Skip to main content

Aristotle: Life as Self-Creation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Organismal Agency

Part of the book series: Biosemiotics ((BSEM,volume 28))

  • 44 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter focuses on Aristotle’s theory of the four causes and the way Aristotle applies this explicative framework to living beings. Their material cause is the body parts, the functional units from which their bodies are composed. The efficient cause is identified with the father, or rather father’s form (species). In the course of embryogenesis, this cause is internalised and the nascent organism itself becomes the cause of its vital movements, including the movement of self-formation. The formal cause is to be understood dynamically, as a complex of vital movements in which a particular, species-specific manner of life takes place. This form of a living body is its soul, i.e., its propre animation. Thus understood, the form merges with the final cause. Finality, or the aiming at a predefined final state, is characteristic of embryogenesis as the ontogenetic movement which (normally) leads to offspring that resemble their parents, both individually and in terms of species. The final cause of the body parts is the function they have in the body; they develop in order to exercise their vital activities. The whole organism does not serve an external purpose: its finality is to be itself, to fulfil its own form.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Aristotle of course did not call his theories about the realm of the living ‘biology’. That is a modern expression.

  2. 2.

    Translations from PA and GA are taken from Balme (1992); other Aristotelian treatises are quoted according to the revised Oxford translation of Aristotle, i.e., Barnes (1984) and Barnes (1985).

  3. 3.

    The heterogeneity of examples listed here shows that Aristotle’s aim is to formulate a universal theory of causality; causal explanation specifically in biology is addressed in PA I.

  4. 4.

    Aristotle himself does not use the term analogy when speaking about the two ontological domains, but – as becomes apparent below – it is a relatively accurate name for his comparative approach to them.

  5. 5.

    From our perspective, Aristotle’s position may seem to underestimate the role of females, but in the context of contemporary debates it presented a conceptual compromise between, on one side, the two-seed theories (widespread among Hippocratic physicians), which downplay or neglect the differences between the male and female contribution to reproduction, and on the other side, the notion of a ‘mother as a fertile furrow’, according to which the embryo is begotten solely by the father (Lefebvre, 2016).

  6. 6.

    Paradigmatic natural entities are animals, because they are capable of all of the abovementioned movements (plants do not engage in locomotion, and the elements are not the cause of their rest: in the absence of any obstacles, they necessarily move to their proper cosmic places).

  7. 7.

    Cf. Gotthelf, 1987, 207: ‘First, in almost every passage in which Aristotle introduces, discusses, or argues for the existence of final causality, his attention is focused on the generation and development of a living organism.’

  8. 8.

    Let us note that Greek tradition ascribes the origins of craftsmanship to the gods. Moreover, individual input and originality were not (until the Modern Era) something that would be especially appreciated in art and/or production. In this view, there is little space for ‘progress’ or cultural evolution, which corresponds also to the fact that Aristotle does not believe in any biological evolution.

  9. 9.

    Although there are discussions, for instance, about convergent evolution of particular traits in different groups of animals, ‘hard core’ finalists are among current biologists rather an exception. The position according to which any possible rational beings will necessarily look like actual humans is nowadays held basically only by Conway Morris (2003).

References

  • Balme, D. (1987). Aristotle’s biology was not essentialist. In A. Gotthelf & J. Lennox (Eds.), Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology (pp. 291–312). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Balme, D. (1992). Aristotle’s De partibus animalium I and De generatione animalium I. (with passages from II.1–3). Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, J. (Ed.). (1984). Complete works of Aristotle, Volume 1. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, J. (Ed.). (1985). Complete works of Aristotle, Volume 2. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, B. (1992). Ethnobiological classification: Principles of categorization of plants and animals in traditional societies. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Broadie, S. (1987). Nature, craft and Phronesis in Aristotle. Philosophical Topics, 15(2), 35–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Connell, S. (2016). Aristotle on female animals: A study of the generation of animals. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Conway Morris, S. (2003). Life’s solution: Inevitable humans in a lonely universe. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, J. M. (1987). Hypothetical necessity and natural teleology. In A. Gotthelf & J. Lennox (Eds.), Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology (pp. 243–274). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Corcilius, K., & Gregorić, P. (2010). Separability vs. difference: Parts and capacities of the soul in Aristotle. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 39, 81–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham, A. (1999). Aristotle’s animal books: Ethology, biology, anatomy, or philosophy? Philosophical Topics, 27(1), 17–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gotthelf, A. (1987). Aristotle’s conception of final causality. In A. Gotthelf & J. Lennox (Eds.), Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology (pp. 204–242). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gotthelf, A. (1999). Darwin on Aristotle. Journal of the History of Biology, 32(1), 3–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. (2000). Investigations. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lefebvre, D. (2016). Le sperma: forme, matière ou les deux? Philosophie Antique, 16, 31–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lennox, J. (1987). Kinds, forms of kinds, and the more and the less in Aristotle’s biology. In A. Gotthelf & J. Lennox (Eds.), Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology (pp. 339–359). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lennox, J. (1993). Darwin was a Teleologist. Biology and Philosophy, 8, 409–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrin, P. (1986). Aristotle’s classification of animals: Biology and the conceptual Unity of the Aristotelian corpus. University of California Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrin, P. (2011). Introduction. In Aristotle, Les Parties des animaux (pp. 7–79). Flammarion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmieri, G. (2018). Something(s) in the way(s) he moves: Reconsidering the embryological argument for particular forms in Aristotle. In A. Falcon & D. Lefebvre (Eds.), Aristotle’s generation of animals: A critical guide (pp. 188–206). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sedley, D. (2010). Teleology, Aristotelian and platonic. In J. Lennox & R. Bolton (Eds.), Being, nature and life in Aristotle: Essays in honor of Allan Gotthelf (pp. 5–29). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Witt, C. (2015). In defense of the craft analogy: Artifacts and natural teleology. In M. Leunissen (Ed.), Aristotle’s physics: A critical guide (pp. 107–120). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eliška Fulínová .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2024 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Fulínová, E. (2024). Aristotle: Life as Self-Creation. In: Švorcová, J. (eds) Organismal Agency. Biosemiotics, vol 28. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-53626-7_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics