Skip to main content

Degree-Preserving Gödel Logics with an Involution: Intermediate Logics and (Ideal) Paraconsistency

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Outstanding Contributions to Logic ((OCTR,volume 21))

Abstract

In this paper, we study intermediate logics between the logic \({\mathrm {G}^{\le }_{\sim }}\), the degree-preserving companion of Gödel fuzzy logic with involution \(\mathrm {G}_\sim \), and classical propositional logic CPL, as well as the intermediate logics of their finite-valued counterparts \(\mathrm {G}^{\le }_{n\sim }\). Although \({\mathrm {G}^{\le }_{\sim }}\) and \(\mathrm {G}^{\le }_{n\sim }\) are explosive w.r.t. Gödel negation \(\lnot \), they are paraconsistent w.r.t. the involutive negation \(\sim \). We introduce the notion of saturated paraconsistency, a weaker notion than ideal paraconsistency, and we fully characterize the ideal and the saturated paraconsistent logics between \(\mathrm {G}^{\le }_{n\sim }\) and CPL. We also identify a large family of saturated paraconsistent logics in the family of intermediate logics for degree-preserving finite-valued Łukasiewicz logics.

This paper is a humble tribute to our friend and colleague Arnon Avron and his outstanding contributions on nonclassical logics, proof theory, and foundations of mathematics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Wansing and Odintsov (2016), p. 179.

  2. 2.

    Ibid., p. 180.

  3. 3.

    Ibid., p. 181.

  4. 4.

    Ibid., p. 181.

  5. 5.

    Ibid., p. 183.

  6. 6.

    It is worth noting that, more recently, the authors have changed the terminology “ideal paraconsistent logic” in Arieli et al. (2011b) to “fully maximal and normal paraconsistent logic,” e.g., in Avron et al. (2018). According to them, they choose the latter “to use a more neutral terminology” (see Avron et al. (2018, Footnote 9, p. 57)).

  7. 7.

    In fact, \({\mathrm {G}^{\le }_{\sim }}\) is then a paradefinite logic (w.r.t. \(\sim \)) in the sense of Arieli and Avron (2017), as it is both paraconsistent and paracomplete, since the law of excluded middle \(\varphi \vee {\sim }\varphi \) fails, as in all fuzzy logics. Logics with a negation which is both paraconsistent and paracomplete were already considered in the literature under different names: non-alethic logics (da Costa) and paranormal logics (Beziau).

  8. 8.

    This axiomatization comes from adding axiom (A7) to the axioms of Hájek’s BL logic (Hájek 1998). Later it was shown that axioms (A2) and (A3) were, in fact, redundant, see Běhounek (2011) for a detailed exposition and the references therein.

  9. 9.

    Called standard Gödel algebra.

  10. 10.

    These are the original axioms from Esteva et al. (2000), see again Běhounek (2011) and the references therein for a shorter axiomatization.

  11. 11.

    Equivalently, as the expansion of \(\mathrm{G}_n\) with \(\sim \) along with the axioms \((\sim 1)\)-\((\sim 3)\), \((\Delta 1)\)-\((\Delta 3)\), and the necessitation rule for \(\Delta \).

  12. 12.

    For practical purposes, we can assume in this paper that \(\mathrm {L}\) is an axiomatic extension of Hájek’s BL logic.

  13. 13.

    Given a class of Kripke models, a formula \(\varphi \) follows locally from a set \(\Gamma \) of formulas if, for any Kripke model M in the class and every world w in M, \(\varphi \) is true in \(\langle M,w\rangle \) whenever every formula in \(\Gamma \) is true in \(\langle M,w\rangle \) as well. On the other hand, \(\varphi \) follows globally from \(\Gamma \) in the class if, for every Kripke model M, \(\varphi \) is true in \(\langle M,w\rangle \) for every w whenever every formula in \(\Gamma \) is true in \(\langle M,w\rangle \) for every w.

  14. 14.

    For \(\mathrm {L} = \mathrm{G}_\sim \).

  15. 15.

    Recall that the finitary companion of a logic \((L, \vdash )\) is given by \((L, \vdash ^f)\) where, for every \(\Gamma \cup \{\varphi \} \subseteq L\), \(\Gamma \vdash ^f \varphi \) iff there exists a finite \(\Gamma _0 \subseteq \Gamma \) such that \(\Gamma _0 \vdash \varphi \).

  16. 16.

    In the following we use p and n to denote positive and negative values in [0, 1] with respect to the negation \(\sim x = 1-x\); in other words, \(p > 1/2\) and \(n < 1/2\).

  17. 17.

    In Avron (2016), the symbols \(\lnot \) and \(\rightarrow \) were used instead of \({\sim }\) and \(\rightarrow _\mathrm {FT}\). We adopt this notation in order to keep the notation of the present paper uniform.

  18. 18.

    Indeed, every formula \(\varphi \in Fm_\mathrm{FT}\) gets the value 1/2 in any evaluation e over \(\mathbf{M}_{[0,1]}\) such that e assigns the value 1/2 to any propositional variable occurring in \(\varphi \).

  19. 19.

    Recall that the \(\Delta \) connective is definable in any algebra \(\mathbf {\L } V_n\).

  20. 20.

    In fact, this is a discriminator term in the whole variety of \(\mathrm{G}_{\sim }\)-algebras. For a definition of discriminator term and discriminator variety, see Burris and Sankappanavar (1981).

  21. 21.

    A filter F of an algebra \(\mathbf{A}\) is compatible with a logic L if, whenever \(\Gamma \vdash _L \varphi \), the following holds: for every \(\mathbf{A}\)-evaluation e, if \(e(\gamma ) \in F\) for every \(\gamma \in \Gamma \) then \(e(\varphi ) \in F\).

  22. 22.

    Strictly speaking, this notation becomes ambiguous if n is not clear from the context and we identify rational numbers such as \(i/(n-1)\) and \(i.k/(n-1).k\), for instance, 1/2, 2/4, 3/6, and so on. In this case, the notation \(F_{\frac{1}{2}}\) is problematic, since it could denote any of an infinite sequence of different filters in \(GV_3\), \(GV_5\), \(GV_7\),...  respectively. The right notation for order filters in \(GV_n\) should be \(F^n_t\). However, the superscript n will be avoided when there is no risk of confusion.

  23. 23.

    The authors, as it was mentioned in Sect. 6.1, have changed the terminology “ideal paraconsistent logic” to “fully maximal and normal paraconsistent logic.” However, it should be noticed that being normal, according to Avron et al. (2018, Definition 1.32), means that the logic L has, besides a deductive implication, a conjunction and a disjunction satisfying the usual properties in terms of consequence relations. Here we decide to keep the original definition of ideal paraconsistency. It is worth noting that all the ideal (and saturated) logics considered in this paper and in Coniglio et al. (2019) are normal in the sense of Avron et al. (2018).

  24. 24.

    Observe that in Coniglio et al. (2019), \(\lnot \) denotes the Łukasiewicz negation, while the Gödel negation for \(\mathsf {J}_3\) and \(\mathsf {J}_4\) is, respectively, denoted by \(\sim ^1_2\) and \(\sim ^1_3\).

  25. 25.

    Using the terminology of Avron et al. (2018), a saturated paraconsistent logic is a logic such that: (i) it has an implication, (ii) it is F-contained in CPL, and (iii) it is strongly maximal.

  26. 26.

    This was denoted by \(L \in \mathbf{Triv}_\Theta \bot \{r\}\) in Ribeiro and Coniglio (2012), where \(\mathbf{Triv}_\Theta \) denotes the trivial logic over the signature \(\Theta \).

  27. 27.

    Indeed, by means of the notion of remainder set \(L \bot R\) of a logic L w.r.t. a set of rules R introduced in Ribeiro and Coniglio (2012, Definition 7), several concepts relative to maximality proposed in the literature can be easily represented, see Ribeiro and Coniglio (2012, p. 273).

  28. 28.

    An algebra is said to be critical if it is a finite algebra not belonging to the quasivariety generated by all its proper subalgebras.

  29. 29.

    This is the case of any pseudo-complemented logic L where \(\Delta \) is definable as \(\Delta \varphi := \lnot {\sim }\varphi \), in particular, the case of Gödel fuzzy logic \(\mathrm {G}\).

References

  • Arieli, O., & Avron, A. (2017). Four-valued paradefinite logics. Studia Logica, 105(6), 1087–1122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arieli, O., Avron, A., & Zamansky, A. (2010). Maximally paraconsistent three-valued logics. In F. Lin, et al. (Eds.), Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning: Proc. of the Twelfth International Conference, (KR 2010) (pp. 9–13). AAAI Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arieli, O., Avron, A., & Zamansky, A. (2011a). Maximal and premaximal paraconsistency in the framework of three-valued semantics. Studia Logica, 97(1), 31–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arieli, O., Avron, A., & Zamansky, A. (2011b). Ideal paraconsistent logics. Studia Logica, 99(1–3), 31–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avron, A. (2005). Non-deterministic matrices and modular semantics of rules. In J.-Y. Beziau (Ed.), Logica Universalis (pp. 149–167). Birkhäuser Basel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avron, A. (2007). Non-deterministic semantics for logics with a consistency operator. International Journal of Approximate Reasoning, 45, 271–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Avron, A. (2009). Modular semantics for some basic logics of formal inconsistency. In W. A. Carnielli, M. E. Coniglio, & I. M. L. D’ Ottaviano (Eds.), The Many Sides of Logic (Vol. 21, pp. 15–26), Studies in Logic. College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avron, A. (2016). Paraconsistent fuzzy logic preserving non-falsity. Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 292, 75–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Avron, A. (2017). Self-extensional three-valued paraconsistent logics. Logica Universalis, 11(3), 297–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Avron, A. (2019). Paraconsistency and the need for infinite semantics. Soft Computing, 23, 2167–2175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Avron, A., Arieli, O., & Zamansky, A. (2010). On strong maximality of paraconsistent finite-valued logics. In Proceedings of the 25th Annual IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science, LICS 2010, 11-14 July 2010, Edinburgh, United Kingdom (pp. 304–313). IEEE Computer Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avron, A., Arieli, O., & Zamansky, A. (2018). Theory of Effective Propositional Paraconsistent Logics (Vol. 75), Studies in Logic. College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avron, A., & Lev, I. (2001). Canonical propositional Gentzen-type systems. In Proceedings of the 1st International Joint Conference on Automated Reasoning (IJCAR 2001) (Vol. 2083, pp. 529–544), LNAI. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avron, A., & Zamansky, A. (2011). Non-deterministic semantics for logical systems–a survey. In D. M. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic (2nd ed., Vol. 16, pp. 227–304). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Běhounek, L., Cintula, P., & Hájek, P. (2011). Introduction to mathematical fuzzy logic. In P. Cintula, P. Hájek, & C. Noguera (Eds.), Handbook of Mathematical Fuzzy Logic – volume 1, Studies in Logic, Mathematical Logic and Foundations (Vol. 37, pp. 1–101). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P., de Rijke, M., & Venema, Y. (2002). Modal Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blok, W.J., & Pigozzi, D. (2001). Abstract algebraic logic and the deduction theorem. http://www.math.iastate.edu/dpigozzi/papers/aaldedth.pdf

  • Blok, W. J., & Pigozzi, D. (1991). Local deduction theorems in algebraic logic. In Algebraic logic (Budapest, 1988) (Vol. 54, pp. 75–109), Colloq. Math. Soc. János Bolyai. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bou, F., Esteva, F., Font, J. M., Gil, A., Godo, L., Torrens, A., et al. (2009). Logics preserving degrees of truth from varieties of residuated lattices. Journal of Logic and Computation, 19(6), 1031–1069.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burris, S., & Sankappanavar, H. P. (1981). A Course in Universal Algebra. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carnielli, W. A., & Coniglio, M. E. (2016). Paraconsistent logic: consistency, contradiction and negation. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science (Vol. 40). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnielli, W. A., Coniglio, M. E., & Marcos, J. (2007). Logics of formal inconsistency. In D. M. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic (2nd ed., Vol. 14, pp. 1–93). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnielli, W. A., & Marcos, J. (2002). A taxonomy of C-systems. In W. A. Carnielli, M. E. Coniglio, & I. M. L. D’Ottaviano (Eds.), Paraconsistency: The Logical Way to the Inconsistent. Proceedings of the 2nd World Congress on Paraconsistency (WCP 2000) (Vol. 228, pp. 1–94), Lecture Notes in Pure and Applied Mathematics. New York: Marcel Dekker.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coniglio, M. E., Esteva, F., & Godo, L. (2014). Logics of formal inconsistency arising from systems of fuzzy logic. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 22(6), 880–904.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coniglio, M. E., Esteva, F., & Godo, L. (2016). On the set of intermediate logics between truth and degree preserving Łukasiewicz logic. Logical Journal of the IGPL, 24(3), 288–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coniglio, M. E., Esteva, F., Gispert, J., & Godo, L. (2019). Maximality in finite-valued Łukasiewicz Logics defined by order filters. Journal of Logic and Computation, 29(1), 125–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ertola, R. C., Esteva, F., Flaminio, T., Godo, L., & Noguera, C. (2015). Paraconsistency properties in degree-preserving fuzzy logics. Soft Computing, 19(3), 531–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esteva, Francesc, & Godo, Lluís. (2001). Monoidal t-norm based logic: Towards a logic for left-continuous t-norms. Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 124(3), 271–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esteva, F., Godo, L., Hájek, P., & Navara, M. (2000). Residuated fuzzy logics with an involutive negation. Archive for Mathematical Logic, 39, 103–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esteva, F., Godo, L., & Marchioni, E. (2011). Fuzzy Logics with Enriched Language. In P. Cintula, P. Hájek, & C. Noguera (Eds.), Handbook of Mathematical Fuzzy Logic, Vol. II, Chap. VIII (Vol. 38, pp. 627–711), Studies in Logic, Mathematical Logic and Foundations. College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Font, J. M. (2009). Taking degrees of truth seriously. Studia Logica, 91(3), 383–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Font, J. M., Gil, A., Torrens, A., & Verdú, V. (2006). On the infinite-valued Łukasiewicz logic that preserves degrees of truth. Archive for Mathematical Logic, 45, 839–868.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gispert, J., & Torrens, A. (2014). Locally finite quasivarieties of MV-algebras (pp. 1–14). arXiv:1405.7504.

  • Hájek, P. (1998). Metamathematics of Fuzzy Logic (Vol. 4), Trends in Logic. Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odintsov, S. P. (2008). Constructive Negations and Paraconsistency (Vol. 26), Trends in Logic. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ribeiro, M. M., & Coniglio, M. E. (2012). Contracting logics. In L. Ong & R. de Queiroz (Eds.), Logic, Language, Information and Computation. WoLLIC 2012 (Vol. 7456, pp. 268–281)., Lecture Notes in Computer Science Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wansing, H., & Odintsov, S. P. (2016). On the Methodology of Paraconsistent Logic. In H. Andreas & P. Verdée (Eds.), Logical Studies of Paraconsistent Reasoning in Science and Mathematics (Vol. 45, pp. 175–204), Trends in Logic. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors are indebted to two anonymous reviewers for their careful and insightful suggestions and remarks that have definitively helped to improve the paper. Coniglio acknowledges support from the National Council for Scientific and Technological Development (CNPq), Brazil, under research grant 306530/2019-8. Gispert acknowledges partial support by the Spanish FEDER/MINECO projects (PID2019-110843GA-100, MTM2016-74892 and MDM-2014-044) and grant 2017-SGR-95 of Generalitat de Catalunya. Esteva and Godo acknowledge partial support by the Spanish FEDER/MINECO project TIN2015-71799-C2-1-P and the project PID2019-111544GB-C21.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lluis Godo .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Coniglio, M.E., Esteva, F., Gispert, J., Godo, L. (2021). Degree-Preserving Gödel Logics with an Involution: Intermediate Logics and (Ideal) Paraconsistency. In: Arieli, O., Zamansky, A. (eds) Arnon Avron on Semantics and Proof Theory of Non-Classical Logics. Outstanding Contributions to Logic, vol 21. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-71258-7_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics