Skip to main content
Log in

Signs and Instruments: The Convergence of Aristotelian and Kantian Intuitions in Biosemiotics

  • Published:
Biosemiotics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Biosemiotics—a discipline in the process of becoming established as a new research enterprise—faces a double task. On the one hand it must carry out the theoretical and experimental investigation of an enormous range of semiotic phenomena relating organisms to their internal components and to other organisms (e.g., signal transduction, replication, codes, etc.). On the other hand, it must achieve a philosophical re-conceptualization and generalization of theoretical biology in light of the essential role played by semiotic notions in biological explanation and modeling. This paper attempts to contribute to the second task by tracing some aspects of the historical evolution of explanatory models in biology. In so doing, a parallel can be drawn between the present status of biosemiotics and that of physics during the early decades of the last century. By following the career of the concept instrument (organon) in Aristotelian science, we revisit historical stages of the antithetical (but often complementary) roles of mechanical and teleological forms of explanation. The impact of the introduction of the organic codes in biology is seen to be somewhat analogous to that of the introduction of the quantum of action in physics. Faced with intractable empirical facts, physicists combined experimental results and bold philosophical speculation to create quantum physics—a wider, deeper framework that accommodates the new facts through a wholesale reformulation of the classical ideas. Essential to this development was the articulation of the epistemic functions of instruments, which was absent from classical physics. Similarly, the consideration of the role of instruments in biology may lead to a synthesis of Aristotelian and Kantian intuitions within a wider framework capable of joining now separate perspectives, such as Jablonka’s four-fold view of inheritance information, Barbieri’s theory of artifactual copymakers and codemakers, and recently developed models of causation based on the idea of manipulative interventions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Abner Shimony calls this self-referential phenomenon an “epistemic circle” in analogy with the “hermeneutic circle” of phenomenology. See, for instance, Shimony (1993). Michel Bitbol has advanced the discussion of the semiotic import of epistemic circles, extending ideas first proposed by Bohr and Heisenberg to current self-organizational theories of cognition. See Bitbol (1996, 2001).

  2. Here I view these external organs as mechanisms in the traditional sense, as structures that transmit efficient causation unidirectionally. See Machamer et al. (2000). Some authors extend this notion to include causal loops. See Bechtel (2007).

  3. This tradition has found echoes inter alia in the self-reproducing automata of John von Neumann (1966), the work of Robert Rosen (1991), the autopoiesis of Humberto Maturana and Francisco Varela (1980) and the autocatalytic networks of Stuart Kauffman (1993).

  4. The relationships between mechanical and teleological explanations in Kant’s thought are complex and subtle. This topic is treated in several papers on Kant and biology that appeared in a single issue of the journal Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences (Volume 37, Issue 4, December 2006). See e.g., Steigerwald (2006); Walsh (2006).

  5. Hulswit’s monograph advances a clarification of the relations between semiosis and traditional types of causal determination, but some points remain obscure. See Hulswit (2002). Deely finds support on late scholastic analyses of these relations to show that Peirce at times conflates some forms of teleology with other forms of “ideal” causation, in particular semiotic determination, which would rather fall under the rubric of formal causation. See e.g., Deely (2001, 2007).

  6. Another version of this characterization, from a letter to Lady Welby, is found in Peirce (1998), 477.

  7. See for instance Barbieri (2005, 2007).

References

  • Aristotle (Jonathan Barnes, Ed.) (1984). The complete works of Aristotle: The revised Oxford translation. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.

  • Barbieri, M. (2003). The organic codes: An introduction to semantic biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbieri, M. (2005). Life is “artifact-making.”. Journal of Biosemiotics, 1(1), 81–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbieri, M. (Ed.) (2007). Introduction to biosemiotics. Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Barbieri, M. (Ed.) (2008). The codes of life. The rules of macroevolution. New York, N.Y.: Springer.

  • Bechtel, W. (2007). Biological mechanisms: Organized to maintain autonomy. In F. C. Boogerd et al.

  • Bitbol, M. (1996). Mécanique quantique, une introduction philosophique. Paris: Flammarion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bitbol, M. (2001). Non-representationalist theories of knowledge and quantum mechanics. SATS (Nordic Journal of Philosophy), 2, 37–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, N. (1933). Light and life. Nature, 25 Mar. 1933, 133:421–423 (Pt. 1), 1 Apr. 1933, 133:457–459 (Pt.2).

  • De Tienne, A. (2006). Peirce’s logic of information. Seminario del Grupo de Estudios Peirceanos. Universidad de Navarra, 28 de Septiembre del 2006. http://www.unav.es/gep/SeminariodeTienne.html. Accessed 2 April 2008.

  • Deacon, T., & Sherman, J. (2007). The physical origins of purposive systems. In J. M. Krois et al. (Eds.) (pp. 3–25).

  • Deely, J. N. (2001). Physiosemiosis in the semiotic spiral: A play of musement. Signs Systems Studies, 29(1), 27–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deely, J. N. (2007). Intentionality and semiotics: A story of mutual fecundation. Scranton: University of Scranton Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delbrück, M. (1971). Aristotle-totle-totle. In Of microbes and life (pp. 50–55). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernández, E. (1993). From Peirce to Bohr: Theorematic reasoning and idealization in physics. In E.C. Moore (Ed.), Charles S. Peirce and the philosophy of science: Papers from the Harvard Sesquicentennial Congress (pp. 233–245). Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press.

  • Folse, H. J. (1990). Complementarity and the description of nature in biological science. Biology and Philosophy, 5(2), 221–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Funkenstein, A. (1986). Theology and the scientific imagination from the middle ages to the seventeenth century. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hulswit, M. (2002). From cause to causation. A Peircean perspective. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. J. (2005). Evolution in four dimensions. Boston: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. R. (2005). Aristotle on teleology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (Paul Guyer, Ed.) (2000). Critique of the power of judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kauffman, S. (1993). The origins of order: Self-organization and selection in evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S., Logan, R. K., Este, R., Goebel, R., Hobill, D., & Shmulevich, I. (2008). Propagating organization: An enquiry. Biology & Philosophy, 23(1), 27–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koyama, C. (Ed.) (2000). Nature in medieval thought: Some approaches East & West. Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters. Leiden: Brill.

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H., & Varela, F. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living. In R.S. Cohen, & M.W. Wartofsky (Eds.), Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 42. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKaughan, D. J. (2005). The influence of Niels Bohr on Max Delbrück: revisiting the hopes inspired by “Light and Life.”. Isis, 96, 507–529.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C.S. (1998). In The essential Peirce: Selected philosophical writings. Volume 2 (1893–1913). Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1991). Life itself: A comprehensive inquiry into the nature, origin, and fabrication of life. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shimony, A. (1993). Search for a naturalistic world view, Volume I, Scientific method and epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steigerwald, J. (2006). Kant’s concept of natural purpose and the reflecting power of judgment. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 37(4), 712–734.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van de Vijver, G. (2006). Kant and the intuitions of self-organization. In B. Feltz et al. (Eds), (pp. 143–161).

  • Von Neumann, J. (A.W. Burks, Ed.). (1966). Theory of self-reproducing automata. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

  • Walsh, D. M. (2006). Organisms as natural purposes: The contemporary perspective. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 37(4), 771–791.

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eliseo Fernández.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Fernández, E. Signs and Instruments: The Convergence of Aristotelian and Kantian Intuitions in Biosemiotics. Biosemiotics 1, 347–359 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-008-9011-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-008-9011-7

Keywords

Navigation