Skip to main content

Naturalism, Transcendentalism, and a New Naturalizing

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Phenomenology

Part of the book series: Palgrave Philosophy Today ((PPT))

  • 1342 Accesses

Abstract

What is the relationship between phenomenology, psychology, and natural science? This chapter addresses questions about Husserl’s differentiation between phenomenology understood as a transcendental project and the idea that phenomenology can be ‘naturalized’ in the form of a phenomenological psychology and as a partner to cognitive science. It explores the phenomenological concepts of ‘lifeworld’ and Heidegger’s concept of the ‘ready-to-hand’. Finally, it explains the notion of ‘mutual constraints’ between phenomenology and cognitive science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 24.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Although Husserl studied mathematics in Berlin from 1878–1880, he wasn’t in Berlin in the 1930s when Sartre studied there, and Sartre never met Husserl. Husserl’s ideas about phenomenology likely originated when he went to Vienna in 1881 to finish his Ph.D. in mathematics and started to attend Brentano’s lectures. On Brentano’s advice, he then went to study with the psychologist Carl Stumpf at University of Halle in 1886.

  2. 2.

    The concept of lifeworld is taken up by sociology via the work of Alfred Schutz (one of Husserl’s students) and Thomas Luckmann in their book Structures of the Life-World (1973; 1983). It also makes its way into critical theory, via Habermas (1987) and his distinction between system and lifeworld and the notion of the colonization of the lifeworld.

  3. 3.

    We can also mention a fourth table, described by Husserl. Call it the table as strictly perceived. ‘When we view the table, we view it from some particular side, and this side is thereby what is genuinely seen. Yet the table has still other sides. It has a non-visible back side, it has a non-visible interior; and these are actually indexes for a variety of sides, a variety of complexes of possible visibility [.…] But this thing is not [merely] the side genuinely seen in this moment; rather (according to the very sense of perception) the thing is precisely the full-thing that has still other sides, sides that are not brought to genuine perception in this perception, but that would be brought to genuine perception in other perspectives’ (Husserl, 2012, 40). We’ll see in the next chapter that we may also discern a transcendental table, or the table as pure phenomenon, which we get to by means of the phenomenological reduction. Thus, speaking about his own table, Husserl says, that as we employ the phenomenological method of the reduction (or the epoché), ‘the perception of this table still is, as it was before, precisely a perception of this table” (1960, 33–32).

  4. 4.

    Similarly, see De Preester (2002), who suggests that if phenomenology accepts the assumptions of cognitive science, then phenomenology self-destructs. “A naturalized phenomenology is no longer phenomenology” (De Preester, 2002, 645). This would only be the case, however, if we supposed a positive answer to Shimon Edelman’s (2002, 125) question: “Is a new phenomenology, which would completely eschew transcendentalism in favor of computational principles, possible?” The issue really goes the other way. That is, the introduction of phenomenology into cognitive science has critically challenged the basic assumptions of cognitive science, including computationalism, and indeed the very concepts of nature and naturalism, and has moved cognitive science towards a view that is more consistent with the views of Husserl and Merleau-Ponty on intentionality, intersubjectvity, action, and embodiment. See Gallagher (2018), Gallagher and Varela (2003), Thompson (2007), Varela et al. (1991).

References

  • De Preester, H. (2002). Naturalizing Husserlian phenomenology: An introduction. Psychoanalytische Perspectieven, 20(4), 633–647.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2018). The fantasy of first-person science. In S. Wuppuluri & F. A. Doria (Eds.), The map and the territory: Exploring the foundations of science, thought and reality (pp. 455–473). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. (1991). Being-in-the-world: A commentary on Heidegger’s being and time, division I. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. (1992). What computers still Can’t do. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eddington, A. (1927). The Nature of the Physical World. Kessinger Publishing, 2005. Also at http://www-history.mcs.st-and.ac.uk/Extras/Eddington_Gifford.html.

  • Edelman, S. (2002). Constraining the neural representation of the visual world. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6, 125–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1894). Rezension von E. Husserl: Philosophie der Arithmetik. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 103, 313–332.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2018). Rethinking nature: Phenomenology and a non-reductionist cognitive science. Australasian Philosophical Review 2(2): 125–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Schmicking, D. (Eds.). (2010). Handbook of phenomenology and cognitive science. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Varela, F. (2003). Redrawing the map and resetting the time: Phenomenology and the cognitive sciences. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 29(Suppl), 93–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gurwitsch, A. (2009). The collected works of Aron Gurwitsch (1901–1973). Vol. I Constitutive phenomenology in historical perspective (J. García-Gómez, Trans. and Ed.). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1987). The theory of communicative action, vol. 2: Lifeworld and system: A critique of functionalist reason (T. McCarthy, Trans.). Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harney, M. (2015). Naturalizing phenomenology–a philosophical imperative. Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology, 119(3), 661–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). Harper & Row. Cited with English/German pagination.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1993). The question concerning technology. In D. Krell (Ed.), Basic writings. Harper Collins Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1960). Cartesian meditations: An introduction to phenomenology (D. Cairns, Trans.). Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1965). Phenomenology and the crisis of philosophy: Philosophy as a science and philosophy and the crisis of European man (Q. Lauer, Trans.). Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1970). The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology: An introduction to phenomenological philosophy (D. Carr, Trans.). Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1977). Phenomenological psychology: Lectures, summer semester, 1925 (J. Scanlon, Trans.). Martinus Nijhoff. German pagination in margins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1989). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy - second book (R. Rojcewicz & A. Schuwer, Trans.). Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001). Logical investigations (Vol. 2, J. N. Findlay with corrections D. Moran, Trans.). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2012). Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis: Lectures on transcendental logic (A. Steinbock, Trans.). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S. M. (1978). Imagery and internal representation. In E. Rosch & B. B. Lloyd (Eds.), Cognition and categorization (pp. 217–257). Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S. M. (1980). Image and mind. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawlor, L. (2009). Becoming and auto-affection (part II): Who are we? Invited lecture, ICNAP, 2009. Published at http://www.icnap.org/meetings.htm (Accessed 15 January 2011).

  • Marbach, E. (1993). Mental representation and consciousness: Towards a phenomenological theory of representation and reference. Kluwer Academic.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mensch, J. (2018). The question of naturalizing phenomenology. In J. Mensch (Ed.), Selfhood and appearing (pp. 38–48). Brill.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964). The primacy of perception and other essays on phenomenological psychology, the philosophy of art, history and politics. Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968). The visible and the invisible (A. Lingis, Trans.). Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2010). Child psychology and pedagogy: The Sorbonne lectures 1949–1952 (T. Welsh, Trans.). Northewestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, J. (1989). Transcendental phenomenology: An analytic account. Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petitot, J., Varela, F. J., Pachoud, B., & Roy, J.-M. (Eds.). (1999). Naturalizing phenomenology: Issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science. Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pokropski, M. (2021). Mechanisms and consciousness: Integrating phenomenology with cognitive science. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1973). What the mind’s eye tells the mind’s brain: A critique of mental imagery. Psychological Bulletin, 80, 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J-P. (2004). The imaginary: A phenomenological psychology of the imagination (J. Webber, Trans.). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1996). Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3(4), 330–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (Ed.). (2012). The Oxford handbook of contemporary phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Gallagher, S. (2022). Naturalism, Transcendentalism, and a New Naturalizing. In: Phenomenology. Palgrave Philosophy Today. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-11586-8_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics