Skip to main content

Megalophueis and anômalia: The Talented Person, Conflicts in Everyday Life, and the Attraction of Philosophy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Sextus Empiricus’ Neo-Pyrrhonism

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 457))

  • 166 Accesses

Abstract

After describing the main steps in becoming a skeptic (as stated in PH 1.12, PH 1.26, and PH 1.29), this chapter is devoted to an analysis of the initial ones, focusing on those steps taken before one starts to investigate philosophically (PH 1.12). Who is the person who eventually becomes a skeptic? Sextus tells us that he is a talented person (magalophueis), but which talents must he have? And what moves him to philosophy in the first place? Here, the notion of irregularity (anomalía) is crucial, and I try to clarify it. An irregularity is something the talented person encounters in the world and is part of our everyday life. It concerns both ethical issues and perception about how things are. Next, I discuss whether other disturbances may lead to philosophy, and reject this possibility. Why irregularity disturbs the talented person is another important question addressed in this first chapter. Finally, I describe the attraction exerted by philosophy on the talented person, for perhaps not all talented people come to philosophize.

We are only expressing this puzzlement by asking a slightly misleading question, the question: ‘What is…?’ This question is an utterance of unclarity, of mental discomfort.

Wittgenstein (1984, p. 26)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Aristotle (Pol. 1455a32; Ret. 1390b28) used this expression in the sense of a man of genius.

  2. 2.

    Bett suggested to me that anômalia is an Aenesidemian term. It is a pity that Polito (2004), a book entirely devoted to Aenesidemus’ appropriation of Heraclitus, does not even mention anômalia. New skeptics prefer diaphônia. But, as we shall see in the next chapter, they do not have the same meaning, nor do they play the same role in the skeptical path.

  3. 3.

    Of course, many scholars have pointed out that anômalia is the starting point of the route leading to Pyrrhonism and even made some comments about it, e.g., Barnes (1998, pp. 89–90); Tad Brennan (1999, pp. 10–13); Katja Vogt (2012, pp. 123–128).

  4. 4.

    I follow the explanation given in the Liddell-Scott-Jones Ancient Greek lexicon.

  5. 5.

    Mates (1996, p. 63) says that “the Greek anômalia means irregularity, or, more generally, seeming incapability of being brought under a coherent account.”

  6. 6.

    Sextus himself sometimes uses phainomenon as equivalent to sense-perception, following Aenesidemus. As is well-known, ‘what appears’ was used in PH 1.9 in this restricted sense, meaning only the objects of sense-perception. By thus restricting its sense in this passage, Sextus appears to be implying that he has a wider sense in mind in other passages, which indeed he does.

  7. 7.

    Hegel (1995, p. 335) says that Pyrrho’s skepticism “aimed against the immediate truth both of the senses and of morality.” If that is true, perhaps the priority of the fourth and tenth of the Ten Modes in raising questions in or from everyday life dates back to Pyrrho. But he thought that Pyrrho was the author of the Ten Modes. This comment certainly applies to Aenesidemus.

  8. 8.

    I will deal with diaphonia as a different concept in the next chapter.

  9. 9.

    Unless otherwise indicated, I will be referring exclusively to the Ten Modes.

  10. 10.

    For an analysis of the Ten Modes in Diogenes, see Sedley (2015).

  11. 11.

    Sextus may mean something broader: philosophical investigation begins with irregularity in the phainomena, irrespective of being sensible or intellectual.

  12. 12.

    Note that everyday people, though they are conscious of irregularity, do not feel disturbed by it and, therefore, do not feel inclined to philosophize.

  13. 13.

    Plato, in the Theaetetus (158b), refers to arguments about knowing whether we are dreaming or awake as if everybody had heard of them; the context suggests that other conditions of perception, similar to those discussed in connection with Mode Four, were equally ordinary. Plato even suggests that reflection on irregularities, or opposites, is what produces philosophical theories (160d–e).

  14. 14.

    Some commentators seem to exaggerate the extent to which irregularities occur in everyday life. Tad Brennan (1999, p. 63) attributes to Sextus the idea of “the chaos of everyday life.” Striker (2001, p. 117) thinks there is, for Sextus, “a general disorder of things” or “ubiquitous conflicts.” In my view, they overestimate the extent of anômalia in everyday life. Language is a good example: there are irregularities, but most of the time rules apply. This idea seems to be behind Sextus’ view on language in M 1.

  15. 15.

    I will resume this topic in Chap. 9, where a different picture of (dogmatic) philosophy will emerge.

References

  • Barnes, J. (1998). The beliefs of a Pyrrhonists. In M. Burnyeat & M. Frede (Eds.), The original Sceptics (pp. 58–91). Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bett, R. (2020). What is Ataraxia like, and why do some schools, but not others, aim for it? Sképsis, 20, 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, T. (1999). Ethics and epistemology in Sextus Empiricus. Garland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnyeat, M. (1998). Can the Sceptic live his Scepticism? In M. Burnyeat & M. Frede (Eds.), The original Sceptics: A controversy (pp. 25–57). Hackett. (Originally published in 1980. Also published in: Burnyeat, Myles (ed.). 1983. The Skeptical Tradition. University of California Press, Berkeley, Los Angeles, London).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1995). Lectures on the history of philosophy: Plato and the Platonists (Vol 2, E. S. Haldane & F. H. Simson, Trans.). University of Nebraska Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mates, B. (1996). The Skeptic Way: Sextus Empiricus’s outlines of Pyrrhonism. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Naess, A. (1968). Scepticism. Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polito, R. (2004). The Sceptical road. Brill.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sedley, D. (1983). The motivation of Greek Scepticism. In M. F. Burnyeat (Ed.), The Skeptical tradition (pp. 9–29). University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sedley, D. (2015). Diogenes Laertius on the Ten Pyrrhonist Modes. In K. M. Vogt (Ed.), Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (pp. 171–185). Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Striker, G. (2001). Skepticism as a kind of philosophy. Archiv für die Geschichte der Philosophie, 83, 113–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogt, K. (2012). Appearances and assent: Sceptical belief reconsidered. The Classical Quarterly, 62(02), 648–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1984). The blue and the brown books. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Smith, P.J. (2022). Megalophueis and anômalia: The Talented Person, Conflicts in Everyday Life, and the Attraction of Philosophy. In: Sextus Empiricus’ Neo-Pyrrhonism. Synthese Library, vol 457. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-94518-3_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics