Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Teaching the Philosophical and Worldview Components of Science

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A common feature of contemporary science education curricula is the expectation that as well as learning science content, students will learn something about science—its nature, its history, how it differs from non-scientific endeavours, and its interactions with culture and society. These curricular pronouncements provide an ‘open cheque’ for the inclusion of history and philosophy of science in science teacher education programmes, and for their utilisation in classrooms. Unfortunately this open cheque is too often not cashed. This paper will discuss an important aspect of the contribution of science to culture, namely its role in the development of worldviews in society. A case study of the adjustments to a central Roman Catholic doctrine occasioned by the metaphysics of Atomism which was embraced at the Scientific Revolution will be presented. Options for the reconciliation of seemingly conflicting scientific and religious worldviews are laid out, and it is claimed that as far as liberal education is concerned, the important thing is to have students first recognise what are the options, and then carefully examine them to come to their own conclusions about reconciliation or otherwise.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The basic statement is in AAAS 1989, chap. 12; 1993 chap. 12. Good (2005) amplifies the AAAS position and argues for incompatibility between scientific and religious habits of mind; Gauld (2005) defends the compatibility of the two outlooks.

  2. Two good books on this theme are Brody and Brody (1997) and Crease (2003). Some of the educational and historiographical debates concerning the use of history of science in science programmes are discussed in Matthews (1994, chap. 4).

  3. The integrative possibilities of a historically-informed science curriculum are discussed in Matthews (2000a, pp. 10–18).

  4. William Cobern (1991, 1996) canvasses much of the literature on this matter.

  5. Nehru embraced Western Enlightenment ideals whilst studying science in England. At Indian Independence he sought, just as Jefferson had done at the independence of the United States, to embody these secular, scientific, Enlightenment ideals in the Indian constitution. He called them the ‘scientific temper’. In 1981, the Nehru Centre in Bombay published a booklet with this title, jointly authored by the leaders of Indian educational, scientific and industrial fields.

  6. Notoriously Constructivism is the most recent fad that has caused immense educational damage across a swathe of countries where teachers and administrators have fallen under its influence. On this matter see Matthews (1995, 2000b) and contributions to Matthews (1998b).

  7. Some useful studies on the philosophical dimension of science are Smart (1968), Wartofsky (1968), Buchdahl (1969), Amsterdamski (1975), Trusted (1991), and Dilworth (2006).

  8. The famous Paul Arthur Schilpp anthology of commentary on Einstein is titled Albert Einstein: Philosopher—Scientist (Schilpp 1951).

  9. See for instance: Boltzmann, Theoretical Physics and Philosophical Problems (1905/1974), Helmholtz’s Science & Culture (1995), Mach’s The Science of Mechanics (1893/1960), Duhem’s The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory (1906/1954), Planck’s Where is Science Going? (1932), Eddington’s The Philosophy of Physical Science (1939), Jean’s Physics and Philosophy (1943/1981), Bohr Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge (1958), Heisenberg Physics and Philosophy (1962), Schrödinger My View of the World (1964), Born My Life & My Views (1968), and Bohm Wholeness and the Implicate Order (1980).

  10. See for instance: Bridgman Reflections of a Physicist (1950), Margenau The Nature of Physical Reality (1950), Rabi Science the Centre of Culture (Rabi 1967), Bunge Philosophy of Science (Bunge 1998), Chandrasekhar Truth and Beauty (Chandrasekhar 1987), Campbell What Is Science?, (Campbell 1921/1952), Holton Thematic Origins of Scientific Thought (Holton 1973), Cushing Philosophical Concepts in Physics (Cushing 1998), Rohrlich From Paradox to Reality (Rohrlich 1987), Shimony Search for a Naturalistic World View (Shimony 1993) and Weinberg Facing Up: Science and Its Cultural Adversaries (Weinberg 2001).

  11. Beyond the substantial and careful writers listed above it needs to be acknowledged that there is a veritable legion of insubstantial and careless writers whose books are nevertheless best sellers. These authors simply muddy the waters, and bring discredit to the programme of understanding the overlap of science and philosophy.

  12. See, for instance, Susan Stebbing’s classic critique of the idealist philosophical conclusions drawn by Jeans and Eddington (Stebbing 1937/1958). See also Mario Bunge’s critiques of the idealist and subjectivist conclusions drawn from quantum mechanics by Bohm, Bohr and many proponents of the Copenhagen school (Bunge 1967).

  13. For further discussion of the role of philosophy in science teaching, see Matthews (1994, chap. 5).

  14. For discussion of values in science see Graham (1981), Resnik (1998), Lacey (2005), and contributions to Koertge (2005).

  15. For discussion of these political dimensions of science, see contributions to Jacob (1994).

  16. Some classics are Hempel (1966), Nagel (1961), Popper (1934/1959), and Scheffler (1963). It can be argued that their logical empiricist convictions resulted in them giving wrong answers to some questions, but they were perceptive in identifying the questions and rigorous in articulating answers, and this is what good philosophy is all about. See also recent texts such as Godfrey-Smith (2003), Bird (1998), Ladyman (2002); and anthologies such as Lange (2007) or Balashov and Rosenberg (2002).

  17. A look at the appalling reasoning ability of students who have studied science for six or more years is enough to dispel any laxity about the achievement of ‘routine’ philosophical competencies. All of the standard logical fallacies are regularly repeated by students in scientific reasoning tasks, and more regularly repeated in their reasoning on non-scientific topics (Matthews 1994, pp. 88–93).

  18. In one especially appalling publication, one of the most cited and most awarded of current science educators boasts that 18/24 of his students at the end of a one semester course converted from realism to constructivism which he described as ‘the most mature epistemological theory’. On this matter of indoctrination, and its implications for teaching and learning about the Nature of Science, see Matthews (1998a).

  19. Mach’s argument is discussed in Matthews (1990) and Scheffler’s argument is discussed in Matthews (1997).

  20. See the elaborate and informative discussion in Buckley (1971).

  21. The classic works on medieval impetus theory are Moody (1975) and Clagett (1959).

  22. The classic treatment is Clavelin (1974).

  23. See Hanson (1965) and Ellis (1965) for excellent discussion of Newton’s formulation of inertia.

  24. Among numerous histories of inertia, a useful one with pedagogical import is Coelho (2007).

  25. The classic discussion of the interaction of physics and metaphysics in formulation of action-at-a-distance laws is Mary Hesse’s Forces and Fields (Hesse 1961), where chapter XI is titled ‘The Metaphysical Framework of Physics’.

  26. See Bunge (2000) for discussion of the metaphysical commitments required to justify the conservation of energy principle.

  27. See discussion in Matthews (1994, pp. 60–70).

  28. See discussion in Sober (1984).

  29. As well as countless books, there are specialised academic journals dealing with philosophy of physics, philosophy of chemistry, and philosophy of biology.

  30. A lot is written on the history of science in Islamic culture, and contemporary engagements between the two; see for example Hoodbhoy (1991).

  31. For the varieties of medieval and renaissance Aristotelianisms, see Schmitt (1983).

  32. On the doctrines and history of Scholastic philosophy see De Wulf (1903/1956).

  33. Sadly this description, sans Church, fitted philosophy departments in most of the former communist states, and still fits philosophy departments in many Islamic states.

  34. On the life and philosophy of Aquinas see Gilson (1929), Copleston (1955), Weisheipl (1974) and Kenny (1980).

  35. See discussion and texts in Matthews (1989).

  36. For historical and philosophical elaboration of the mechanical world view see Dijksterhuis (1961/1986), Harré (1964), and Westfall (1971).

  37. See Locke’s Essay Concerning Human Understanding Book II Chap. 8 (Locke 1689/1924, pp. 64–73).

  38. On ancient, medieval and modern theories of matter, see contributions to McMullin (1963a, b).

  39. Desmond Clarke provides a corrective to the common view, when he writes: ‘I interpret the extant writings of Descartes as the output of a practising scientist who, somewhat unfortunately, wrote a few short and relatively unimportant philosophical essays’ (Clark 1982, p. 2).

  40. For Descartes’ early education see Gaukroger 1995, chaps. 1, 2.

  41. Ibid chap. 3.

  42. In his Discourse on Method he says that ‘I will say nothing of philosophy except that it has been studied for many centuries by the most outstanding minds without having produced anything which is not in dispute and consequently doubtful’ (Descartes 1637/1960, p. 8). For an intellectual biography of Descartes that pays detailed attention to his Scholastic philosophical education see Gaukroger (1995); for Descartes’ philosophy of science see Clarke (1982).

  43. Descartes held a modified Atomism, in as much as he did not believe in a void; for him a plenum occupied the void of the ancient atomists. See discussion in Pullman (1998, pp. 157–163).

  44. Numerous works are available on Newton’s philosophy and metaphysics, among them are McMullin (1978), Stein (2002), McGuire (1995) and Hughes (1990). Although an atomist, Newton distanced himself from Descartes’ interpretation of the theory.

  45. For Newton’s early scientific and philosophical formation see Herivel (1965).

  46. On the history of Atomism and its connections with science on the one hand and with philosophy on the other, see Pyle (1997) and Pullman (1998). An older historical study that concentrates more on the philosophical side of Atomism is Melsen (1952).

  47. There are many good accounts of the modification, and eventual breakdown, of the mechanical worldview. See especially Harman (1982, chap. 6), Einstein and Infeld (1938, chap. 2).

  48. There are countless books on the worldview of modern physics: see for example, contributions to Cushing and McMullin (1989), especially Abner Shimony’s contribution ‘Search for a Worldview Which Can Accommodate Our Knowledge of Microphysics’. See also the contributions to the special issue of Science & Education dealing with Quantum Theory and Philosophy (vol. 12 nos. 5–6, 2003).

  49. See for instance Porter (2000), Israel (2001) and Brooke (1991, chap. V).

  50. A translation of the deposition, and discussion, is also available in Finocchiaro (1989, pp. 202–204).

  51. This contention echoed through all Catholic teaching, and devotional practice, right to the present day. As one Catholic Handbook states the matter: ‘The Catholic belief is that the sacrifice of the Mass is the sacrifice of the body and blood of Christ under the form of bread and wine’ (Lucey 1915, p. 93).

  52. One hundred years after Priestley’s complaints to Boscovich, Joseph McCabe, a former Franciscan priest and professor of philosophy who left the Church in the 1890s, well described the state of Roman Catholic theology when he said of his theological training that:

    The various points of dogma which are contained (or supposed to be contained) in Scripture, were first selected by the Fathers, and developed, generally by the aid of the Neo-Platonic philosophy, into formidable structures. The schoolmen completed the synthesis with the aid of Peripatetic philosophy, and elaborated the whole into a vast scheme which they called theology. (McCabe 1912, p. 73)

  53. On John Paul II’s encyclical and how it reviewed and revised the status of Thomism, see Ernst (2006).

  54. Concerning early 20th-century academic philosophy in Colombia, Daniel Restrepo wrote: ‘To the extent that the Columbian State was governed by theocratic criteria, philosophy, conceived as “servant of theology”, played the role of ideological mediator in the political action and principles of those who had held power since 1886’ (Restrepo 2003, p. 144). Being able to ‘prove’ the falsity of positivism, determinism, and evolutionism was a requirement for entry to university!

    The English philosopher Anthony Kenny gives a depressing account of comparable pseudo-philosophy being practised in the Roman ecclesiastical universities through to the 1960s (Kenny 1985)

  55. The last is of particular significance because it did put modern science centre-stage in its articulation of the ‘perennial philosophy’. For an account of the Lyceum’s principles and publications see the Introductory essay in Weisheipl (1961), also Ashley (1991). For examples of the kind of applied natural philosophy that it promoted see contributions to Kane et al. (1953).

  56. There are many accounts of the mixed fortunes of 20th-century Thomism. For an account of the dominant individuals and strands, see John (1966); for reflections on the future of Thomism see Clarke (1968), Weisheipl (1968) and Lonergan (1974).

  57. See the first volume of his three-volume The Career of Philosophy where he says ‘What is clear is that the central themes of modern philosophy have been the grappling with science and with individualistic values’ (Randall 1962, p. 22).

  58. Atomism, as an ontology, came from outside science (natural philosophy), it was a philosophical position developed by the Greek pre-Socratics, notably Democritus and Epicurus; but it was adopted by the New Science, and derived its strength and credibility from the success of its scientific adherents.

  59. For representative literature on this topic of ‘Christian Philosophy’ see Trethowan (1954) and Tresmontant (1965). For discussion of the suitability of Thomism as a vehicle for the interpretation of Christian doctrine, see McInerny (1966) and Weisheipl (1968).

  60. See Graham (1973), Joravsky (1970), Lecourt (1977) and Soyfer (1994).

  61. There has been debate about just what degree of proof a factual scientific claim needs to have before it triggers a revision in a competing factual religious claim—Augustine thought revision was needed only in the face of absolutely proven ‘scientific’ claims. The details of this debate do not bear on the present argument; for the arguments, and the debate’s literature, see McMullin (2005).

  62. John Polkinghorne could be picked out as an exemplar of a research physicist and believer, indeed he is an Anglican priest (Polkinghorne 1988, 1991, 1996). Many such individuals can be found contributing to journals such as Zygon: Journal of Religion & Science. For just one compilation of contemporary Christian scientists, see Mott (1991). There are comparable compilations of Hindu, Islamic, Mormon, and Judaic scientists. There may even be compilations of Scientologist scientists, and Christian Science scientists. These lists are relevant to the question of the psychological compatibility between scientific and religious beliefs, but not their philosophical or rational compatibility.

  63. See extensive discussion and bibliography in Martin (1991).

  64. These educational goals should not just be the responsibility of the science teacher; they should be realised by informed and competent curricula coordination across the subjects of science, philosophy and history.

References

  • Adler MJ (1978) Aristotle for everybody. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS) (1989) Project 2061: science for all Americans. AAAS, Washington, DC. Also published by Oxford University Press, 1990

  • American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS) (1990) The Liberal Art of Science: Agenda for Action. AAAS, Washington, DC

  • American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS) (1993) Benchmarks for Science Literacy. Oxford University Press, New York

  • Amsterdamski S (1975) Between experience and metaphysics. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashley BM (1991) The river forest school and the philosophy of nature today. In: Long RJ (ed) Philosophy and the god of Abraham. Essays in memory of James A. Weisheipl, OP. Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, Toronto, pp 1–15

    Google Scholar 

  • Balashov Y, Rosenberg A (eds) (2002) Philosophy of science: contemporary readings. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergmann P (1949) Basic theories of physics. Prentice-Hall, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernal JD (1939) The social function of science. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Birch LC (1990) On purpose. University of New South Wales Press, Sydney

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird A (1998) Philosophy of science. McGill-Queen’s University Press, Montreal & Kingston

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohm D (1980) Wholeness and the implicate order. Ark Paperbacks, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohr N (1958) Atomic physics and human knowledge. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Boltzmann L 1905/1974, Theoretical physics and philosophical problems. Reidel, Dordrecht

  • Born M (1968) My life & my views. Scribners, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan SO’F (1961) The meaning of “Nature” in the Aristotelian philosophy of nature. In: Weisheipl JA (ed) The dignity of science: studies in the philosophy of science presented to William Humbert Kane O.P. The Thomist Press, pp 247–265

  • Bridgman PW (1950) Reflections of a physicist. Philosophical Library, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Brody DE, Arnold R (1997) The science class you wish you had: the seven greatest scientific discoveries in history and the people who made them. Allen & Unwin, Melbourne

  • Brooke JH (1991) Science and religion: some historical perspectives. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchdahl G (1969) Metaphysics and the philosophy of science. Basil Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckley MJ (1971) Motion and motion’s god. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge M (1967) Analogy in quantum mechanics: from insight to nonsense. Br J Philos Sci 18:265–286

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge M (1998) Philosophy of science, 2 vols. Transaction Publishers, New Brunswick, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge M (2000) Energy: between physics and metaphysics. Sci & Educ 9(5):457–461

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell NR (1921/1952) What is science? Dover, New York

  • Chandrasekhar S (1987) Truth and beauty: aesthetics and motivations in science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Clagett M (1959) The science of mechanics in the middle ages. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison WI

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke DM (1982) Descartes’ philosophy of science. Manchester University Press, Manchester

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke WN (1968) The future of thomism. In: McInerny RM (ed) New themes in Christian philosophy. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, pp 187–207

    Google Scholar 

  • Clavelin M (1974) The natural philosophy of Galileo. Essay on the origin and formation of classical mechanics. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobern WW (1991) Word view theory and science education research, National Association for Research in Science Teaching, Manhattan, KS

  • Cobern WW (1996) Worldview theory and conceptual change in science education. Sci Educ 80(5):579–610

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coelho RL (2007) The law of inertia: how understanding its history can improve physics teaching. Sci & Educ 16(9–10):955–974

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collingwood RG (1945) The idea of nature. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Copleston FC (1955) Aquinas. Penguin Books, Harmondsworth

    Google Scholar 

  • Crease RP (2003) The prism and the pendulum: the ten most beautiful experiments in science. Random House, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Cushing JT (1998) Philosophical concepts in physics: the historical relation between philosophy and scientific theories. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Cushing JT, McMullin E (eds) (1989) Philosophical consequences of quantum theory. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, IN

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (2006) The god delusion. Bantam Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • De Wulf M (1903/1956) An Introduction to Scholastic Philosophy: Medieval and Modern (trans: Coffey P). Dover Publications, New York

  • Dennett DC (1995) Darwin’s dangerous idea: evolution and the meanings of life. Allen Lane, Penguin Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes R (1637/1960) Discourse on Method (trans: Lafleur LJ). Bobbs-Merrill, Indianapolis

  • Descartes R (1644/1983) Principles of Philosophy (trans: Miller VR, RP). Reidel, Dordrecht

  • Dewey J (1910) Science as subject-matter and as method. Science 31:121–127. Reproduced in Sci & Educ (1995) 4(4):391–398

    Google Scholar 

  • Dijksterhuis EJ (1961/1986) The mechanization of the world picture. Princeton University Press, Princeton NJ

  • Dillenberger J (1961) Protestant thought & natural science: a historical study. Collins, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Dilworth C (2006) The metaphysics of science. An account of modern science in terms of principles, laws and theories, 2nd edn. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem P (1906/1954) The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory (trans: Wiener PP). Princeton University Press, Princeton

  • Duhem P (1908/1969) To save the phenomena: an essay on the idea of physical theory from Plato to Galileo. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Duschl RA, Osborne J (2002) Supporting and promoting argumentation discourse in science education. Stud Sci Educ 38:39–72

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eddington A (1939) The philosophy of physical science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein A, Infeld L (1938) The evolution of physics. Simon & Schuster, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis BD (1965) The origin and nature of Newton’s laws of motion. In: Colodny RG (ed) Beyond the edge of certainty. Englewood Cliffs, NJ, pp 29–68

    Google Scholar 

  • Ernst HE (2006) New horizons in catholic philosophical theology: Fides et Ratio and the changed status of thomism. Heythrop J 47(1):26–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finocchiaro MA (1989) The Galileo affair. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Galileo G (1623/1957) The assayer. In: Drake S (ed) Discoveries and opinions of Galileo. Doubleday, New York, pp 229–280

  • Gaukroger S (1995) Descartes, an intellectual biography. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauld CF (2005) Habits of mind, scholarship and decision-making in science and religion. Sci & Educ 14(3–5):291–308

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gill HV (1943) Fact and fiction in modern science. M.H. Gill & Son, Dublin

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilson E (1929) The philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas, 2nd edn. Dorset Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2003) Theory and reality: an introduction to the philosophy of science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Good RG (2005) Scientific and religious habits of mind. Peter Lang, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1999) Rock of ages: science and religion in the fullness of life. Ballantine Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham LR (1973) Science and philosophy in the Soviet Union. Alfred A. Knopf, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham LR (1981) Between science and values. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall AR (1965) Galileo and the science of motion. Br J Hist Sci 2:185–199

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall AR (1980) Philosophers at war. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson NR (1965) Newton’s first law: a philosopher’s door into natural philosophy. In: Colodny RG (ed) Beyond the edge of certainty. Prentice Hall, Englewood-Cliffs, NJ, pp 6–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman PM (1982) Energy, force and matter: the conceptual development of nineteenth-century physics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré R (1964) Matter and method. Macmillan & Co, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Heisenberg W (1962) Physics and philosophy. Harper & Row, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Helmholtz H von (1995) Science and culture: popular and philosophical essays, (edited with introduction by David Cahan). Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel CG (1966) Philosophy of natural science. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Herivel J (1965) The background to Newton’s ‘Principia’. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse MB (1961) Forces and fields: the concept of action at a distance in the history of physics. Thomas Nelson & Sons, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchens C (2007) God is not great: how religion poisons everything. Hachette Book Group, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Holton G (1973) Thematic origins of scientific thought. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoodbhoy P (1991) Islam and science: religious orthodoxy and the battle for rationality. Zed Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes RIG (1990) Philosophical perspectives on Newtonian science. In: Bricker P, Hughes RIG (eds) Philosophical perspectives on Newtonian Science. MIT Press, Cambridge MA, pp 1–16

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (1988) Science as a process: an evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1739/1888) A treatise of human nature: being an attempt to introduce the experimental method of reasoning into moral subjects. Clarendon Press, Oxford

  • Israel J (2001) Radical enlightenment: philosophy and the making of modernity 1650–1750. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob MC (ed) (1994) The politics of western science, 1640–1990. Humanities Press, Atlantic Highlands, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeans J (1943/1981) Physics and philosophy. Dover Publications, New York

  • John HJ (1966) The Thomist spectrum. Fordham University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Joravsky D (1970) The Lysenko affair. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Kane WH, Corcoran JD, Ashley BM, Nogar RJ (eds) (1953) Science in synthesis. A dialectical approach to the integration of the physical and natural sciences. The Aquinas Library, River Forest, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1784/2003) What is enlightenment? In Hyland P (ed) The enlightenment: a sourcebook and reader. Routledge, London

  • Kenny A (1980) Aquinas. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny A (1985) A path from Rome: an autobiography. Sidgwick & Jackson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Koertge N (ed) (2005) Scientific values and civic virtues. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1970) The structure of scientific revolutions, 2nd edn. Chicago University Press, Chicago (1st edn, 1962)

  • Lacey H (2005) Values and objectivity in science. Lexington Books, Lantham MD

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman J (2002) Understanding philosophy of science. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I (1970) Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In: Lakatos I, Musgrave A (eds) Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 91–196

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamont J (2009) The fall and rise of Aristotelian metaphysics in the philosophy of science. Sci & Educ

  • Lange M (ed) (2007) Philosophy of science: an anthology. Blackwell Publishing, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Lecourt D (1977) Proletarian science? The case of Lysenko. Manchester University Press, Manchester

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke J (1689/1924) An essay concerning human understanding, abridged and edited by Pringle-Pattison AS, Clarendon Press, Oxford

  • Lonergan BJF (1974) The future of Thomism. In: Bernard JF Lonergan SJ, Ryan WFJ, Tyrrell BJ (eds) A second collection. Darton, Longman & Todd, pp 43–53

  • Lucey JM (1915) The mass. The proper form of Christian worship. In: Cabinet of catholic information. The Treasury Publishing Company, pp 84–100

  • Mach E (1883/1960) The science of mechanics. Open Court Publishing Company, LaSalle IL

  • Mach E (1886/1986) On instruction in the classics and the sciences. In: Mach E (ed) Popular scientific lectures. Open Court Publishing Company, La Salle, pp 338–374

  • Margenau H (1950) The nature of physical reality: a philosophy of modern physics. McGraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin RND (1991) Pierre Duhem: philosophy and history in the work of a believing physicist. Open Court, La Salle, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Mascall EL (1956) Christian theology and natural science: some questions in their relations. Longmans, Green & Co., London

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews MR (ed) (1989) The scientific background to modern philosophy. Hackett Publishing Company, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews MR (1990) Ernst Mach and contemporary science education reforms. Int J Sci Educ 12(3):317–325

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews MR (1994) Science teaching: the role of history and philosophy of science. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews MR (1995) Challenging New Zealand science education. Dunmore Press, Palmsterston North

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews MR (1997) Israel Scheffler on the role of history and philosophy of science in science teacher education. Stud Philos Educ 16(1–2):159–173

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews MR (1998a) In defense of modest goals for teaching about the nature of science. J Res Sci Teach 35(2):161–174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews MR (ed) (1998b) Constructivism in science education: a philosophical examination. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews MR (2000a) Time for science education: how teaching the history and philosophy of pendulum motion can contribute to science literacy. Kluwer Academic Publishers, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews MR (2000b) Constructivism in science and mathematics education. In: Phillips DC (ed) National society for the study of education, 99th yearbook, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 161–192

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1982) The growth of biological thought. Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA

    Google Scholar 

  • McCabe J (1912) Twelve years in a monastery, 3rd edn. Watts & Co., London

    Google Scholar 

  • McGuire JE (1995) Tradition and innovation: Newton’s metaphysics of nature. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • McInerny RM (1966) Thomism in an age of renewal. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin E (ed) (1963a) The concept of matter in Greek and medieval philosophy. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin E (ed) (1963b) The concept of matter in modern philosophy. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin E (1978) Newton on matter and activity. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin E (2005) Galileo’s theological venture. In: McMullin E (ed). The church and Galileo. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, pp 88–116

    Google Scholar 

  • Melsen AG van (1952) From atomos to atom. Duquesne University Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Monod J (1971) Chance and necessity: an essay on the natural philosophy of modern biology. Knopf, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Moody EA (1975) Studies in medieval philosophy, science and logic. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Mott N (ed) (1991) Can scientists believe? James & James, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel E (1961) The structure of science. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Nasr SH (1996) Religion and the order of nature. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • National Research Council (NRC) (1996) National science education standards. National Academy Press, Washington, DC

  • Newton I (1729/1934) Mathematical Principles of Mathematical Philosophy (trans: Motte A, revised Cajori F). University of California Press, Berkeley

  • Newton I (1730/1979) Opticks or a treatise of the reflections, refractions, inflections & colours of light. Dover Publications, New York

  • Passmore JA (1972) A hundred years of philosophy. Pelican Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Petersen A (1985) The philosophy of Niels Bohr. In: French AP, Kennedy PJ (eds) Niels Bohr: a centenary volume. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 299–310

    Google Scholar 

  • Planck M (1932) Where is science going? W.W. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga A (2000) Warranted Christian belief. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré H (1905/1952) Science and hypothesis. Dover Publications, New York

  • Polanyi M (1958) Personal knowledge. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Polkinghorne J (1988) Science and creation: the search for understanding. SPCK, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Polkinghorne J (1991) Reason and reality: the relationship between science and theology. SPCK, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Polkinghorne J (1996) The faith of a physicist: reflections of a bottom-up thinker. Fortress Press, Minneapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (1934/1959) The logic of scientific discovery. Hutchinson, London

  • Popper KR (1963) Conjectures and refutations: the growth of scientific knowledge. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Porter R (2000) The enlightenment: Britain and the creation of the modern world. Penguin Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Pullman B (1998) The atom in the history of human thought. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Pyle A (1997) Atomism and its critics: from Democritus to Newton. Thoemmes Press, Bristol

    Google Scholar 

  • Rabi II (1967) Science the centre of culture. World Publishing Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Randall JH (1958) Nature and historical experience. Essays in naturalism and in the theory of history. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Randall JH (1962) The career of philosophy. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Redondi P (1988) Galileo heretic. Allen Lane, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik DB (1998) The ethics of science. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Restrepo DH (2003) Philosophy in contemporary Colombia. In: Fløistad G (ed) Philosophy of Latin America. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, pp 143–154

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohrlich F (1987) From paradox to reality: our basic concepts of the physical world. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Royal Ministry of Church, Education and Research (RMCER) (1994) Core curriculum for primary, secondary, and adult education in Norway, RMCER, Oslo, Norway

  • Rutt JT (ed) (1817–32) The theological and miscellaneous works of Joseph Priestley, 25 vols. London (Kraus Reprint, New York, 1972)

  • Scheffler I (1963) The anatomy of inquiry. Bobbs-Merrill, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler I (1970) Philosophy and the curriculum. In: Scheffler I (ed) Reason and teaching. London, Routledge, 1973, pp 31–44. Reprinted in Sci & Educ 1(4):385–394

  • Schilpp PA (ed) (1951) Albert Einstein: philosopher–scientist, 2nd edn. Tudor, New York

  • Schmitt CB (1983) Aristotle and the renaissance. Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Schofield RE (ed) (1966) A scientific autobiography of Joseph Priestley (1733–1804): selected scientific correspondence. MIT Press, Cambridge

  • Schrödinger E (1964) My view of the world. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuster JA (1977) Descartes and the scientific revolution, 1618–1634, 2 vols. University of Michigan Press, Ann Abor

    Google Scholar 

  • Shimony A (1983) Reflections on the philosophy of Bohr, Heisenberg, and Schrödinger. In: Cohen RS, Laudan L (eds) Physics. Philosophy and Psychoanalysis, Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 209–221

    Google Scholar 

  • Shimony A (1993) Search for a naturalistic world view. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart JJC (1968) Between science and philosophy: an introduction to the philosophy of science. Random House, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1984) The nature of selection: evolutionary theory in philosophical focus. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Soyfer VN (1994) Lysenko and the Tragedy of Soviet Science (trans: Gruliow L, Gruliow R). Rutgers University Press, New Brunswick, NJ

  • Stebbing LS (1937/1958) Philosophy and the physicists. Dover Publications, New York

  • Stein H (2002) Newton’s metaphysics. In: Cohen IB, Smith GE (eds) The Cambridge companion to Newton. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 256–302

  • Stewart M (ed) (1991) Selected philosophical papers of Robert Boyle. Hackett Publishing Company, Indianapolis, IN

  • Tresmontant C (1965) Christian metaphysics. Sheed and Ward, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Trethowan I (1954) An essay in Christian philosophy, Longmans. Green & Co., London

    Google Scholar 

  • Trusted J (1991) Physics and metaphysics: theories of space and time. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace WA (1979) From a realist point of view. University Press of America, Washington

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace WA (1996) The modeling of nature: philosophy of science and philosophy of nature in synthesis. Catholic University of America Press, Washington, DC

    Google Scholar 

  • Wartofsky MW (1968) Conceptual foundations of scientific thought: an introduction to the philosophy of science. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg S (2001) Facing up: science and its cultural adversaries. Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisheipl JA (ed) (1961) The dignity of science. Studies in the philosophy of science presented to William Humbert Kane O.P. The Thomist Press, USA

  • Weisheipl JA (1968) The revival of Thomism as a Christian philosophy. In: McInerny RM (ed) New themes in Christian philosophy. University of Notre Dame Press, South Bend, IN, pp 164–185

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisheipl JA (1974) Friar Thomas D’Aquino: his life,thought and works. Basil Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisheipl JA (1985) Nature and motion in the middle ages. Catholic University of America Press, Washington DC

    Google Scholar 

  • Westfall RS (1971) The construction of modern science: mechanisms and mechanics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson EO (1998) Consilience: the unity of knowledge. Little, Brown & Co. London

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael R. Matthews.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Matthews, M.R. Teaching the Philosophical and Worldview Components of Science. Sci & Educ 18, 697–728 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-007-9132-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-007-9132-4

Keywords

Navigation