Skip to main content

Strong Kleene Metainferential Logics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Metainferential Logics

Part of the book series: Trends in Logic ((TREN,volume 61))

  • 90 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, we will introduce the most studied family of pure and impure mixed metainferential logics of level 1: the Strong Kleene metainferential logics. We will only focus on some of them: the ones that can be characterized through the inferential logics \(\textbf{K3}, \textbf{LP}, \textbf{ST }\), and \(\textbf{TS }\), which will be introduced below.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Though strictly speaking, boolean valuations are not Strong Kleene valuations, they are obviously equivalent to these Strong Kleene valuations.

  2. 2.

    Although we won’t expand on this point, it is important to mention it since it helps to deeply understand the connection between \(\textbf{ST }\) and \(\textbf{CL }\). See e.g. [1] for more details.

  3. 3.

    Meaning that \(\langle x, y\rangle \le _{lex} \langle x', y'\rangle \) if and only if \(x\le x'\) and \(y\le y'\).

  4. 4.

    In the sense that it is locally invalid in \(\textbf{ST }/\textbf{ST }\).

  5. 5.

    For an extensive presentation of \(\textbf{ST }\), see Cobreros, Ripley, Egré and van Rooij [4], Ripley [5, 6] and Cobreros, Ripley, Egré and van Rooij [7]. Though originally applied to vagueness and semantic paradoxes by these authors, Hlobil [8] offers an interpretation of this logic in terms of truth-makers.

  6. 6.

    \(\textbf{TS }\) is discussed by e.g., Cobreros, Ripley, EgrĂ© and van Rooij [4], and also by ChemlĂ¡, EgrĂ© and Spector [11]. Moreover, it was also discussed by Malinowski [12] as a tool to model empirical inference, and more recently was stressed by Rohan French [13], in connection with the paradoxes of self-reference.

  7. 7.

    Shramko and Wansing offer in [14] a way to read these two kinds of logics. While some logics, like \(\textbf{ST }\), take as valid derivations of conclusions whose degree of strength (i.e., the conviction in its truth) is smaller than the one of the premises, other logics, like \(\textbf{TS }\), are designed to qualify as valid derivations of true sentences from non-refuted premises (understood as hypotheses).

  8. 8.

    Barrio, Rosenblatt and Tajer [15], Dicher and Paoli [16] and Pynko [17] have shown that—through some suitable translation—the set of valid inferences in \(\textbf{LP}\) coincides with the set of valid metainferences in \(\textbf{ST }\). Moreover, French [13], have conjectured that—again, through some suitable translation—the set of valid inferences in \(\textbf{K3}\) coincides with the set of valid metainferences in \(\textbf{TS }\).

  9. 9.

    As we have already mentioned, a similar move can be made using different notions of being a counterexample, as Ripley has recently done in [18]. Nevertheless, we will stick to the way they have been initially presented in Pailos [19].

  10. 10.

    This means that we will be explicit about the four metainferential mixed but pure logics about which Pailos [19] says nothing about—i.e., \(\mathbf {ST/ST}\), \(\mathbf {TS/TS}\), \(\mathbf {LP/LP}\) and \(\mathbf {K_3/K_3}\). His silence might be explained by the (presumed) fact that he is identifying them with the inferential and well-known logics \(\textbf{ST }\), \(\textbf{LP}\), \(\textbf{TS }\), and \(\textbf{K3}\), respectively. But this identification can and has been, resisted. See, in particular, what Ripley says in [18]. There, Ripley defends the view that inferential logics are silent about higher-order behavior. (And, more generally, that an n-logic is silent about what happens in higher-than-n metainferential levels).

  11. 11.

    A detailed review of each of these impure logics can be found in Pailos [19].

  12. 12.

    In order to make sense to these rules we would need to take the collections of formulas as lists or sequences of formulas, in the case of Exchange, and as multisets in the case of Contraction.

  13. 13.

    First established in [19], and whose consequences are explored, e.g., in Barrio, Pailos, and Szmuc [21], Pailos [21] or Scambler [22].

  14. 14.

    Nevertheless, it is not true that a valuation v is a counterexample in \(\textbf{CL }\) to an inference \(\Gamma \Rightarrow \Delta \) if and only if v is a counterexample to that inference in \(\textbf{ST }\). Consider for example the \(\textbf{SK}\)-valuation \(v^{**}\) such that \(v^{**}(p)=1\) and \(v(q)=\frac{1}{2}\). The valuation \(v^{**}\) is a counterexample in \(\textbf{ST }\) to the inference \(\psi \Rightarrow \), but it surely is not a counterexample in \(\textbf{CL }\) to that inference, because \(v^{**}\) is not a bivaluation. A similar point can be made with respect to the relation between \(\textbf{TS }\) and \(\textbf{CL }\). That’s why it is important to keep in mind that we are transforming bivaluations into trivaluations, and vice versa.

  15. 15.

    Recall that, as we explained at the beginning of the chapter, this notion is defined over the partial (information) order \(\le \) of this schema, which is defined by stipulating that \(\frac{1}{2}\le 0\) and \(\frac{1}{2}\le 1\).

  16. 16.

    Though this is not mandatory. If these two things are regarded as different, then logics that validate one but not the other may be admitted.

  17. 17.

    The previous footnote can be adapted here for inferences and metainferences, and, in general, for metainferences of level n and metainferences of level \(n+1\). See, in particular, Ripley’s position in [18].

  18. 18.

    But it has many valid metainferences of higher levels, as we will soon show.

  19. 19.

    Therefore, it is not completely non-Tarskian.

  20. 20.

    Similarly, Identity is valid in \(\mathbf {LP/K3 }\) because it is valid in \(\textbf{K3}\).

References

  1. Da Re, B., et al. On three-valued presentations of classical logic. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Frankowski, S. (2004). Formalization of a plausible inference. Bulletin of the Section of Logic, 33(1), 41–52.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Fjellstad, A. (2016). Naive modus ponens and failure of transitivity. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 45(1), 65–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Cobreros, P., et al. (2012). Tolerant, classical, strict. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41(2), 347–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Ripley, D. (2012). Conservatively extending classical logic with transparent truth. Review of Symbolic Logic, 5(2), 354–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Ripley, D. (2013). Paradoxes and failures of cut. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(1), 139–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Cobreros, P., et al. (2014). Reaching transparent truth. Mind, 122(488), 841–866.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Hlobil, U. (2022). A truth-maker semantics for ST: Refusing to climb the strict/tolerant hierarchy. Synthese, 200(1), 1–23. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03820-w

  9. Malinowski, G. (1990). Q-consequence operation. Reports on Mathematical Logic, 24(1), 49–59.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Girard, J.-Y. (1987). Proof theory and logical complexity. Bibliopolis.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Chemla, E., & Égré, P., Spector, B. (2017). Characterizing logical consequence in many-valued logic. Journal of Logic and Computation, 27(7), 2193–2226.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Malinowski, G. (2014). Kleene logic and inference. Bulletin of the Section of Logic, 43(1/2), 43–52.

    Google Scholar 

  13. French, R. (2016). Structural reactivity and the paradoxes of self-reference. Ergo, an Open Access Journal of Philosophy, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Shramko, Y., & Wansing, H. (2010). Truth values. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford University. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/truth-values/

  15. Barrio, E., Rosenblatt, L., & Tajer, D. (2015). The logics of strict-tolerant logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 44(5), 551–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Dicher, B., & Paoli, F. (2019). ST, LP and tolerant metainferences. In: Graham priest on dialetheism and paraconsistency (pp. 383–407). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Pynko, A. (2010). Gentzen’s cut-free calculus versus the logic of paradox. Bulletin of the Section of Logic, 39(1/2), 35–42.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ripley, D. (2022). One step is enough. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 51(6) (2022).

    Google Scholar 

  19. Pailos, F. (2019). A family of metainferential logics. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics, 29(1), 97–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Cobreros, P., La Rosa, E., & Tranchini, L. (2021). Higher-level inferences in the strong-kleene setting: A proof-theoretic approach. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 1–36.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Pailos, F. (2020). A fully classical truth theory characterized by substructural means. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 13(2), 249–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Scambler, C. (2020). Classical logic and the strict tolerant hierarchy. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 49(2), 351–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Cobreros, P., Tranchini, L., & La Rosa, E. (2020). (I Can’t Get No) Antisatisfaction. Synthese,, 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ripley, D. A toolkit for metainferential logics. Manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Federico Pailos .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Pailos, F., Da RĂ©, B. (2023). Strong Kleene Metainferential Logics. In: Metainferential Logics. Trends in Logic, vol 61. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-44381-7_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics