Skip to main content

A Husserlian Approach to Affectivity and Temporality in Affordance Perception

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Affordances in Everyday Life

Abstract

Gibson defined affordances as action possibilities directly offered to an animal by the environment. Ambitiously, affordances are meant to show the inadequacy of the subjective-objective dichotomy in the study of cognition. Armed with similar concerns, some neo-Gibsonians recently thought of affordances as latent dispositions existing independently of individual organisms or whole species. It is no coincidence that critics had, on several occasions, objected that this theoretical stance dramatically neglects the role of the perceiver in the emergence of affordances. In this paper, we provide a phenomenological characterization of the perceiver’s role in affordance perception. Specifically, we borrow from Husserlian phenomenology to characterize two features of affordance perception that can enrich our understanding of the individual’s engagement with the environment, namely, its affective and temporal aspects. Taking an everyday activity such as rock climbing as a case example, we show that phenomenological investigations, if not be misinterpreted as mere introspection, can represent an ally for ecological psychologists.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It should be acknowledged that there might be some tension between phenomenology and ecological psychology insofar as the former (especially in its Husserlian version) is explicitly anti-naturalist, whereas the latter “rejects the causal reductionism of other scientific psychologies but without rejecting their emphasis on experiment and empirical explanation” (Reed, 1996, p. 19). It would go beyond the scope of this paper to delve into Husserl’s anti-naturalism and the possibility of integrating phenomenology and ecological psychology. Suffice it to say that, from a Husserlian standpoint, consciousness should be seen as a condition for the natural world to appear, and thus, it would be a category mistake to study consciousness from the perspective of the natural sciences for they assume that the objects they study are in the natural world. We believe, however, that a non-objectivist scientific approach to the mind (such as ecological psychology) and/or a re-conceptualization of the idea of nature could be consistent with phenomenology’s anti-naturalism. For a brief suggestion on how ecological psychology and Husserlian phenomenology could be integrated, see Roy et al. (1999, pp. 68–71). For more on the idea of re-thinking the concept of nature and thus opening the possibility of integrating a new kind of naturalism and phenomenology, see Vörös (2014) and Gallagher (2018).

  2. 2.

    To be sure, affection and temporality are not the only phenomenological characteristics that underpin affordance perception. One should also acknowledge, among other things, the experience of one’s own embodiment, the sedimentation of habits or attunement towards daily sociocultural practices. However, we will focus on affection and temporality alone.

  3. 3.

    The relevance of a phenomenological analysis of affordance perception has already been pointed out by Dreyfus and Kelly (2007), as well as other authors inspired by them. However, most (if not all) those phenomenological approaches to affordance perception have usually drawn to Merleau-Pontian phenomenology, rather than from Husserlian phenomenology as we do.

  4. 4.

    Our phenomenological approach to affordance perception needs thus to be differentiated from the idea that perceivers project or construct a subjectiveenvironment. Instead, we think of agents as actively disclosing their meaningful surroundings. This difference can be furtherly highlighted by comparing ourproposal with the contemporary approaches in biosemiotics that stemmed from the work of Jakob von Uexküll. For him, as much as for his followers (e.g. Kull etal., 2011), agents, through the receptors of their physiological apparatuses, literally create their niches. As von Uexküll puts it, “So in the nervous system thestimulus itself does not really appear but its place is taken by an entirely different process which has nothing to do with events in the outside world. [...] Thestimuli of the outside world are altogether translated into a nervous sign language” (1909/1996, p. 33). As it should be clear at this point, we reject thisconstructivist view in favour of a relational approach to affordances.

  5. 5.

    A similar take on the role on affectivity has been embraced in empirical psychology by Frijda (2004) and Lambie (2020), among others.

  6. 6.

    This can be related to Dreyfus and Kelly (2007), who anticipated that, when manifesting, affordances are perceived as solicitations. We suggest that, while more than one affordance can have an inviting character, the subject will tend towards one specific action possibility depending on their affective force.

  7. 7.

    Here affectivity is understood in relation to the possibility of being affected, i.e. to be allured or to undergo a stimulus (“Reiz” in German). This sense of affectivity might seem very different from the one related to affective states such as emotions or moods. We believe, however, that both senses are intrinsically related. For instance, something disgusting may draw one’s attention because of how disgusting it is. Furthermore, Husserl (2006, Nrs. 69–75) himself suggests that affection may be defined by feelings of pleasure or displeasure (lust and unlust) that motivate the ego to react in different ways. In a few words, both senses of affectivity are connected by the idea that something can only affect if there is a lack of indifference towards it (Colombetti, 2014). A full-fledged phenomenological analysis of affordances would have to say much more about the affective nature of affordances.

  8. 8.

    There are several subtle and complex relations between retention, primal impression, and protention which constitute the living present. It is, however, impossible to develop this topic further in this paper. See Husserl (1991, 2001).

  9. 9.

    We would like to thank two anonymous reviewers for their comments on an earlier version of this paper.

References

  • Chemero, A. (2003). An outline of a theory of affordances. Ecological Psychology, 15(2), 181–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2014). The feeling body. Affective science meet the enactive mind. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A. (2016). Across the Uncanny Valley: The ecological, the enactive, and the strangely familiar. Constructivist Foundations, 11(2), 327–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dings, R. (2018). Understanding phenomenological differences in how affordances solicit action. An exploration. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 17(4), 681–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H., & Kelly, S. D. (2007). Heterophenomenology: Heavy-handed sleight of hand. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(1–2), 45–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frijda, N. H. (2004). Emotions and action. In A. S. R. Manstead, N. H. Frijda, & A. Fischer (Eds.), Feelings and emotions: The Amsterdam symposium (pp. 158–173). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fultot, M., Nie, L., & Carello, C. (2016). Perception-action mutuality obviates mental construction. Constructivist Foundations, 11(2), 298–307.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2018). Rethinking nature: Phenomenology and a non-reductionist cognitive science. Australasian Philosophical Review, 2(2), 125–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1972). A theory of direct visual perception. In J. Royce & W. Rozenboom (Eds.), The psychology of knowing (pp. 77–89). Gordon and Breach.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1977/2017). The theory of affordances. In R. Shaw & J. Bransford (Eds.), Perceiving, acting and knowing (pp. 67–82). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979/2015). The ecological approach to visual perception. Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heras-Escribano, M. (2019). The philosophy of affordances. Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1991). On the phenomenology of the consciousness of internal time (1893–1917) (J. Barnett Brough, Trans.). Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001). Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis. Lectures on transcendental logic (A. J. Steinbock, Trans.). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2006). Späte Texte über Zeitkonstitution (1929–1934). Die C-Manuskripte (D. Lohmar, Hrsg.). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Käufer, S., & Chemero, A. (2021). Phenomenology: An introduction (2nd ed.). Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kull, K., Deacon, T., Emmeche, C., Hoffmeyer, J., & Stjernfelt, F. (2011). Theses on biosemiotics: Prolegomena to a theoretical biology. In C. Emmeche & K. Kull (Eds.), Towards a semiotic biology: Life is the action of signs (pp. 25–42). Imperial College Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lambie, J. A. (2020). The demanding world of emotion: A gestalt approach to emotion experience. New Ideas in Psychology, 56, 100751.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reed, E. S. (1996). Encountering the world. Toward an ecological psychology. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roy, J.-M., Petitot, J., Pachoud, B., & Varela, F. J. (1999). Beyond the gap: An introduction to naturalizing phenomenology. In J. Petitot, F. J. Varela, B. Pachoud, & J.-M. Roy (Eds.), Naturalizing phenomenology: Issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science (pp. 1–80). Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rucińska, Z. (2020). Affordances in Dennett’s from bacteria to Bach and Back. Avant, 11(2), 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turvey, M. T. (1992). Affordances and prospective control: An outline of the ontology. Ecological Psychology, 4(3), 173–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Dijk, L., Withagen, R., & Bongers, R. M. (2015). Information without content: A Gibsonian reply to enactivists’ worries. Cognition, 134, 210–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Uexküll, J. (1909). Umwelt und Innenwelt der Tiere. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vörös, S. (2014). The uroboros of consciousness: Between the naturalisation of phenomenology and the phenomenologisation of nature. Constructivist Foundations, 10(1), 96–104.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Juan Diego Bogotá .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Bogotá, J.D., Artese, G.F. (2022). A Husserlian Approach to Affectivity and Temporality in Affordance Perception. In: Djebbara, Z. (eds) Affordances in Everyday Life. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-08629-8_17

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics