Skip to main content

Hume and Cicero on Metaphysics: Philo’s Non-Dogmatic Deism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Academic Skepticism in Hume and Kant

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 449))

  • 195 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, I discuss how Hume applies his normative theory of belief – consisting of a typology of beliefs and a set of rules to guide causal inferences – to the theses of natural theism in the Dialogues concerning Natural Religion. Given the significant influence that Cicero’s De Natura Deorum had on Hume’s Dialogues, I begin the chapter by surveying the most important references to Cicero in Hume’s correspondence and philosophical works. After this, I draw a parallel between the two dialogues’ philosophical arguments and narrative strategies, to prepare the ground for the most detailed analysis of Hume’s application of his normative theory of belief in the Dialogues. The third section of the chapter, centers on determining what kind of belief, in Hume’s typology, is held by natural theism. I show that this belief is a probability based on an analogy by, first, examining the possibilities that it is a natural belief or a proof, and discarding both options based on Philo’s use of some of the rules for causal inferences in his skeptical objections. I close the chapter with a discussion of the last part of the Dialogues, usually referred to as “Philo’s reversal,” to evaluate whether Philo’s sudden profession of faith can be understood as an avowal of theism, fideism, or deism, or simply as a disguise of his atheistic inclinations. I claim that, after the skeptical examination of natural theism, Philo accepts a non-dogmatic adoption of a much less metaphysically robust belief—namely the belief that Gaskin called “attenuated deism” and that I would like to name “non-dogmatic, anti-religious deism.”

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See: Battersby 1979, pp. 239–252; Fosl 1994, pp. 103–120; Jones 1982, p. 29; Penelhum 1979, pp. 253–278; Price 1964, pp. 97–106; Smith 1947, pp. 60–61.

  2. 2.

    For Jones: “Every educated reader could discern, at the time of their posthumous publication, that Hume’s Dialogues concerning Natural Religion was modeled on Cicero’s De Natura Deorum” (Jones 1982, p. 3).

  3. 3.

    Fosl argues: “Hume drew upon the Academica and De Natura Deorum in developing his own “Academical” philosophy of religion” (Fosl 1994, p. 104).

  4. 4.

    According to Jones, in the first year of his undergraduate studies at Edinburgh University, Hume learned, “Greek grammar, and the rules of rhetoric, with special reference to Cicero and Ramus.” (Jones 1982, p. 10).

  5. 5.

    For example, he refers to Terentia, Cicero’s first wife, perhaps to insinuate to his addressee, by analogy, that she is not behaving as well as he would wish (Letters, Vol. II, 8–11).

  6. 6.

    Interestingly, this idea is quite the opposite of Hume’s final remarks in the Dialogues, where he sides with the Epicureans, although, of course, he omits their idea that we should emulate the gods.

  7. 7.

    He argues this in the context of an assessment of Great Britain’s lack of grandiloquent oratory. For a good treatment of the ambiguities and the political implications of this essay, see: Potkay 1994, pp. 24–58.

  8. 8.

    I cite here the 1826 edition of Hume’s Essays since, unfortunately, the Liberty Fund edition overlooked this footnote.

  9. 9.

    As I show in this chapter, Kant considered Cicero as a Stoic in moral matters (VL-Jäsche, 31; VL-Vienna, 803).

  10. 10.

    Jones argues that “[…] explicit allusion [to Cicero] was often unnecessary since Cicero was the one classical writer familiar to and admired by almost every educated person in France and England in the late seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries.” (Jones 1982, p. 30).

  11. 11.

    I will refer to the influence of his metaphysical treatise De Fato, in this chapter, where I discuss Hume’s treatment of freedom in relation to Kant’s Antinomies.

  12. 12.

    See: Smith 1947, pp. 1–75; Penelhum 1979, pp. 253–278; Jones 1982, pp. 44–92; Price 1964, pp. 97–106; Gaskin 1978, pp. 209–231; Mossner 1936, pp. 334–349; Noxon 1964, pp. 248–261.

  13. 13.

    According to Pyle (2006, p. 4), this position is also shared by Colin Maclaurin, Newtonian mathematician and defender of natural theology.

  14. 14.

    See: Gaskin 1976, pp. 301–311, 1978, pp. 209–231; O’Connor 2001, p. 24; Penelhum 1979, p. 270; Price 1964, pp. 97–106.

  15. 15.

    According to Gaskin: “Hume distinguishes at least three species of “natural instincts” or essential “natural beliefs:” (1). Belief in the continuous existence of an external world independent of our perception. (2) Belief that the regularities, which have occurred in our experience, form a reliable guide to those which will occur. (3) Belief in the reliability of our senses […]. (Gaskin 1978, p. 116).

  16. 16.

    There is an interesting debate on this point. Gaskin claims that, given Hume’s views in the Natural History of Religion that there are atheistic communities, this belief cannot be universal. For M. Badía, however, Hume’s position in this text does not allow for such a clear-cut interpretation. He says: “While Hume appears to suggest that belief in an invisible and intelligent power is not strictly universal, he also recognizes in the same place that the “propensity to believe in an invisible, intelligent power” (NHR, 135) is a general tendency of human nature. In essence, Hume is conceding to this belief the universality that he seemed to deny it at the beginning of the work” (Badía 1996, p. 100, my translation). In fact, Badía’s quotation appears at the end of NHR, where Hume says that belief in God is not instinctive, although it does accompany human nature: “The universal propensity to believe in invisible, intelligent power, if not an original instinct, being at least a general attendant of human nature, may be considered as a kind of mark or stamp, which the divine workman has set upon his work.” (NHR, 135, my italics). On this basis, Badía claims that this belief is “natural” but not “instinctive.” (1996, pp. 96–109). However, at the beginning of the text, Hume had argued that, “this preconception springs not from an original instinct or primary impression of nature” (NHR, p. 125). Thus, despite the plausibility of Badía’s argument, I believe Gaskin’s view is more accurate.

  17. 17.

    The same reference to the skeptic as a nomad will appear in Kant (A IX).

  18. 18.

    There is yet a third thesis, advanced by Foley, according to which Philo is simply inconsistent and Hume wishes to portray him as such (2006, pp. 83–112).

  19. 19.

    Kant himself offers this interpretation in his Prolegomena: “For let us assume at the outset (as Hume in his Dialogues makes Philo grant Cleanthes), as a necessary hypothesis, the deistic concept of the First Being […]” (Ak. IV, 359).

  20. 20.

    I will not refer to the last point, namely the rejection of belief in the immortality of the soul, but an analysis of Hume’s essay “Of the Immortality of Soul” (E. 590–597) would easily confirm Hume’s deistic inclination.

  21. 21.

    As Gaskin claims, Hume’s apparently fideistic avowal at the end of the Enquiry, where he says that “whoever is moved by Faith to assent to it [Christian religion], is conscious of a continued miracle in his own person, which subverts all the principles of his understanding and gives him a determination to believe what is most contrary to custom and experience” (EHU X, 131) is, in reality, ironic, and cannot be seen as an endorsement of fideism. Hume’s views, expressed in Philo’s apparently pious “reversal,” are consistent with this passage’s irony.

  22. 22.

    However, he seems to have accepted “a tincture of deism” in his thought (Gaskin 1983, p. 168).

  23. 23.

    This very complaint can be found in other essays by Hume, such as “Of Suicide” (E. 493–502), “Of Superstition and Enthusiasm” (E. 98–103), and “Of the Immortality of the Soul” (E. 503–510).

Bibliography

  • Badía, Miguel A. 1996. La reflexión de David Hume en torno a la religión. San Juan: Editorial de la Universidad de Puerto Rico.

    Google Scholar 

  • Battersby, Christine. 1979. The Dialogues as Original Imitation: Cicero and the Nature of Hume’s Skepticism. In McGill Hume Studies, ed. D.F. Norton, N. Capaldi, and W.L. Robinson, 239–252. San Diego: Austin Hill Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blake, William. 1957. Complete Writings with Variant Readings, ed. G. Keynes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Ronald J. 1960. Natural Belief and the Enigma of Hume. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 42 (1): 73–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cicero, Marcus Tullius. 1997. De Officiis (On Duties). Trans. Walter Miller. Cambridge/London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. De Natura Deorum (On the Nature of the Gods). Trans. H. Rackham. Cambridge/London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001a. De Fato (On Fate). Trans. H. Rackham. Cambridge/London: Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001b. De Finibus (On Moral Ends). Trans. Julia Annas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006a. Academica (On Academic Scepticism). Trans. Charles Brittain. Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006b. De Divinatione (On Divination). Trans. D. Wardle. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foley, Rich. 2006. Unnatural Religion: Indoctrination and Philo’s Reversal in Hume’s Dialogues concerning Natural Religion. Hume Studies 32 (1): 83–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Force, James E. 1993. Biblical Interpretation, Newton and English Deism. In Scepticism and Irreligion in the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries, ed. Richard H. Popkin and Arjo J. Vanderjagt, 282–305. Leiden: E.J. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Samuel Clarke’s Four Categories of Deism, Isaac Newton, and the Bible. In Scepticism in the History of Philosophy: A Pan-American Dialogue, ed. Richard H. Popkin, 53–74. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fosl, Peter S. 1994. Doubt and Divinity: Cicero’s Influence on Hume’s Religious Skepticism. Hume Studies 20 (1): 103–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Hume, Skepticism, and Early American Deism. Hume Studies 25 (1–2): 171–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020. Hume’s Scepticism: Pyrrhonian and Academic. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaskin, John C.A. 1976. Hume’s Critique of Religion. Journal of the History of Philosophy 14 (3): 301–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1978. Hume’s Philosophy of Religion. London: Macmillan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1983. Hume’s Attenuated Deism. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 65: 160–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gay, Peter. 1968. Deism: An Anthology. Princeton: Van Nostrand Reinhold Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, W. 2009. The English Deists. Studies in Early Enlightenment. London: Pickering & Chatto.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, Wayne, Diego Lucci, and Jeffrey R. Wigelsworth, eds. 2014. Atheism and Deism Revalued. Heterodox Religious Identities in Britain, 1650–1800. London: Ashgate Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 1826. Of the Rise and Progress of the Arts and Sciences. In The Philosophical Works of David Hume, Vol. 3. Edinburgh: Adam Black and William Tait.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1896. A Tratise of Human Nature, ed. L.A. Selby-Bigge. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1902. Enquiries Concerning the Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. L.A. Selby-Bigge. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1932. The Letters of David Hume (Vol. I and II), ed. J.Y. Greig. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1985. Essays. Moral, Political and Literary. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007a. Dialogues concerning Natural Religion and Other Writings, ed. Dorothy Coleman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007b. Natural History of Religion. In Dialogues concerning Natural Religion and Other Writings, ed. Dorothy Coleman, 124–136. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, Peter. 1982. Hume’s Sentiments. Their Ciceronian and French Context. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1992. Lectures on Logic (VL). Trans. J. Michael Young. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Critique of the Power of Judgment (KU). Trans. Paul Guyer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics (P). Trans. G. Hartfield. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laird, John. 1932. Hume’s Philosophy of Human Nature. London: Methuen & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laird, John, Alfred Edward Taylor, and Thomas Edmund Jessop. 1939. The Present-Day Relevance of Hume’s Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 18: 179–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Livingston, Donald. 1998. Philosophical Melancholy and Delirium. Hume’s Pathology of Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1975. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maia Neto, Jose R. 1997. Academic Skepticism in Early Modern Philosophy. Journal of the History of Ideas 58 (2): 199–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mossner, Ernest Campbell. 1936. The Enigma of Hume. Mind 45 (179): 334–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, David Fate. 1991. Hume, Atheism, and the Autonomy of Morals. Taula 16: 29–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noxon, James. 1964. Hume’s Agnosticism. The Philosophical Review 73 (2): 248–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, David. 2001. Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Hume on Religion. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penelhum, Terence. 1979. Hume’s Skepticism and the Dialogues. In McGill Hume Studies, ed. D.F. Norton, N. Capaldi, and W.L. Robison, 253–278. San Diego: Austin Hill Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plutarch. 1967. Adversus Colotem (Reply to Colotes). In Moralia Vol. XIV. Trans. B. Einarson and P.H. De Lacy, 153–315. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potkay, Adam. 1994. The Fate of Eloquence in the Age of Hume. Ithaca/London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, John Vladimir. 1964. Sceptics in Cicero and Hume. Journal of the History of Ideas 25 (1): 97–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1965. The Ironic Hume. Austin: University of Texas Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, Graham. 1985. Hume’s Final Argument. History of Philosophy Quarterly 2 (3): 349–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pyle, Andrew. 2006. Hume’s Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion: Reader’s Guide. London/New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, Charles B. 1972. Cicero Scepticus: A Study of the Influence of the Academica in the Renaissance. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sextus, Empiricus. 2000. Pyrrhoniae Hypotyposes (Outlines of Scepticism), ed. Julia Annas and Jonathan Barnes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Norman Kemp. 1947. Introduction. In Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, ed. David Hume, 1–75. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tweyman, Stanley. 1986. Scepticism and Belief in Hume’s Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

González Quintero, C. (2022). Hume and Cicero on Metaphysics: Philo’s Non-Dogmatic Deism. In: Academic Skepticism in Hume and Kant. Synthese Library, vol 449. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-89750-5_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics