Skip to main content
Log in

Happiness Economics, Eudaimonia and Positive Psychology: From Happiness Economics to Flourishing Economics

  • Research Paper
  • Published:
Journal of Happiness Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A remarkable current development, happiness economics focuses on the relevance of people’s happiness in economic analyses. As this theory has been criticised for relying on an incomplete notion of happiness, this paper intends to support it with richer philosophical and psychological foundations. Specifically, it suggests that happiness economics should be based on Aristotle’s philosophical eudaimonia concept and on a modified version of ‘positive psychology’ that stresses human beings’ relational nature. First, this analysis describes happiness economics and its shortcomings. Next, it introduces Aristotle’s eudaimonia and takes a look at positive psychology with this lens, elaborating on the need to develop a new approach that goes beyond the economics of happiness: the economics of flourishing. Finally, the paper specifies some possible socio-economic objectives of a eudaimonic economics of happiness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for example, Nussbaum (2005) for a comparison of happiness notions by Aristotle, Bentham and Mill.

  2. A recent complete survey is George MacKerron’s (2012).

  3. Davis (forthcoming) has recently proposed slight changes to Putnam’s arguments in order to apply them to economics.

  4. John M. Cooper, in Reason and Human Good, Harvard University Press, Cambridge (Mass..), 1975; Rosalind Hursthouse in ‘Virtue Ethics’ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-virtue/, 2012, retrieved on May 2, 2013; Julia Annas, The Morality of Happiness, Oxford University Press, 1993, p. 44; John M. Finnis, Fundamentals of Ethics, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1983, p. 8; and Fred D. Miller, Jr., Nature, Justice, and Rights in Aristotle’s Politics, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1995, p. 19.

  5. Familiarized with Aristotle’s ideas, Amartya Sen has been careful to use the Greek term eudaimonia and not its usual translation as happiness. He realized that happiness was a very different thing for Aristotle and for Utilitarians. Eudaimonia is not a state of the mind, but an activity guided by reason. In The Standard of Living, Sen stated that ‘the breadth and richness of the Greek concept of eudaimonia may suggest similarly broad interpretations of happiness or pleasure’ (1987, p. 8). Richard Kraut (1979, p. 169) elaborated on the difficulties of translating eudaimonia and finally suggested just using this word, noting (1979, p. 170), ‘Aristotle thinks that the most eudaimon individual is someone who has fully developed and regularly exercises the various virtues of the soul, both intellectual and moral’.

  6. Early forms of Utilitarianism were hedonistic. On these forms, see, e.g., Irwin (2011, pp. 364–397).

  7. Crespo 2007 (p. 376) explains the Aristotelian distinction between a) ends that can be considered only as means and that are only pursued for the sake of something else (first-order or instrumental ends), b) ends that are desirable in themselves and are also pursued for the sake of the final end (second-order ends), and c) ends which are only desirable in themselves (third-order or final ends—usually known as eudaimonia or ‘happiness’). The following example is provided for greater clarity: we study for an exam (i.e. a means to an instrumental end) in order to graduate (a second-order end), in order to be happy (a final end) according to our life plan (designed by practical reason). Sen’s capabilities, for example, are second-order ends. Fowers (2012a) uses the term ‘instrumental’ to refer to goods in a) and ‘constitutive’ for goods in c), probably viewing goods in b) as ‘constitutive’ as well.

  8. We use the expression ‘relational’ in a broader sense than Martha Nussbaum (1986, Chapter 12), but this meaning does not discard the relevance for eudaimonia assigned by Nussbaum to the possession of ‘relational goods’ such as friendship, love, and political commitment. That is, we do not point only to the relational (and vulnerable) character of political relations, love and friendship, but to the root of these relational goods—i.e., the intrinsic relational character of human beings as ‘political animals’.

  9. On this, see Barker’s commentary (in Aristotle 1958, p. 8) and NE I, 7, 1097b 15–7. See also C. C. W. Taylor (1995, p. 237).

  10. Instead, Layard’s theory, in Seligman’s words, is ‘a naked monism’ (2011, p. 25).

  11. See van der Rijt (2013) for a review and analysis of the difficulties involved in this task.

References

  • Annas, J. (2011). Intelligent virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1954). Nicomachean ethics (Sir David Ross, Trans. and Introduced). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Aristotle. (1958). Politics (Ernest Barker, Edited and Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Aristotle. (1995). The complete works of Aristotle. The revised Oxford translation (J. Barnes (ed.) 6th printing with corrections). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Barrotta, P. (2008). Why economists should be unhappy with the economics of happiness. Economics and Philosophy, 24, 145–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Begley, N. (2010). Psychological adoption and adaption of eudaimonia. on Line in http://positivepsychology.org.uk/pp-theory/eudaimonia/140-the-psychological-adoption-and-adaptation-of-eudaimoni.html. Retrieved March 1, 2012.

  • Bentham, J. (1954). Jeremy Bentham’s economic writings (Critical edition based on his printed works and unprinted manuscripts by W. Stark). London: The Royal Economic Society and George Allen & Unwin.

  • Bruni, L., & Porta, P.-L. (2007). Introduction. In L. Bruni & P. L. Porta (Eds.), Handbook on the economics of happiness. Cheltenham: Elgar.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Carabelli, A. M., & Cedrini, M. A. (2011). The economic problem of happiness: Keynes on happiness and economics. Forum of Social Economy, 40, 335–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crespo, R. F. (2006). The ontology of the Economic: An Aristotelian analysis. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 30(5), 767–781.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crespo, R. F. (2007). Practical comparability and ends in economics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 14(3), 371–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crespo, R. F. (2013). Theoretical and practical reason in economics (pp. 59–62). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Crespo, R. F. (2014). A re-assessment of Aristotle's economic thought (pp. 64–71). London: Routledge.

  • Davis, J. B. (forthcoming). ‘Economists’ odd stand on the positive-normative distinction: A behavioral economics view. In G. DeMartino & D. McCloskey (Eds.), Handbook on professional economic ethics: Views from the economics profession and beyond. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Diener, E., Wirtz, D., Tov, W., Kim-Prieto, C., Choi, D., Oishi, S., et al. (2010). New well-being measures: Short scales to assess flourishing and positive and negative feelings. Social Indicators Research, 97, 143–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Easterlin, R. A. (1974). Does economic growth improve the human lot? Some empirical evidence. In R. David & M. Reder (Eds.), Nations and households in economic growth: Essays in honor of Moses Abramovitz (pp. 89–125). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flyvbjerg, B. (2001). Making social science matter. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fowers, B. J. (2005). Virtue ethics and psychology: Pursuing excellence in ordinary practices. Washington, DC: APA Press Books.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fowers, B. J. (2008). From continence to virtue: Recovering goodness, character unity, and character types for positive psychology. Theory & Psychology, 18, 629–653.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fowers, B. J. (2012a). An Aristotelian framework for the human good. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 32(1), 10–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fowers, B. J. (2012b). Placing virtue and the human good in psychology. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 32(1), 1–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fowers, B. J., Mollica, C. O., & Procacci, E. N. (2010). Constitutive and instrumental goal orientations and their relations with eudaimonic and hedonic well-being. The Journal of Positive Psychology, 5(2), 39–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frey, B. S., & Stutzer, A. (2002). Happiness and economics: How the economy and institutions affects human well-being. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graff Low, K. (2011). Flourishing, Substance use, and engagement in students entering college: A preliminary study. Journal of American College Health, 59(6), 555–561.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. ([1752] 1970). Writings on economics (edited with an Introduction by Eugene Rotwein). Madison: The University of Wisconsin Press.

  • Huppert, F. A., & So, T. T. C. (2009). What percentage of people in Europe are flourishing and what characterises them? Cambridge: Well-Being Institute, University of Cambridge. Prepared for the OECD/ISQOLS meeting ‘Measuring subjective well-being: an opportunity for NSOs?’ Florence—July 23/24, 2009, on line in http://www.isqols2009.istitutodeglinnocenti.it/Content_en/Huppert.pdf. Retrieved 1 May 2013.

  • Huppert, F. A., & So, T. T. C. (2013). Flourishing across Europe: Application of a new conceptual framework for defining well-being. Social Indicators Research, 110, 837–861. On line in http://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007%2Fs11205-011-9966-7.pdf. Retrieved 1 May 2013.

  • Huta, V., & Ryan, R. M. (2010). Pursuing pleasure or virtue: The differential and overlapping well-being benefits of hedonic and eudaimonic motives. Journal of Happiness Studies, 11, 735–762.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Irwin, T. W. (2011). The development of ethics. A historical and critical study. Volume III: From Kant to Rawls. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keyes, C. L. M. (1998). Social Well-Being. Social Psychology Quarterly, 61, 121–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keyes, C. L. M. (2002). The mental health continuum: From languishing to flourishing in life. Journal of Health and Social Research, 43, 207–222.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keyes, C. L. M. (2005). Mental Illness or mental health? Investigating axioms of the complete state model of health. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 73, 539–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keyes, C. L. M., & Annas, J. (2009). Feeling good and functioning well: Distinctive concepts in ancient philosophy and contemporary science. The Journal of Positive Psychology, 4(3), 197–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knight, F. H. (1956). On the history and method of economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraut, R. (1979). Two conceptions of happiness. The Philosophical Review, 88(2), 167–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laertius, D. (2007). The lives and opinions of eminent philosophers (C. D. Yonge, Trans.). www.classicpersuasion.org/pw/diogenes/dlaristotle.htm. Retrieved 1 September 2013.

  • Layard, R. (2005). Happiness. Lessons from a new science. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Layard, R. (2007). Happiness and public policy: A challenge to the profession. In J. F. Bruno & A. Stutzer (Eds.), Economics and psychology. A promising new cross-disciplinary field (pp. 155–168). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKerron, G. (2012). Happiness economics from 35,000 feet. Journal of Economic Surveys, 26(4), 705–735.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malthus, T. R. ([1798] 1914). An essay on the principle of population. London: J. M. Dent.

  • McMahan, E. A., & Estes, D. (2011). Hedonic versus eudaimonic conceptions of well-being: Evidence of differential associations with self-reported well-being. Social Indicators Research, 103, 93–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (1986). The fragility of goodness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (2005). Mill between Aristotle and Bentham. In L. Bruni & P. L. Porta (Eds.), Economics and happiness (pp. 170–183). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (1934). Some reflections on “The nature and significance of economics”. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 48(3), 511–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, C., & Seligman, M. E. P. (2004). Character strengths and virtues: A handbook and classification. New York: American Psychological Association, Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (2004). The collapse of the fact/value dichotomy and other essays. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rasmussen, D. C. (2011). Adam Smith on commerce and happiness: A response to Den Uyl and Rasmussen. Reason Papers, 33, 95–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, F. C. (2012). On psychology and virtue ethics. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 32(1), 24–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, F. C., Fowers, B. J., & Guignon, C. (1999). Re-envisioning psychology: Moral dimensions of theory and practice. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riedel, M. (ed.) (1972–1974) Rehabilitierung der praktischen Philosophie. Freiburg: Rombach.

  • Robbins, L. (1935). An essay on the nature and significance of economic science. London: MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sabetti, F. (2012). Public happiness as the wealth of nations: The rise of political economy in Naples in a comparative perspective. California Italian Studies, 3(1), 1–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seligman, M. (2011). Flourish. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1987). The standard of living. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Skidelsky, R., & Skidelsky, E. (2012). How much is enough? New York: Other Press.

  • Slife, B. D., & Richardson, F. C. (2008). Problematic ontological underpinnings of positive psychology: A strong relational alternative. Theory and Psychology, 18(5), 699–723.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slife, B. D., & Williams, R. (1995). What’s behind the research? Discovering hidden assumptions in the behavioral sciences. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. ([1759] 1976). The theory of moral sentiments. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Taylor, C. (1985a). Human agency and language Philosophical papers 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1985b). Philosophy and the human sciences. Philosophical Papers 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. C. W. (1995). Politics. In J. Barnes (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van der Rijt, J.-W. (2013). Public policy and the conditional value of happiness. Economics and Philosophy, 29, 381–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wijngaards, A. (2102). Wordly theology. On connecting public theology and economics. Doctoral Thesis defended at the Radboud Universiteit Nijmegen, on line in http://hdl.handle.net/2066/93624. Retrieved March 1, 2013.

Download references

Acknowledgments

We acknowledge the comments of John B. Davis, Jorge Streb, and two anonymous referees. We are also grateful for the English editing of M. Donadini.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ricardo F. Crespo.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Crespo, R.F., Mesurado, B. Happiness Economics, Eudaimonia and Positive Psychology: From Happiness Economics to Flourishing Economics. J Happiness Stud 16, 931–946 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10902-014-9541-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10902-014-9541-4

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation