Skip to main content

A Formal Analysis of Hollis’ Paradox

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Logic, Rationality, and Interaction (LORI 2023)

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNCS,volume 14329))

Included in the following conference series:

  • 250 Accesses

Abstract

In Hollis’ paradox, A and B each chose a positive integer and whisper their number to C. C then informs them, jointly, that they have chosen different numbers and, moreover, that neither of them are able to work out who has the greatest number. A then reasons as follows: B cannot have 1, otherwise he would know that my number is greater, and by the same reasoning B knows that I don’t have 1. But then B also cannot have 2, otherwise he would know that my number is greater (since he knows I don’t have 1). This line of reasoning can be repeated indefinitely, effectively forming an inductive proof, ruling out any number – an apparent paradox. In this paper we formalise Hollis’ paradox using public announcement logic, and argue that the root cause of the paradox is the wrongful assumption that A and B assume that C’s announcement necessarily is successful. This resolves the paradox without assuming that C can be untruthful, or that A and B are not perfect reasoners, like other solutions do. There are similarities to the surprise examination paradox. In addition to a semantic analysis in the tradition of epistemic logic, we provide a syntactic one, deriving conclusions from a set of premises describing the initial situation – more in the spirit of the literature on Hollis’ paradox. The latter allows us to pinpoint which assumptions are actually necessary for the conclusions resolving the paradox.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 59.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 74.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Hollis [9] already hints at this assumption: “...each of us has to assume that the other is not stupid...”.

  2. 2.

    Olin [14] claims that it is “a version of surprise examination”; Hollis [10] on the other hand argues that his paradox is “wider”.

  3. 3.

    See [12] for an overview of different variants and a discussion of historic origins.

  4. 4.

    In muddy children, that happens in the last joint announcement by the children.

  5. 5.

    Here and in the following we mean “truthful” in the strong sense that the announcement is in fact true (rather than only believed to be true).

  6. 6.

    If \(\phi \) is, e.g., a primitive proposition, then “was true” is the same as “is true”. However, this is not the case in general: it could be that \(\phi \) was true in a certain state before the announcement, but became false in the same state as a result of the announcement. The canonical example of the latter is the so-called Moore sentence \(\phi = p \wedge \lnot K_a p\).

  7. 7.

    Gerbrandy [8, pp. 27–29] discusses the same point in the context of surprise examination.

  8. 8.

    This can be expressed elegantly by the iterated announcement operator in [13]: \(M_1 \models \langle ann2^*\rangle \lnot ann2\), which is true iff \(M_1 \models \underbrace{\langle ann2 \rangle \cdots \langle ann2 \rangle }_n\lnot ann2\) for some \(n \ge 1\). See also [20] for a further discussion of this and related operators.

  9. 9.

    There are two schemas but actually infinitely many formulas.

  10. 10.

    We could assume that these premises are common knowledge, writing e.g., \(C_{\{a,b\}} (1_i \rightarrow \lnot p_i)\). However, it turns out that assuming common knowledge is not needed, and it is of interest to illucidate exactly how many levels of nested knowledge are sufficient: e.g., two levels for (A4).

  11. 11.

    Observe that \(\alpha \) expresses that (1) the two numbers are different, and (2) both agents consider each of the numbers to be the greatest (\(\alpha \) implies \(ann1 \wedge ann2\) but not the other way around).

  12. 12.

    Nevertheless, that was no problem for \(157_a \rightarrow [ann1][ann2]\lnot K_a\lnot 2_b\), which happens to hold in those models too.

  13. 13.

    \((we \wedge \lnot K we) \vee (th \wedge [\lnot we]\lnot K th) \vee (fr \wedge [\lnot we][\lnot th] \lnot K fr) \vee K \bot \). Note that Gerbrandy assumes that the knowledge modalities are K45 rather than S5.

  14. 14.

    Note that this kind of self-reference is not the same as saying that “you don’t know it now and you still don’t know it after it is announced that you don’t know it now” as briefly discussed at the end of Sect. 3.

References

  1. Ågotnes, T.: A logic of Finite Syntactic Epistemic States. Ph.D. thesis, Department of Informatics, University of Bergen, Norway (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Baltag, A., Bezhanishvili, N., Fernández-Duque, D.: The topology of surprise. In: Proceedings of the International Conference on Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning, vol. 19, pp. 33–42 (2022)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Baltag, A., Smets, S.: Surprise?! an answer to the hangman, or how to avoid unexpected exams!. In: Logic and Interactive Rationality Seminar (LIRA), Slides (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Van Ditmarsch, H., Kooi, B.: The secret of my success. Synthese 151(2), 201–232 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Fagin, R., Halpern, J.Y., Moses, Y., Vardi, M.: Reasoning about Knowledge. MIT, Cambridge (1995)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Freudenthal, H.: Solution to problem no. 223. Nieuw Archief voor Wiskunde 3(18), 102–106 (1970)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Gerbrandy, J.: Bisimulations on Planet Kripke. University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Gerbrandy, J.: The surprise examination in dynamic epistemic logic. Synthese 155, 21–33 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Hollis, M.: A paradoxical train of thought. Analysis 44(4), 205–206 (1984)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Hollis, M.: More paradoxical epistemics. Analysis 46(4), 217–218 (1986)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Kinghan, M.: A paradox derailed: reply to Hollis. Analysis 46(1), 20–24 (1986)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Marcoci, A.: The surprise examination paradox in dynamic epistemic logic. Master’s thesis, Universiteit van Amsterdam (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  13. Miller, J.S., Moss, L.S.: The undecidability of iterated modal relativization. Stud. Logica. 79, 373–407 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Olin, D.: On a paradoxical train of though. Analysis 46(1), 18–20 (1986)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Plaza, J.A.: Logics of public communications. In: Proceedings of the ISMIS 1989, pp. 201–216 (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Poundstone, W.: Labyrinths of Reason: Paradox, Puzzles, and the Frailty of Knowledge. Anchor (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  17. Rea, G.: A variation of Hollis’ paradox. Analysis 47(4), 218–220 (1987)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. van Ditmarsch, H., Kooi, B.: In: One Hundred Prisoners and a Light Bulb, pp. 83–94. Springer, Cham (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-16694-0_9

  19. Van Ditmarsch, H., van Der Hoek, W., Kooi, B.: Dynamic Epistemic Logic, volume 337 of Synthese Library. Springer, Cham (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  20. van Ditmarsch, H.: To be announced. Inf. Comput. 292, 105026 (2023)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The first author was supported by L. Meltzers Høyskolefond.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Ågotnes .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this paper

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this paper

Ågotnes, T., Sakama, C. (2023). A Formal Analysis of Hollis’ Paradox. In: Alechina, N., Herzig, A., Liang, F. (eds) Logic, Rationality, and Interaction. LORI 2023. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol 14329. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-45558-2_24

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-45558-2_24

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-031-45557-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-031-45558-2

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics