Skip to main content

Ordinals vs. Cardinals in ℕ and Beyond

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Mathematical Knowledge, Objects and Applications

Part of the book series: Jerusalem Studies in Philosophy and History of Science ((JSPS))

  • 238 Accesses

Abstract

Ordinality and cardinality, in the finite domain, are ordinarily considered as mere aspects of the very same objects, the natural numbers. Yet Steiner (Mathematics – application and applicability. In: Shapiro S (ed) The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mathematics and logic. Oxford University Press, 2005) draws attention to the intricate interplay between them, which is made implicit by this conception of them. In this chapter, I present a fitting cognitive framework and use it to account for how this situation comes to be. The framework concerns basic principles of object representation in the cognitive system, and particularly when and how different “aspects” of objects come, developmentally, to be integrated into a deeper, combined representation. Our coming to master the natural numbers is then presented as the process of such integration of ordinals and cardinals, based on their well-behaved interaction in the finite domain. This regular connection in the finite domain between ordinality and cardinality, however, is grasped automatically by the cognitive system as a statistical pattern rather than being stated explicitly, mathematically. Philosophically, this case study thus serves as a warning against ignoring cognition’s inner workings. The upshot is a novel, cognitively motivated account of the natural numbers.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    That the final number-word in a count sequence, which is attributed to the last object counted, indicates the cardinal value of the set, is known in the developmental mathematical cognition literature as the Cardinal Principle. (Gelman & Gallistel Charles, 1978; Wynn, 1992).

  2. 2.

    For a methodological discussion, see (Keren, 2018), Chap. 4.

  3. 3.

    For musings in similar spirit by a historically notable figure, see (Poincaré, 1905), Chap. 4.

  4. 4.

    My full account can be found at (Keren, 2018), Chap. 6. The main omissions in this current paper are: (1) The cognitive-scientific material that gives this framework substance, (2) A substantial section on the developmental dynamics, (3) More elaborate connections specifically to mathematics.

  5. 5.

    I do not suggest even the beginning of an approach to the age-old question of how intentionality could arise here. The point is just to point to the level at which such an account would have to begin.

  6. 6.

    I leave open the further issue of when and why we come to identify different (cognitive) object-types as of the same type.

  7. 7.

    Even if it technically were (i.e., without strawberries, etc. in the world), then even though technically a watermelon (say) could be peeled, it would not be relevant as a cognitive object-type, for which mastering the preparation of a watermelon typically goes through other means.

  8. 8.

    A structurally related theory in cognitive science is that of Conceptual Blending (Fauconnier & Turner, 2002), which in particular has been used to account for concepts in mathematics (Guhe et al., 2011; Lakoff & Núñez, 2000).

  9. 9.

    For a richer discussion see (Keren, 2018), p. 156, and section 6.5.

  10. 10.

    Though in cognition, the boundaries may ordinarily be graded or ill-defined (Rosch et al., 1976).

  11. 11.

    See (Keren, 2018 p. 170).

  12. 12.

    Much more importantly for this story, the objectification could in principle land directly on something larger. As will become clear when we get to it soon, this may particularly be ℕ, the system never coming to individuate anything like the object-type TOrd or some reduct along the way. This possibility, however, is not theoretically reasonable nor empirically evident. For a more detailed discussion of these developmental complexities, see (Keren, 2018), Section 7.7.

  13. 13.

    Though there is certainly alot going on here too:

    1. 1.

      “all that the successor procedure ever could generate from 1” is a higher-order reflection on a procedure (within the context of the rest of the array), not just its usage by another procedure (which is standard). For a preliminary cognitive account of (some) infinitary ordinals, see (Keren, 2018 pp. 235–237).

    2. 2.

      A different amalgalm, between natural numbers and the continuum, serves here to provide the model in which this post-finite element can be seen to exist.

  14. 14.

    “Visual ‘pop-out’ refers to the phenomenon in which a unique visual target (e.g. a feature singleton) can be rapidly detected among a set of homogeneous distractors”. (Hsieh et al., 2011).

  15. 15.

    Another, linguistics-based possibility considered by Snyder et al. (2018a, b, pp. 93–95).

  16. 16.

    This is not to rule out the possibility for amalgamation of natural numbers as an object-type with new object-types yet (nor the possibility that there are more abstract types integrated into them to begin with). To the extent that such a further amalgamation would keep fixed the ontology of individuated objects (rather than restrict it, e.g., to the even numbers, or extend it, e.g., to the rationals), we would take that object-type to still be about natural numbers (in the mathematical world), of which we have learned something new. But this is just a special case within the broader formal structure, and the finer distinctions that my cognitively grounded framework makes must not be ignored.

  17. 17.

    Keren (2018), Section 6.5.

  18. 18.

    Keren (2018 p. 168).

  19. 19.

    See (Keren, 2018), Section 7.7.

  20. 20.

    (Keren, 2018), Section 6.5.

References

  • Benacerraf, P. (1965). What numbers could not be. The Philosophical Review, 74, 47–73. Duke University Press, ISSN: 00318108, 15581470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S. (2011). The number sense: How the mind creates mathematics (Revised and Updated ed.). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eysenck, M. W., & Keane, M. T. (2010). Cognitive psychology: A Student’s handbook (6th ed.). Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fauconnier, G., & Turner, M. (2002). The way we think: Conceptual blending and the mind’s hidden complexities. Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feigenson, L., Dehaene, S., & Spelke, E. (2004). Core systems of number. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 307–314. ISSN: 1364-6613.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A., & Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1981). How direct is visual perception?: Some reflections on Gibsonś “Ecological Approach”. Cognition, 9, 139–196. Netherlands.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gelman, R., & Gallistel Charles, R. (1978). The child’s understanding of number. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gödel, K. (1947). What is Cantor’s continuum problem? The American Mathematical Monthly, 54(9), 515–525. Taylor & Francis.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guhe, M., et al. (2011). A computational account of conceptual blending in basic mathematics. Cognitive Systems Research, 12(3), 249–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hsieh, P.-J., Colas Jaron, T., & Kanwisher, N. (2011). Unconscious pop-out: Attentional capture by unseen feature singletons only when top-down attention is available. Psychological Science, 22(9), 1220–1226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keren, A. (2018). Towards a cognitive foundation of mathematics [Report]. PhD dissertation. The Hebrew University of Jerusalem.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kinzler, K. D., & Spelke Elizabeth, S. (2007). Core systems in human cognition. Progress in Brain Research, 164, 257–264. From Action to Cognition. ISSN: 0079-6123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Núñez, R. (2000). Where mathematics comes from: How the embodied mind brings mathematics into being. Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnebo, Ø. (2009). The individuation of the natural numbers. In O. Bueno & Ø. Linnebo (Eds.), New waves in philosophy of mathematics. Palgrave Macmillan UK.

    Google Scholar 

  • Modayil, J., & Kuipers, B. (2008). The initial development of object knowledge by a learning robot. Robotics and Autonomous Systems, 56(11), 879–890.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, D. (2017, Spring). Mental representation. In N. Zalta Edward (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (1905). Science and hypothesis. The Walter Scott Publishing Co., LTD.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosch, E., et al. (1976). Basic objects in natural categories. Cognitive Psychology, 8(3), 382–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuels, R, Shapiro, S., & Snyder, E. (2017). Basically natural: On the relative fundamentality of ordinal and cardinal conceptions of number [Conference], forthcoming?.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, E., Samuels, R., & Shapiro, S. (2018a). Neologicism, Frege’s constraint, and the frege-heck condition. Noûs, 54(1), 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, E., Shapiro, S., & Samuels, R. (2018b). Cardinals, ordinals, and the prospects for a Fregean foundation. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 82, 77–107. Cambridge University Press.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, M. (2005). Mathematics – Application and applicability. In S. Shapiro (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mathematics and logic. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wynn, K. (1992). Children’s acquisition of the number words and the counting system. Cognitive Psychology., 24(2), 220–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Keren, A. (2023). Ordinals vs. Cardinals in ℕ and Beyond. In: Posy, C., Ben-Menahem, Y. (eds) Mathematical Knowledge, Objects and Applications. Jerusalem Studies in Philosophy and History of Science. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-21655-8_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics