Skip to main content

The Rise of a Dichotomy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Simulating Science

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 479))

  • 113 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter provides a broad overview of the different philosophical frameworks that have emerged attempting to situate computer simulations and their epistemic import within scientific inquiry. In particular, it provides an analysis of the two main frameworks through which computer simulations have been understood: on one side there are those that have interpreted computer simulations to be akin to mathematical models; on the other side those that consider their extra-mathematical elements to be evidence of their epistemic proximity to empirical experimentation. Together, these two frameworks constitute a dominant dichotomy in the understanding of computer simulations in science. Important reactions to and within this dichotomy are also surveyed in this chapter as the ‘in-betweenness’ of computer simulations is introduced and explored.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Hartmann (1996) and Humphreys (2004) which will be treated in detail in Chap. 4 of this book for examples of these definitions.

  2. 2.

    The representational heuristic of the simulations pipeline will be treated in more detail in a further section within this chapter.

  3. 3.

    He mentions three possible objections against the supposed sui generis nature of computer simulations in these claims: (1) you could say that computer simulations are just extensions of numerical methods already in existence. Therefore, they are not entirely an additional methodology, as suggested by the first claim; (2) computer techniques do not qualify as a method apart because they do not directly access empirical content. If so, then it is hard to account for what exactly is their epistemic import in scientific inquiry; and (3) examining the reliability of computational methods has serious-enough challenges that may prevent them from ever meeting the requirements of rigor in scientific settings. Hence, even if computer simulations were to qualify as an additional category of scientific inquiry, that they would be on a par with existing methodologies is highly questionable.

  4. 4.

    Importantly, the question of whether or not simulations in fact represented any novel epistemic challenges gave rise to an important debate about the nature and role of computer simulations in science. In particular, Frigg and Reiss (2009) wrote an important rebuttal of the views expressed by Humphreys which implied that computer simulations were anything new: in their view, not only did simulations not represented the advent of a new methodological paradigm, as some of the quotes above suggest, but philosophically speaking they also did not pose any new epistemically interesting questions. And if they posed any epistemically interesting questions at all, these were questions that could be easily addressed by, or whose context could already be found in, the rich literature in philosophy of science concerning the role of models.

    It is within this debate on the possible epistemic novelty of computer simulations that important questions and insights begin to emerge regarding the close relationship of computer simulations with models. Those with the intuition that there was indeed something epistemically particular and therefore interesting about the use of computer simulations in science responded to Frigg and Reiss. Amongst them was Humphreys own reply (2009a, b) in which he states that at the very least, computer simulations do in fact represent novel epistemic challenges due to the unprecedented epistemic opacity of their processes. While other methods may be generally opaque, Humphreys argues, computer simulations are essentially epistemically opaque.

  5. 5.

    As we will see, another argumentative strategy is to acknowledge the distinction of computer simulations from either category and push the discourse to its natural conclusion: accepting that computer simulations must be in fact a strange and novel element in scientific inquiry altogether. A sui generis way of doing science. In other words, by suggesting that computer simulations are neither exactly identical to formal methods like mathematical modeling or identical to established experimental practices, philosophers and practitioners have tried to make sense of their epistemic role in scientific inquiry by suggesting that computer simulations are epistemologically speaking somewhere in between experiment and theory because they are completely novel additions to science or because they are a distinct kind of science or a distinct kind of scientific practice. While there is much to be said about these other strategies, let us consider the first argumentative strategy first.

  6. 6.

    As we will also see, the view that computer simulations are instruments does not belong to any of these strategies. Yes, the instrument view accepts that computer simulations does not belong to either category. Yet it does not deem them to be special cases of either. And no, it does not deem them to be a novel sui generis element of scientific inquiry either.

  7. 7.

    In fact, it is precisely the detail that computer simulations require the kind of calibration or tuning that Lenhard mentions that makes Florian Boge (2021) think that computer simulations are more like a precision instrument. This view is in many ways like that of Margaret Morrison explained below, in particular, it deploys a metaphorical use of the term ‘instrument’ that makes few ontological commitments, and it is ultimately deflationary vis-a-vis both precision and instrumentation (2015).

  8. 8.

    It is worth noting that in the computer simulation literature, even this seemingly simple assertion is highly contested (See Primiero, 2019 Ch. 10–12 p. 171–213)

References

  • Baird, D. (2004). Thing knowledge: A philosophy of scientific instruments. University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barberousse, A., & Jebeile, J. (2019). How do the validations of simulations and experiments compare? In Computer simulation validation (pp. 925–942). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barberousse, A., Franceschelli, S., & Imbert, C. (2009). Computer simulations as experiments. Synthese, 169(3), 557–574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beisbart, C. (2017). Advancing knowledge through computer simulations? A socratic exercise. In M. Resch, A. Kaminski, & P. Gehring (Eds.), The science and art of simulation I: Exploring-understanding-knowing (pp. 153–174). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boge, F. J. (2021). Why trust a simulation? Models, parameters, and robustness in simulation-infected experiments. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 75. https://doi.org/10.1086/716542

  • Bruce, A. (1999). The Ising model, computer simulation, and universal physics. Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science, 52, 97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durán, J. M. (2018). Computer simulations in science and engineering. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., & Reiss, J. (2009). The philosophy of simulation: Hot new issues or same old stew? Synthese, 169(3), 593–613.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galison, P. (1996). Computer simulations and the trading zone. In P. Galison & D. J. Stump (Eds.), The disunity of science: Boundaries, contexts, and power (pp. 118–157). Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gehring, P. (2017). Doing research on simulation sciences? Questioning methodologies and disciplinarities. In The science and art of simulation I (pp. 9–21). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2017). Seven problems with massive simulation models for policy decision-making. In The science and art of simulation I (pp. 85–101). Springer, Cham.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, S. (1996). The world as a process. In Modelling and simulation in the social sciences from the philosophy of science point of view (pp. 77–100). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (1994). Numerical experimentation (pp. 103–121). Scientific Philosopher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2004). Extending ourselves: Computational science, empiricism, and scientific method. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2009a). The philosophical novelty of computer simulation methods. Synthese, 169(3), 615–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2009b). Network epistemology. Episteme, 6(2), 221–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaufmann, W., & Smarr, L. L. (1993). Supercomputing and the transformation of science. Scientific American Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, E. F. (2003). Models, simulation, and “computer experiments.”. In H. Radder (Ed.), The philosophy of scientific experimentation (pp. 198–215). University of Pittsburgh.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lenhard, J. (2007). Computer simulation: The cooperation between experimenting and modeling. Philosophy of Science, 74(2), 176–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lenhard, J. (2019). Calculated surprises: A philosophy of computer simulation. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M. S., Morrison, M., & Skinner, Q. (Eds.). (1999). Models as mediators: Perspectives on natural and social science (Vol. 52). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (2015). Reconstructing reality. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nieuwpoort, W. C. (1985). Science, simulation and supercomputers. In Supercomputers in theoretical and experimental science (pp. 3–9). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, S., & Suppe, F. (2001). Why atmospheric modeling is good science. In Changing the atmosphere: Expert knowledge and environmental governance (pp. 67–105).

    Google Scholar 

  • Parker, W. S. (2003). Computer modeling in climate science: Experiment, explanation, pluralism (Doctoral dissertation, University of Pittsburgh).

    Google Scholar 

  • Parker, W. S. (2009). Does matter really matter? Computer simulations, experiments, and materiality. Synthese, 169(3), 483–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Primiero, G. (2019). On the foundations of computing. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resch, M. M. (2013). What’s the result? Thoughts of a center director on simulation. In J. M. Durán & E. Arnold (Eds.), Computer simulation and the changing face of scientific experimentation (pp. 233–246). Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resch, M. M. (2017). On the missing coherent theory of simulation. In The science and art of simulation I: Exploring-understanding-knowing (pp. 23–32). Springer International Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohrlich, F. (1990). Computer simulation in the physical sciences. In PSA: Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association (Vol. 2, pp. 507–518). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saam, N. J. (2017a). Understanding social science simulations: Distinguishing two categories of simulations. In M. Resch, A. Kaminski, & P. Gehring (Eds.), The science and art of simulation I (pp. 67–84). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Saam, N. J. (2017b). What is a computer simulation? A review of a passionate debate. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 48(2), 293–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1969). The sciences of the artificial. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Symons, J., & Alvarado, R. (2019). Epistemic entitlements and the practice of computer simulation. Minds and Machines, 29(1), 37–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tal, E. (2012). The epistemology of measurement: A model-based account. University of Toronto.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warner, D. J. (1990). What is a scientific instrument, when did it become one, and why? The British Journal for the History of Science, 23(1), 83–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2012). Simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, E. (2003). Simulated experiments: Methodology for a virtual world. Philosophy of science, 70(1), 105–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, E. (2010). Science in the age of computer simulation. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, E. (2019). Computer simulations in science. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2015 edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/simulations-science/. Accessed 20 Dec 2018.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Alvarado, R. (2023). The Rise of a Dichotomy. In: Simulating Science. Synthese Library, vol 479. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-38647-3_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics