. What is perceived represents the attributes of the substance but not in a perfect reflection.

Common perceptibles like shape and motion are perceived through the special sense organs but in another capacity: an eyeball perceives motion not in virtue of the visual sense but in virtue of the common sense . They are perceived per accidens but not fallaciously so. Common perceptibles like motion are constructed by both abstracting and then combining perceptions. Aristotle allows for error in perceiving, less so with special perceptibles than with the common ones; more so in perceiving per accidens than in perceiving per se. He recognizes two sorts of per accidens perception : one where the special perceptibles are used in constructing the common perceptibles , like motion ; the other based on collateral information, as with identifying the hooded man as the son of Diares. The fallacy of accident can come about typically in the latter case.

Perceptions provide the material from which universal concepts are abstracted. Universals exist in re; science is of these universals.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    So too Block 1961a: 2, 1988: 235–49.

  2. 2.

    On the meaning of Hamlyn (1961: 28) says that Aristotle was “on the verge” of making this distinction, which has been embraced today by those like Humphrey (1999). So too Kahn 1992: 364.

  3. 3.

    Also we moderns at least can then talk of plants having a sort of perception too, as they do respond to external stimuli with, say, increased cellular activity at the root cells that have come into contact with a higher concentration of water molecules.

  4. 4.

    Still, for stylistic reasons, I shall use ‘sense organ ’ instead of ‘organ of perception’ etc.

  5. 5.

    See Sorabji 1974: 162 for a general survey of interpretations of Aristotle’s theory of perception. Some, like Slakey , take perception as physiological [what Everson (1997) calls the literalist view]; others, like Solmsen , take it as purely not physical [Everson ’s spiritualist view]. Sorabji (1974: 167–8, 175) himself tends to side with the latter, as he takes perception itself to have a matter and a form, where the former is physical and the latter is not.

  6. 6.

    Cf. (ps.) Simplicius , in de An. 190, 14–5; Plotinus , Enneads IV.4.23.26–7. In the case of sight or touch, the organ is a part of the body relative to some determinate function.

  7. 7.

    Cf. Ross 1956: 267 on 424b17–8 (which has many possible translations!).

  8. 8.

    See Caston 2005: 245–7 for a discussion of the dispute between Sorabji and Burnyeat .

  9. 9.

    So too Caston 2005: 299.

  10. 10.

    Reeve (2000: 149 ff.) juxtaposes these two accounts. He agrees with Burnyeat that the eye jelly becomes proto-colored and then the person sees color (Reeve 2000: 153). Still he then sides with Sorabji that these two differ and says that the “eye jelly is the hypothetically necessary matter of an organ whose form is seeing, and its taking on a proto-color constitutes, but is not identical to, seeing” (Reeve 2000: 156).

  11. 11.

    This is the main flaw in Burnyeat ’s example that Aristotle views the perception of red to occur in the eyeball in the same way water in a glass takes on the color of a nearby red object. See Burnyeat 1992b: 425–7. (This is an English translation of a paper first published in French in Revue philsophique de la France de I ‘Étranger, Vol. 118 [1993] and, with corrections, in Études sur le de Anima d’Aristote, ed. G. Dherbey (Paris, 1995), and earliest in Revista latinamerica de philosofia, Vol. 20 1994.)

  12. 12.

    “…the eye ’s becoming aware of red does not require its going red…” (Nussbaum and Putnam 1992: 36).

  13. 13.

    Apparently these harmonies reflect the ratios of the lengths of the strings being plucked. [Sens. 439b25–449a6]

  14. 14.

    Thus Aristotle explains that plants do not perceive because their organs receive the forms of external objects with their matter, and not apart from it.

  15. 15.

    Cf. Simplicius , in Phys 414, 21–28 [also 493, 21], on whether energeia and entelechia are the same: not if ‘entelechy’ means ‘completion’. He cites Alexander , 412, 29–33: “…it is said to be an entelechy in virtue of this so far as the actuality in virtue of it is a completion of what is in potency, just as in the case of states the actuality in virtue of it is the completion of the state.”

  16. 16.

    Also cf. Physics. I.1 (discussed below) where Aristotle says that a child first perceives a general image before a singular one.

  17. 17.

    Themistius , in De An. 57, 4: “the forms of the perceptibles and the accounts () without the matter”. So too Everson 1997: 101. Summers (1987: 27) concurs that the particulars called up by imagination “…were, of course, the “forms” of particulars at the first level of abstraction from external sense. They were not, however, sufficiently abstracted to be the “universals” subject to the activity of intellect.”

  18. 18.

    Bolton (2005: 221) claims that we do perceive objects [substances?] too—but all he seems to mean by this is that animals can experience them “without intellection” [without rational activity?].

  19. 19.

    Cf. Everson 1997: 117–23 on perception as a relation . He concurs that the correlative of ‘perception’ is ‘the perceptible’, and not the objects proper to each sense.

  20. 20.

    Cf. (ps.) Simplicius , in de An. 262, 1–2: “For if it is not at some distance or if some other passion does not prevent, it is always true of the proper perceptibles.”

  21. 21.

    On this notation see the “Relata as Paronyms” section. So too Graeser 1978: 73. He rightly wonders why then are not perceptual judgments like ‘the white is Socrates ’ objectionable for Aristotle, as they seem to be unnatural predications (Graeser 1978: 74–6).

  22. 22.

    The translation of “form” seems to be following, e.g., (ps.) Simplicius , in De An. 167, 6–9: “For, even when the body is heated, the admission of the form is not in virtue of being heated but in virtue of operating cognitively in virtue of the form of the hot, since the organ as heated is perceptible but does not come to be perceptive.” For instance suppose hot honey is put on the tongue. The tongue itself senses the heat and the sweet but not in virtue of the same sense organ . The point here would be that the tongue insofar as it is the part of the body that is being heated and having something sweet adhere to it, is not the sense organ but just a body that is able to be perceived in these two different ways, of feeling and tasting.

  23. 23.

    Cf. Pichter 1992: 380; Block 1960: 93: “But one question that persistently plagued modern philosophy was never explicitly discussed by Aristotle, namely how and in what manner we perceive or come to be aware of the concrete, physical objects to which sense-qualities belong.”

  24. 24.

    (Ps.) Simplicius , in De An. 227, 36–7: “…but at the same time that he is calling forms not the accidents (for the perceptive soul is receptive of these) but those essences that are per se or completely of themselves insofar as being defined per se they are essential.”

  25. 25.

    ‘Body’ might be taken to signify the substance but more likely signifies the common perceptible , itself accidental (Lewis 1991: 286–7).

  26. 26.

    Cf. (ps.) Simplicius , in De An., 183, 34–5.

  27. 27.

    Kahn claims to be following Geach .

  28. 28.

    Cf. Ward 1988: 220–1 on 424a20–21.

  29. 29.

    Caston (1998: 268) likewise says that perceiving “is just to receive a certain transformation of the form, where the key aspects of that form are preserved.” Cf. Caston 1998: 249; 263. However he says to ignore the difference of the impression of the ring (Caston 2005: 301, n. 110).

  30. 30.

    Hamlyn (1968: xvii, 88) finds that Aristotle uses “” ambiguously between the sensation and the sense, just as ‘perception is the perception of something’ would exemplify.

  31. 31.

    Cf. Phys. 201b2–5; (ps.) Simplicius (in Phys. 425, 31–4) says that the visible is a relatum , while color is not but is per se. Rather color is a proprium of color. Color is not visible in virtue of the fact that it is color.

  32. 32.

    Broadie (1993: 152) notes a possible exception: “…a strong-smelling substance can make the air around it smell the same, and he says that the substance has this effect by virtue of its smell even though smell perception does not result. Unfortunately Aristotle deals with this very cursorily.”

  33. 33.

    The problem of constructing a common perceptible from particular sense perceptions is today called the binding problem. Cf. Horgan 1999: 23; Hubel 1988: 220.

  34. 34.

    Moreover if the objects of mathematics are common perceptibles , their perception need not agree with any of the proper perceptions: Aristotle says that a mathematical line is not a perceived line.

  35. 35.

    Cf. Hamlyn 1968: 199: “What he is seeking is something like the fiction of a unity of consciousness per Kant’s synthetic unity of apperception, as has been frequently enough suggested.”—but has only the unity of sense perception (Hamlyn 1968: 208).

  36. 36.

    Contra Modrak (1987: 64). The perception of shape involves for Aristotle mentally “moving” about the colored regions so as to trace it and so perhaps involves time too. Cf. Hamlyn 1968: 118.

  37. 37.

    Contra Everson (1997: 150), who says, “The common sensibles are not such as to affect those [sense] organs…” I can agree to this only in virtue of the proper senses. He himself admits that “what are directly perceived are change and continuity in the proper sensibles.” But these are types of motion , a common perceptible .

  38. 38.

    However, Bynum (1987: 97) claims that for Aristotle, the sense organ for touch or taste is “the region of the heart that he says contains the sensus communis.” On the heart cf. Hamlyn 1968: 117; Everson 1997: 156, n. 29.

  39. 39.

    E.g., Hamlyn 1968: 117. Kahn (1966: 67) and Kosman (1975) somewhat have the view of the common sense as “a single, unified sense faculty, of which the individual senses are so many diverse modes or aspects.” Still some despair: Sorabji 1972: 75.

  40. 40.

    Aristotle does not seem committed to claiming that the common perceptibles are all perceived by all the senses. He says for instance that they are perceived mostly by sight. Cf. Hamlyn 1968: 204: “Rather the koine aisthesis is a potentiality possessed by each of the individual sense-organs, or at least by that of sight and touch.”

  41. 41.

    Likewise in the Categories Aristotle speaks of propria , both special and common ones. E.g., 4a10; it is in this way that we should understand at 418a24–5: of the two sorts of per se perceptibles , the special ones are the special propria , while the common ones are propria not in the strict sense—not deny, with Everson (1997: 153) that common perceptibles are not the proper objects of the special senses, although perceived per se by them. See too Graeser 1978: 69–70, 79, 85–9.

  42. 42.

    E.g., Graeser (1978: 81) has the conjunctive reading; Brunschwig (1996: 217) the disjunctive.

  43. 43.

    Or, perhaps: all those able to do so: for locomotion or shape might be not able to be tasted etc.

  44. 44.

    Cf. Brunschwig 1991: 455–74.

  45. 45.

    At Sens. 437a8–9 Aristotle suggests that not all the special senses provide perceptions of the common perceptibles ; rather sight does so preeminently. See Everson 1997: 152–3, 155. Charles (2000: 127–8) agrees that the common perceptibles are perceived via the sense organs of the proper senses.

  46. 46.

    In On Dreams 458a15–6 Aristotle says that we seem to see that the approaching figure is white and is a man. However the context has it that this is what we seem to do. It’s just that sense perception is necessary for us to form that belief.

  47. 47.

    See below on the fallacy of accident .

  48. 48.

    Hence we get the doctrine of per se accidents . [Metaph. 997a7; 1025a30–5; 1029b16–23; Simplicius , in Phys. 803, 9–16] Cf. D. Frede 1992: 151.

  49. 49.

    Although there are many interpretations of the passage. Cf. Hamlyn 1968: 118–20.

  50. 50.

    “But if Aristotle’s description of perceptual consciousness as perception that we perceive still seems strange, consider the following [from Moore 1903: 449–50]: “A sensation is, in reality, a case of ‘knowing’ or ‘being aware of’ or ‘experiencing’ something. When we know that the sensation of blue exists, the fact we know is that there exists an awareness of blue…. To be aware of the sensation of blue … is to be aware of an awareness of blue; awareness being used, in both cases, in exactly the same sense.”” (Kosman 1975: 517).

  51. 51.

    Block (1964: 61), on Somno 455b 1–14, stresses the relative independence of the common sense from the special senses. (Ps.) Simplicius (in de An. 172, 20–3; 171, 1–7) offers another explanation, that rational animals can perceive that they perceive and so ties that ability to the rationality of the perceiving animal (rather like Kant).

  52. 52.

    Cf. Everson 1997: 68, 140–2.

  53. 53.

    “It is that the De Anima is an incomplete and immature working-out of Aristotle’s views on sense perception, whereas Aristotle’s matured and crystallized views on this subject are to be sought in the Parva Naturalia…” (Block 1964: 58). Cf. Block 1961b. Likewise, Modrak (1987: 66–7) claims that Aristotle has a different account of the common sense in Somno and An. with respect to what is that in virtue of which a sense is aware of its own activity: in Somno 455a13 it is the common sense and in An. II.2 the sense itself. Cf. her n. 31 where she suggests that Aristotle might be considering different cases here. So too (ps.) Simplicius (in de An. 191, 7–8) says that Book III is about human perception unlike the previous books of De Anima.

  54. 54.

    Thus Gregorić (2007: 125) says that Aristotle does not have a technical or a single meaning for ‘common sense ’.

  55. 55.

    My interpretation does not conflict with Everson ’s claim that perceptibles are per se because they are the per se causes of changes in the sense organs. See Everson 1997: 155–7.

  56. 56.

    Consider ‘facet’ as ‘face-t’, a certain respect or façade of the object. Cf. .

  57. 57.

    In one sense, ‘(a) body’ signifies a substance; in another a quantum . Here it signifies a common perceptible as discussed above. In any case, it is still not the correlative of the visibly perceptible etc.

  58. 58.

    Cf. Caston 2005: 309.

  59. 59.

    Cf. Slakey 1961: 84; Nuyens 1948.

  60. 60.

    Just as with the Stoic example of a top, whose shape affects the nature of its motion when spun.

  61. 61.

    “Aristotle holds perception to be a certain physical process, wherein certain perceptual or cognitive abilities of an organ of the body are actualized” (Burnyeat 1992a: 26). So too Everson 1997: 229; Slakey 1990: 77: “Perception is simply the movement which occurs in the sense organs, not some psychic process in addition to the movement in the organs.” Slakey (1990: 82–3) then claims that Aristotle’s theory of perception fails, as it cannot distinguish between say smelling and becoming odorous. Yet perception cannot be reduced to a purely material process: the formal, structural features themselves are not material constituents. Cf. Metaph. VII.3; Part. An. I.1; Sorabji 1974: 175.

    Still, we should not neglect how much for Aristotle perception is a physical, or, better, a physiological, dynamic process, and not a conscious one. When we discuss sense perception, we tend to be speaking of the experience of it, especially since we human beings do have the experience (in Aristotle’s sense too) and the consciousness of the perception as well as the perceptions themselves. Aristotle himself makes this distinction at 425b12–3; 425b20. Cf. Bynum 1987: 92.

  62. 62.

    Cf. Modrak 1987: 39.

  63. 63.

    Still cf. Tht. 156a-157a, where Plato mentions the view that things perceived like the white or the hot have no being in themselves but only in the relational complex.

  64. 64.

    As in Resp. X. I do not want to defend this interpretation of Plato in detail, but just to make the contrast with Aristotle.

  65. 65.

    Still I can agree with Kahn (1992: 367) that only singulars are perceived, strictly speaking.

  66. 66.

    More about noûs below.

  67. 67.

    Cf. Bolton 1996: 303.

  68. 68.

    Following Kant’s similar remark about Hume ’s analysis of causality: the same grounds on which Hume rejects a rational basis for claims about causality apply equally well to claims about substance.

  69. 69.

    Perhaps thus (ps.) Simplicius , in de An. 190, 26 when he speaks of “types” () being presented to the imagination by the sense organ .

  70. 70.

    Themistius (in De An., 58, 11–4) refers to Cat. 7a35 on “stripping away” all the accidental attributes. Cf. Avicenna , Al-Burhān 160, 12–20.

  71. 71.

    Most scholars today do seem to accept individual accidents (Frede 1987). Corkum (2008: 87, n. 20) gives a survey of secondary literature on whether individual accidents are non-recurrent or recurrent. Plato , Tht. 209c6 speaks of the snubness of the nose of Theaetetus differing from the snubnesses of other noses.

  72. 72.

    I leave it open here whether there are individual items of intelligible substances, and, if so, of what sort, and how we come to be acquainted with them. As I have discussed a bit above, in ‘2 + 2 = 4’, we have two instances of the number two. Aristotle may take these as “individuals”; witness his doctrine of intelligible matter at Metaph. 1036a2–12; 1059b14–6.

  73. 73.

    (Ps.) Simplicius , in De An. 182, 1–2: “substance is apprehended by reason and not by perception.”

  74. 74.

    (Ps.) Simplicius , in De An., 127, 32–128, 2: “…just as we say that the master and the sculpture is a man per accidens because he is so not qua man. Thus in this way substance is perceptible per accidens, because not in virtue of being substance.”

  75. 75.

    Hence the talk of ratios. Cf. Ward 1988: 220–1 on 424a20–21.

  76. 76.

    So too Modrak 1987: 89; Robinson (1989: 69, n. 8) holds that the eikon must resemble things only in some respect.

    I leave it open whether Aristotle requires a perception to have a perceiver “becoming aware of some sensible quality in the environment: [the “spiritualist” interpretation] or just that “the [sense] organ is so altered that it literally becomes like its (proper object” [the “literalist” interpretation]; so Everson 1997: 10–1. I admit that I am inclined to the literalist one, at least for the perceptions of animals like grubs. Indeed, I have been using ‘perceive’ and its cognates instead of ‘sense’ for this reason. Note that, on either interpretation, the reproduction of the form of the object being perceived need not be identical but only “like”.

  77. 77.

    Everson (1997: 187–8) likewise suggests that we ought not take per se perception as perceiving the proper object (seeing the color) and per accidens perception as having propositional content (seeing that the red thing is an apple).

  78. 78.

    Charles (2000: 123–4) agrees that Aristotle allows for error even of the proper perceptibles. Robinson (1989: 67) says, “To the extent that the percipient reports only this bare sensation, he cannot be wrong”—e.g., in reporting an ache, a flash of light, or a drumbeat. Yet this doesn’t help much: for now we have a self-conscious report applying linguistic expressions to the past perception. Surely all this goes far beyond the per se perception itself. Cf. (ps.) Simplicius , in de An., 261, 35–262, 10.

  79. 79.

    But then (ps.) Simplicius , in De An., 126, 37–127, 8.

  80. 80.

    As noted above, such too is, or at any rate has been, the presumption in modern psychological studies of perception. However, see Charles 2000: 121–2, n. 19 on what Aristotle requires for a sense organ to be “functioning well”.

  81. 81.

    Thus Graeser (1978: 86) says that for Aristotle error and falsity only if there is synthesis .

  82. 82.

    There are many variants of the text here, but these do not affect the doctrine that I am presenting.

  83. 83.

    Hamlyn (1961: 26–7, 1968: 106) discusses how sense can err and in what way there cannot: “a sense cannot confuse its object with that of another sense; it can err over the identity and place of the material object which possesses the quality in question. It can also err over instances of its type of object.” He admits that the incorrigibility here is puzzling.

  84. 84.

    This text has some variants and alternate readings.

  85. 85.

    Modrak (2001: 233, 236) makes a similar point about imagination . Re incidental sensibles, see Bernard 1988: 75–86; Madden 2004: 47–8. In seeing the color, the eye cannot help but to “register” some colored object, sc., the substance. This is an incidental perception but somewhat reliable.

  86. 86.

    Barnes 1994: 255. “If we were often mistaken in perceiving physical objects per se Aristotle could not say that the eye ’s perception of colored objects is always true. However, Aristotle says that the objects of indirect perception are often false (428b20), therefore physical objects cannot be objects of indirect perception” (Block 1960: 97).

  87. 87.

    I do not mean that a sense perception of a red circle suffices to give scientific knowledge of redness or circles, but only materials from which such knowledge can be constructed. Actually, Aristotle generally says that color is the proper object of sight. [418a27 et passim; cf. Top. 119a30] Yet the shape too seems likely; cf. 425b6–9. It’s just that no other sense besides sight perceives color, and so here we have a “proper” object in the strict sense of the proprium .

  88. 88.

    At Rhetoric 1370a28 Aristotle says that imagination is weak in getting at the truth, and our apprehension of common perceptibles depends upon imagination … Cf. Themistius , in De An. 90, 8–13; 91, 18.

  89. 89.

    “Vision is the process of extracting from two-dimensional images information about the three-dimensional structure of the world” (Egan 1996: 232). Still, as Charles (2000: 127) notes, what we immediately perceive are “cross-modal, three-dimensional objects typically grasped by the senses working in tandem.” We, like Aristotle, have to work backwards, to separate, distinct principles .

  90. 90.

    Cf. Ross 1955: 273–4 on the finger example in psychology.

  91. 91.

    Perhaps Aristotle takes this basic discriminative sense to coming from the linkage of the proper sense organs with the region around the heart via the blood and its ducts. Narcy (1996: 252) says that Aristotle is reacting to the doctrines of Protagoras and Plato at Tht., 189e-190a; Soph. 263e.

  92. 92.

    Cf. his account of the brutish, whose attributes are produced by disease or deformity. [Eth. Nic. 1145a30–3; also Metaph. 1010b6–11 on the erroneous perceptions of the weak and the sleeping and of those perceiving distant objects]

  93. 93.

    Everson (1997: 188–91, 39, 45) takes 418a20–4 causally, to assert: that if x is perceived per accidens by s, then “x is an accidental cause of s’s perceiving some proper sensible.”

  94. 94.

    Lorenz (1963: 26) reports that jackdaws are taught by their elders about friends or foes. The elder birds have more experience. The type of “memory ’ here need not require deliberation, intentionality, or reasoning. [Mem. 450a15–6] Rather, it is a process of the concatenation of movements of the various sense perceptions in the soul . Recollection , on the other hand, requires reasoning, as the one seeking to recollect constructs a sort of syllogism, and so must deliberate and think about what she is doing. [453a8–14] Cf. Robinson 1989: 72–3; Sorabji 1972.

  95. 95.

    “Aristotle’s treatment of accidental perception in the DA and the De Sensu is no more than cursory—so cursory, in fact, that it would not be too hopeful to maintain that he provides any theory of accidental perception in those works” (Everson 1997: 192).

  96. 96.

    It is worth noting that, while Aristotle himself does not have the clearest or most regular terminology, the English translations add to the confusion: both the special and the common perceptibles are “proper” perceptibles, even though strictly speaking only the former are perceived in virtue of the special senses. (Ross 1956: 270 discusses the problems with the manuscripts.) The common perceptibles are still “proper” perceptibles, in the sense of propria : some of them necessarily accompany the special perceptibles : we see no color without a shape. Note that some of the common perceptibles may be “proper” in the second sense of ‘per se’ given in An. Po. I.4: this gives the disjunctive reading discussed above.

  97. 97.

    I shall assume for the sake of the example that Coriscus is the son of Diares: in fact probably not. See Ross 1955: 238–9.

  98. 98.

    “…notons la construction et son sens : “fils de Diarès” sujet de la phrase mais sans article, est accident, et “1e blanc”, datif complement avec article, est sujet au sens de suppôt des accidents” (Cassin 1996: 284).

  99. 99.

    That is, from the point of view of the perceiver, the connection is accidental. It might be essential to a son to have the father that he does.

  100. 100.

    Not via one special sense, like touch, perceiving a perceptible of another sense, as in feeling a red patch. Cf. Brunschwig 1996: 215. He distinguishes “…deux sortes de perception par accident, celle d’un koinon par un sens spécial et celle d’un idion par un sens spécial autre que le sien. Cette tentative, je l’avoue, me paraît acrobatique.”

  101. 101.

    Still, Themistius , in De An., 81, 32–5: “for the son of Cleon is not knowable from the color but also from many other things which it was not of a single perception to compose and examine, but is thereby perhaps of another, worthier power that the arational animals do not have in common.”

  102. 102.

    Cf. the definition of motion at Physics 201a10–2 discussed above. Also in An. I.3 when discussing perception Aristotle alludes to his theory of the movement of animals. Perception would be automatic too.

  103. 103.

    Wedin ’s account of per accidens perception also suggests this (Wedin 1988: 94, 205–6).

  104. 104.

    See Themistius , in De An. 81, 35–82, 14 on various modes of perceiving per accidens

  105. 105.

    Bäck 2000: 65–74 discusses being per se and per accidens.

  106. 106.

    On the role of memory in per accidens perception cf. Weidmann 2001: 98–101.

  107. 107.

    Graeser (1978: 90) notes that some cases of ‘seeing as’ are genuine; cf. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations II.19. So too Michon 2001: 328–9; Wedin 1988: 94; Hamlyn 1976: 176; Barnes 1975: 266.

  108. 108.

    Aristotle does not make it entirely clear whether the proper correlates are ‘perceived’ and ‘seen’ or ‘perceivable’ or ‘visible’. His theory might suggest the former, but his discussion at 7b35–8a12 suggests the latter.

  109. 109.

    At best, a common perceptible will make reference to the proper perceptibles per se in the second sense of ‘per se’ distinguished at 73a37–b1, as a number is even “per se”, because the predicate ‘even’ makes reference to the subject in its definition—if it is true that a common perceptible is by definition visible or audible or gustative or olfactive or tangible.

  110. 110.

    Cashdollar (1973: 162) errs when he claims that the typical case of per accidens predication reverses the usual order of subject and predicate. For, in any case, per se perception does that too. Per se versus per accidens perception is not the same as per se versus per accidens predication!

  111. 111.

    A case can be made for items in other categories: e.g., via motion we can perceive such positions as sitting, whereas like being on top of (as with one color on top of another), perhaps some relations, including those of position and having and possibly perception itself, given a very strong interpretation of Aristotle’s claim that we perceive that we perceive. Aristotle works little of this out for us—and it would be quite involved.

  112. 112.

    Below I discuss how we can come to know individual substances etc. at all. Here I suppose that we know them somehow, as we seem to and as Aristotle seems to assume too.

  113. 113.

    On the practical syllogism , cf. Nussbaum 1978: 165 ff.

  114. 114.

    Or, to avoid the appearance of an ‘I’ of self-consciousness : There is an ear of corn and hunger pains…

  115. 115.

    So too in modern homomorphic theories of perception. Cf. Rosenthal 2005 where qualitative states, representing and caused by real structures of the objects perceived, need not be conscious.

  116. 116.

    In contrast, Nussbaum 1978: 259. As Everson (1997: 159) says, she holds that “…the capacities of perception and phantasia play a complementary role: the activity of perception is to register the proper sensibles whilst that of phantasia is to interpret the information received in perception, allowing the subject to discriminate substances as such and act on them.”

  117. 117.

    Everson (1997: 164–6) himself seems to make this distinction (cf. Schofield 1978: 113). He does say “Actions, then, do not require the agent to be able to interpret his perceptions so as to recognize the accidental sensibles…” (Everson 1997: 165).

  118. 118.

    Harte (2006: 25) finds the distinction already in Plato .

References

  • Akins, K. (Ed.). (1996). Perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avicenna. (1956). In A. Affifi (Ed.), Al-Burhān, aš-Šifa’ (Vol. I.4). Cairo: Organisme General des Imprimeries Gouvernementales.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avicenna. (1975). In G. C. Anawati & S. Zayed (Eds.), Fī Nafs, aš-Šhifa’ (Vol. II.1). Cairo: Organisme General des Imprimeries Gouvernementales.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bäck, A. (2000). Aristotle’s theory of predication. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bäck, A. (2009). Mistakes of reason. Phronesis, 54(2), 101–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bäck, A. (forthcoming). How the fallacy of accident got its name. In P. Pérez-Ilzarbe & M. Cerezo (Ed.), Studies in the history of logic: A volume in honour of Angel d’Ors. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, J. (Trans. & Comm.). (1975). Aristotle: Posterior analytics (1st ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. [2nd ed. 1994, Oxford: Oxford University Press.]

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernard, W. (1988). Rezeptivität und Spontaneität der Wahrnehmung bei Aristoteles. BadenBaden: V. Koerner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, I. (1960). Aristotle and the physical object. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 21(1), 93–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, I. (1961a). Truth and error in Aristotle’s theory of sense perception. The Philosophical Quarterly, 11(42), 1–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, I. (1961b). The order of Aristotle’s psychological writings. The American Journal of Philology, 82(1), 50–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, I. (1964). Three German commentators on the individual senses and the common sense in Aristotle’s psychology. Phronesis, 9(1), 58–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, I. L. (1988). Aristotle on the common sense: Reply to Kahn and others. Ancient Philosophy, 8(2), 235–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolton, R. (1996). Scepticisme et véracité dans le De Anima et La Métaphysique d’Aristote. In G. Romeyer-Dherbey & C. Viano (Eds.), Corps et Âme: sur le De Anima D’Aristote (pp. 295–330). Paris: J. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolton, R. (2005). Perception naturalized in Aristotle’s De Anima. In R. Salles (Ed.), Metaphysics, soul and ethics in ancient thought (pp. 209–244). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broadie, S. (1993). Aristotle’s perceptual realism. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 31, 137–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brunschwig, J. (1991). Les multiples chemins aristotéliciens de la sensation commune. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, 96(4), 455–474.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunschwig, J. (1996). En quel sens le sens commun est-il commun? In G. Romeyer Dherbey & C. Viano (Eds.), Corps et Âme: sur le De Anima D’Aristote (pp. 189–218). Paris: J. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnyeat, M. (1991). From Aristotle to Brentano: The development of the concept of intentionality. In H. Blumenthal & H. Robinson (Eds.), Aristotle and the later tradition (Oxford studies in ancient philosophy, Suppl Vol. 9, pp. 227–259).

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnyeat, M. (1992a). Is an Aristotelian theory of mind still credible? In M. C. Nussbaum & A. O. Rorty (Eds.), Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima (pp. 15–26). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnyeat, M. (1992b). Remarks on De Anima 2. 7–8. In M. Nussbaum & A. Rorty (Eds.), Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima (pp. 425–427). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnyeat, M. (2002). ‘De Anima’ II 5. Phronesis, 47(1), 28–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bynum, T. (1987). A new look at Aristotle’s theory of perception. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 4(2), 163–178. (Reprinted from Aristotle’s De Anima in focus, by M. Durrant, Ed., 1993, London: Taylor and Francis).

    Google Scholar 

  • Cashdollar, S. (1973). Aristotle’s account of incidental perception. Phronesis, 18(1), 156–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cassin, B. (1996). Enquête sur le logos dans le De Anima. In G. Romeyer Dherbey & C. Viano (Eds.), Corps et Âme: sur le De Anima D’Aristote (pp. 257–293). Paris: J. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caston, V. (1998). Aristotle and the problem of intentionality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58(2), 249–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caston, V. (2002). Aristotle on consciousness. Mind, 111, 751–815.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caston, V. (2005). The spirit and the letter: Aristotle on perception. In R. Salles (Ed.), Metaphysics, soul, and ethics in ancient thought (pp. 245–320). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charles, D. (2000). Aristotle on meaning and essence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charlton, W. (1980). Aristotle’s definition of soul. Phronesis, 25(2), 170–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charlton, W. (1981). Telling the difference between sweet and pale. Apeiron, 15(2), 103–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cleary, J. (1995). Aristotle and mathematics: Aporetic method in cosmology & Metaphysics. Leiden: E.J. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. M. (1992). Hylomorphism and functionalism. In M. C. Nussbaum & A. O. Rorty (Eds.), Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima (pp. 57–74). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corkum, P. (2008). Aristotle on ontological dependence. Phronesis, 53(1), 65–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ebert, T. (1983). Aristotle on what is done in perceiving. Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung, 37(2), 181–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, F. (1996). Intentionality and the theory of vision. In K. Akins (Ed.), Perception (pp. 232–247). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Everson, S. (1997). Aristotle on perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frede, M. (1987). Individuals in Aristotle. In Essays in ancient philosophy (pp. 49–71). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frede, D. (1992). The cognitive role of Phantasia in Aristotle. In M. C. Nussbaum & A. O. Rorty (Eds.), Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima (pp. 279–298). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frede, M. (1996). La théorie Aristotelicienne de l’intellect agent. In G. Romeyer Dherbey & C. Viano (Eds.), Corps et Âme: sur le De Anima D’Aristote (pp. 377–390). Paris: J. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graeser, A. (1978). On Aristotle’s framework of Sensibilia. In G. E. R. Lloyd & G. E. L. Owen (Eds.), Aristotle on mind and the senses (pp. 69–98). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Granger, H. (1993). Aristotle and perceptual realism. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 31(Suppl), 161–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregorić, P. (2007). Aristotle on the common sense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hamlyn, D. W. (1959). Aristotle’s account of aesthesis in the De Anima. Classical Quarterly, 9, 6–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamlyn, D. W. (1961). Sensation and perception. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamlyn, D. W. (1968). Koine Aisthesis. The Monist, 52(2), 195–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamlyn, D. W. (Ed. & Trans.). (1968). Aristotle’s De Anima: Books II and II. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamlyn, D. W. (1976). Aristotelian epagoge. Phronesis, 21(2), 167–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harte, V. (2006). Beware of intuitions: Image recognition in Plato. In F.-G. Herrmann (Ed.), New essays on Plato (pp. 21–42). Swansea: The Classical Press of Wales.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, J. (1999). The undiscovered mind. New York: Touchstone.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hubel, D. (1988). Eye, brain and vision. New York: W.H. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphrey, N. (1999). A short history of mind. New York: Copernicus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johansen, T. K. (2012). The powers of Aristotle’s soul. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kahn, C. H. (1966). Sensation and consciousness in Aristotle’s psychology. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 48(1–3), 43–81. (Reprinted from Essays on Aristotle, Vol. 4, pp. 43–81, by J. Barnes, M. Schofield, & R. Sorabji, Eds., 1979, London: Duckworth).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahn, C. (1992). Aristotle on thinking. In M. C. Nussbaum & A. O. Rorty (Eds.), Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima (pp. 359–380). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kosman, L. A. (1975). Perceiving that we perceive: On the soul III. Philosophical Review, 84(4), 499–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, F. A. (1991). Substance and predication in Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz, K. (1963). On aggression. New York: University Paperbacks.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz, H. (2007). The assimilation of sense to sense object in Aristotle. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 33, 179–220.

    Google Scholar 

  • Madden, J. D. (2004). Aristotle, induction, and first principles. International Philosophical Quarterly, 44(1), 35–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michon, C. (2001). Intentionality and proto-thoughts. In D. Perler (Ed.), Ancient and medieval theories of intentionality (pp. 325–342). Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Modrak, D. K. W. (1987). Aristotle: The power of perception. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Modrak, D. K. W. (2001). Aristotle’s theory of language and meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1903). The refutation of idealism. Mind, 12(48), 433–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moravcsik, J. M. E. (1974). Aristotle on adequate explanations. Synthese, 28(1), 3–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moravcsik, J. M. E. (1975). Aitia as generative factor in Aristotle’s philosophy. Dialogue, 14(4), 622–638.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Narcy, M. (1996). . In G. Romeyer Dherbey & C. Viano (Eds.), Corps et Âme: sur le De Anima D’Aristote (pp. 391–404). Paris: J. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (1978). Aristotle’s De Motu Animalium. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M., & Putnam, H. (1992). Changing Aristotle’s mind. In M. C. Nussbaum & A. O. Rorty (Eds.), Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima (pp. 27–56). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nuyens, F. (1948). L’Évolution de la psychologie d’Aristote. Louvain: La Haye.

    Google Scholar 

  • Owen, G. E. L. (1965). Inherence. Phronesis, 10(1), 97–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Philoponus. (1991). On Aristotle on the intellect. (W. Charlton, & F. Bossier, Trans.). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pichter, G. (1992). Aristotles’ De Anima (2nd ed.). Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porphyry. (1887). In A. Busse (Ed.), Aristotelis Categorias Commentarium (Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca, Vol. 4.1). Berlin: Reimer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge: The Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rapp, C. (2001). Intentionalität und Phantasia bei Aristotles. In D. Perler (Ed.), Ancient and medieval theories of intentionality (pp. 63–96). Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reeve, C. D. C. (2000). Substantial knowledge: Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. Burnyeat, M. (1992). Remarks on De Anima, 2, (7–8). In M. C. Nussbaum, & A. O. Rorty (Eds.), Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima (pp. 27–56). New York: Oxford University Press. (This is an English translation of a paper first published in French in Revue philsophique de la France de I‘Étranger, Vol. 118 [1993] and, with corrections, in Études sur le de Anima d’Aristote, ed. G. Dherbey (Paris, 1995), and earliest in Revista latinamerica de philosofia, Vol. 20 1994).

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, D. N. (1989). Aristotle’s psychology. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. (2005). Consciousness and mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (Ed. & Comm.). (1955). Aristotle’s Parva Naturalia. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (Ed. & Comm.). (1956). Aristotle: De Anima. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheiter, K. M. (2012). Images, appearances, and phantasia in Aristotle. Phronesis, 57, 251–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, M. (1978). Aristotle on the imagination. In G. E. R. Lloyd & G. E. L. Owen (Eds.), Aristotle on the mind and the senses (pp. 99–141). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, M. (1992). Aristotle on the imagination. In M. C. Nussbaum & A. O. Rorty (Eds.), Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima (pp. 249–278). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silverman, A. (1989). Color and color-perception in Aristotle’s De Anima. Ancient Philosophy, 9(2), 271–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simplicius. (1907). In C. Kalbfleisch (Ed.), Aristotelis Categorias Commentarium (Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca, Vol. 8). Berlin: Reimer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slakey, T. J. (1961). Aristotle on sense perception. Philosophical Review 70(4), 470–484. (Reprinted from Aristotle’s De Anima in focus, by M. Durrant, Ed., 1993, London: Taylor and Francis).

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorabji, R. (1971). Aristotle on demarcating the five senses. The Philosophical Review, 80(1), 55–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sorabji, R. (1972). Aristotle on memory. London: Duckworth; (2nd ed., Chicago, 2006).

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorabji, R. (1974). Body and soul in Aristotle. Philosophy 49(187), 63–89. (Reprinted from Aristotle’s De Anima in focus, by M. Durrant., Ed., 1993, London: Taylor and Francis).

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorabji, R. (1992). Intentionality and physical processes. In M. C. Nussbaum & A. O. Rorty (Eds.), Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima (pp. 195–226). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Summers, D. (1987). The judgement of sense. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tracy, T. J. (1969). Physiological theory and the doctrine of the mean in Plato and Aristotle. Chicago: Loyola University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, J. K. (1988). Perception and Lo¢goV in De Anima II.12. Ancient Philosophy, 8(2), 217–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wedin, M. V. (1988). Mind and imagination in Aristotle. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weidmann, H. (2001). War Aristoteles ein Repräsentationalist? In D. Perler (Ed.), Ancient and medieval theories of intentionality (pp. 97–104). Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bäck, A. (2014). Perceiving. In: Aristotle's Theory of Abstraction. The New Synthese Historical Library, vol 73. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-04759-1_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics