Skip to main content

Dasein, Determination Judgments and the Essence

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Transcendental Idealism and Metaphysics

Abstract

The chapter proposes to consider the phenomenological ontology developed by both Jean Hering and Roman Ingarden as the main reference point to understand Heidegger’s thesis that “the essence of Dasein lies in its existence” (Being and Time, §9). Not only is Heidegger’s own project understood as a criticism of a certain phenomenological ontology, and of a certain conception of the essence-existence distinction; his project should be regarded as part of the very tradition from which he himself intends to depart. For, his own view on Dasein’s essence needs in fact to be construed as a radicalization of some of the theses underlying Hering’s and Ingarden’s theory of ideas.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Husserl’s letter to Ingarden from June 20, 1921: “Ihr Bergson ist im Druck, ein Bogen schon in I. Corr. Dr. Heidegger hat das große Opfer gebracht, Ihr Msc. sprachlich auszufeilen” (Husserl, 1968, 19).

  2. 2.

    See Heidegger’s letter to Löwith from January 25, 1921: “Im Jahrbuchband mit Pfänders Logik u.a. erscheint noch die Arbeit von Ingarden über die Gefahr einer Petitio principii in der Erkenntnistheorie. Gesehen hab ich sie nicht. Frl. Stein hat schon wieder ein neues Buch fertig über Staatsphilosophie” (Heidegger & Löwith, 2017, 32).

  3. 3.

    On the relation between the assertion-function and the truth-making principle in Pfänder, see Mulligan, 2014, 45 ff.

  4. 4.

    See Ingarden 1935, 34, for a distinction between existential ontological problems (which bear upon possible modes of existence) and existential metaphysical ones (concerning “the ascertainment of the factual existence of something”).

  5. 5.

    On these distinctions, see also the detailed analyses proposed by Seifert, 1996, 235–251; and the diagram partially charting these differences in Ferrari, 2001, 64.

  6. 6.

    Hering will recognize the distinction which we are about to mention in his essay on phenomenology of religion (see Hering, 1926, 111–112). On this point, see also De Santis, 2014, 36 and ff.

  7. 7.

    On Ingarden’s theory on knowledge, see Chrudzimski, 1999, Chapters 4 and 5.

  8. 8.

    To which Lipps himself had already critically referred in his book of 1927; see Lipps, 1976, 16–17.

  9. 9.

    “Ich bin Ihnen für diesen Brief sehr dankbar. Für den Brief, weil ich aus ihm Ihre Meinung über meine Essentiale Fragen und über meinen Habilitationsvortrag kennengelernt haben (und was die Essentialen Fragen betrifft, war gerade Ihre Meinung für mich von besonderem Interesse, da ich ja doch Probleme behandelte, an denen sie schon vor mir gearbeitet haben, und da sie unter den Phaenomenologen vielleicht der einzigen sind, der meine Behauptungen auf Grund des früher Geschauten kontrollieren konnte” (Ingarden, 1926, 1).

  10. 10.

    This is why Arnold Metzger and Herbert Spiegelberg will propose to drop altogether the notion of essentiality and focus only on ideas (see Metzger, 1925, 665; Spiegelberg, 1930, 229).

  11. 11.

    The expression is also employed, for example, by Reinach in his course of 1913 Introduction to Philosophy (Reinach, 1989, 438) as well as in the 1914 lecture About Phenomenology (Reinach, 1989, 532). But the fact that his notes on Hering’s concept of essence (Reinach, 1989, 382) were taken during the WS of 1912/1913 (see Reinach, 1989, 733) corroborates our hypothesis about Hering being the first to systematically use it to mean the individual essence.

  12. 12.

    It is worth pointing out that Hering uses more often the term “traits” (Züge) to refer to the many elements making up the essence of an individual object, and the expression “property” (Eigenschaft) appears rarely and only towards the end of the essay (Hering, 1921 527). “Property” as Eigenschaft is on the contrary massively employed by Ingarden in his Essential Questions: we are under the impression that Hering’s modal conception, only sketched and never really elaborated upon by his author, is superseded in the work of the Polish phenomenologist by a more traditional view that tends to construe of the essence as a set of properties which the object itself “has.” The situation is slightly different if we look at Ingarden 1935. Here, in fact, Ingarden recognizes that “it belongs to the essence of the object to exist in a certain mode (eine bestimmte Weise),” just as it belongs to the object’s traits (Merkmale) to be in a certain manner (Seinsweise). Hence, the problem arises that consists in clarifying the relation between these two essentially different, yet inseparable “modes of being” (Ingarden, 1935, 52–53; 65 and ff.). However, the idea of the object having (Jeder Gegenstand “hat” Eigenschaften) properties seems to still guide most of Ingarden’s analyses of the formal structure of the individual object (see for example the beginning of §12 in Ingarden, 1935, 54 and ff.).

  13. 13.

    For a systematic discussion, see for example Borden Sharkey, 2010; Betschart, 2010.

  14. 14.

    Conrad-Martius had already spoken of Zentrum and Bildungswurzel of one’s own personality (Conrad-Martius, 1917, 31 and 55) in a text to which Stein will constantly refer in her works. What they intend to develop, albeit in different ways (Ales Bello, 1992, 2003; Miron, 2021, Part II), is a “centered,” and yet “dynamic” conception of the person.

  15. 15.

    It is noteworthy that in his habilitation of 1928 written under Heidegger, Karl Löwith seems to combine both his master’s existential jargon with Husserl’s ontology. For example, Löwith speaks of the “human individuum” as “an individuum in the mode of being of ‘person’” (Löwith, 2016, 85). A person is an “individuum” (Husserl) having a certain Seinsweise (Heidegger). It is also worth remarking that in a letter from August 1927, Löwith writes to Heidegger that his critical position vis-à-vis the analytics of Being and Time is similar (auf einem analogen Punkt) to the one adopted by the Münchener vis-à-vis Husserl’s constitutive phenomenology (Heidegger & Löwith, 2017, 140).

  16. 16.

    For a commentary on Being and Time, §9, and the notion of So-Sein, see Von Herrmann, 2005, 33–47. Unfortunately, the text entails no reference whatsoever to Hering as a possible source of Heidegger’s discourse.

  17. 17.

    For example, were Agamben to deepen his knowledge of the early phenomenological tradition, he would find out that the modal interpretation of the “fundamental ontology” of Being and Time was already endorsed by Max Beck in the first critical review of the book (Beck, 1928). Beck’s criticism and dismissal of the “fundamental ontology” of Being and Time (whether consistent or not, we shall not decide) is explicitly directed against the reduction of the “material” plurality of the entities to Dasein’s own modes of being (see Beck, 1928, 17 and ff.). This is how we would also read the following remark by Mark Wrathall: “To understand is to be in a certain way, to embody a particular way of existing in the world” (Wrathall, 2013, 180). On Beck and Heidegger, see De Santis, (2023).

References

  • Agamben, G. (2015). L’uso dei corpi (Homo Sacer IV, 2). Neri Pozza Editore.

    Google Scholar 

  • Agamben, G. (2016). The use of bodies. Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ales Bello, A. (1992). Fenomenologia dell’essere umano. Lineamenti di una filosofia al femminile. Città Nuova Editrice.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ales Bello, A. (2003). L’universo nella coscienza. Introduzione alla fenomenologia di Edmund Husserl, Edith Stein, Hedwig Conrad-Martius. ETS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, M. (1928). Martin Heidegger, Sein und Zeit (Referat und Kritik). Philosophische Hefte, 1, 5–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Betschart, C. (2010). “Kern der Person.” (Meta-)Phänomenologische Begründungen der menschlichen Person nach Edith Steins Frühwerk. In H.-B. Gerl-Falkowitz, R. Kaufamnn, & H.-R. Sepp (Hrsg.), Europa und seine Anderen. Emmanuel Levinas, Edith Stein, Jósef Tischner (pp. 61–72). Thelem.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borden Sharkey, S. (2010). Thine own self. Individuality in Edith Stein’s later writings. The Catholic University of American Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chrudzimski, A. (1999). Die Erkenntnistheorie von Roman Ingarden. Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. (1917). Von der Seele. Summa, II (pp. 106–136).

    Google Scholar 

  • De Santis, D. (2014). Di Idee ed essenze. Un dibattito su fenomenologia e ontologia (1921–1930), con saggi di Jean Hering, Roman Ingarden e Herbert Spiegelberg. Mimesis.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Santis, D. (2015). Wesen, Eidos, Idea. Remarks on the “Platonism” of Jean Hering and Roman Ingarden. Studia Phaenomenologica, XV, 155–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Santis, D. (2016). Jean Hering on Eidos, Gegenstand and Methexis. Phenomenological adventures and misadventures of “participation”. Discipline filosofiche, XXV, 145–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Santis, D. (ed.) (2023). Maximilian Beck e Martin Heidegger. Un’inedita disputa su Essere e tempo. Morcelliana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrari, D. (2001). Consciousness in time. C. Winter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1965). Kant and the problem of metaphysics. Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1967). Sein und Zeit (GA 2). Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1979). Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs (GA 20). V. Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1985). History of the concept of time. Prolegomena. Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1988). The basic problems of phenomenology. Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1995). Logik. Die Frage nach der Wahrheit (GA 21). V. Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1997). Die Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie (GA 24). V. Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2010). Being and time. State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2010a). Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik (GA 3). V. Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2010b). Logic. The question of truth. Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M., & Löwith, K. (2017). Briefwechsel 1919–1973. Karl Alber Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hering, H. (1914). Lotzes Lehre vom Apriori. Eine philosophische Studie (Hering Archive, Fondation du Chapitre de Saint-Thomas, Strasbourg) (unpublished).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hering, J. (1921). Bemerkungen über das Wesen, die Wesenheit und die Idee. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, 4, 495–543.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hering, J. (1926). Phénoménologie et philosophie religieuse. Alcan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hering, J. (2021). Remarks concerning essence, ideal quality, and idea (Szylewicz, Trans. A.). Phenomenological Investigations, 1, 51–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1968). Briefe an Roman Ingarden. M. Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ingarden, R. (1925). Essentiale Fragen. Ein Beitrag zum Wesensproblem. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, 7, 125–304.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingarden, R. (1926). Brief an Jean Hering (April 4). Hering Archive, Fondation du Chapitre de Saint-Thomas, in Strasbourg (Unpublished).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingarden, R. (1929). Bemerkungen zum Problem “Idealismus-Realismus”. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung. Ergänzungsband: Husserl-Festschrift (pp. 159–190). Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingarden, R. (1935). Vom formalen Aufbau des individuellen Gegenstandes. Studia Philosophica, 1, 29–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenoci, M. (2000). Logica, ontologia e fenomenologia in Alexander Pfänder. Discipline filosofiche, 673–700.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipps, H. (1976). Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie der Erkenntnis (Werke I). Frankfurt a. M., Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Löwith, K. (2016). Das Individuum in der Rolle des Mitmenschen. Karl Alber Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzger, A. (1925). Der Gegenstand der Erkenntnis. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, 7, 613–770.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miron, R. (2021). Hedwig Conrad-Martius. The gateway to reality. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan, K. (2014). Truth and truth-making principle in 1921. In E. J. Lowe & A. Rami (Eds.), Truth and truth-making (pp. 39–58). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfänder, A. (1963). Logik. Tübingen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfänder, A. (2009). Logic. Ontos Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reinach, A. (1989). Sämtliche Werke. Philosophia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1927). Review of R. Ingarden, Essentiale Fragen. Mind, 36, 366–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, M. (1913). Zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Sympathiegefühle. Verlag von Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, M. (1921). Der Formalismus in der Ethik und die materiale Wertethik. Verlag von Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seifert, J. (1996). Sein und Wesen. C. Winter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sepp, H.-R. (2017). Edith Stein’s conception of the person within the context of the phenomenological movement. In E. Magrì & D. Moran (Eds.), Empathy, sociality and personhood. Essays on Edith Stein’s phenomenological investigations (p. 48.62). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, H. (1930). Über das Wesen der Idee. Eine ontologische Untersuchung. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, 11, 1–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, E. (1962). Endliches und ewiges Sein. Versuch eines Aufstieges zum Sinn des Seins. Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, E. (2002). Finite and Eternal Being. ICS Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, E. (2010). Beiträge zur philosophischen Begründung der Psychologie und der Geisteswissenschaften. Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, E. (2014). Letters to Roman Ingarden. ICS Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, E. (2015). Briefe an Roman Ingarden (ESGA 4). Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, E. (2016). Zum Problem der Einfühlung. Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Herrmann, F.-W. (2005). Hermeneutische Phänomenologie des Daseins. Ein Kommentar zu Sein und Zeit. Erster Abschnitt: Die vorbereitende Fundamentalanalyse des Daseins § 9–§ 27. V. Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wrathall, M. (2013). Heidegger on Human Understanding. In M. Wrathall (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Heidegger’s being and time (pp. 177–200). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniele De Santis .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

De Santis, D. (2023). Dasein, Determination Judgments and the Essence. In: Transcendental Idealism and Metaphysics. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 126. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-39590-1_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics