Skip to main content
Log in

Why mandate young borrowers to contribute to their retirement accounts?

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Economic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many countries, in an effort to address the problem that many retirees have too little saved up, impose mandatory contributions into retirement accounts, that too, in an age-independent manner. This is puzzling because such funded pension schemes effectively mandate the young, the natural borrowers, to save for retirement. Further, present-biased agents disagree with the intent of such schemes and attempt to undo them by reducing their own saving or even borrowing against retirement wealth. We establish a welfare case for mandating the middle-aged and the young to contribute to their retirement accounts, even with age-independent contribution rates. We find, somewhat counterintuitively, that even though the young responds by borrowing more, that too at a rate higher than offered by pension savings, their lifetime utility increases.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It has been documented that, among Americans 40–45 years of age, the median retirement account balance is just $14,500—less than 4% of what the median-income worker will require in savings to meet his retirement needs. (Ghilarducci and James 2018). Gillers et al. (2018) cite a Wall Street Journal analysis that finds “more than 40 percent of households headed by people aged 55 through 70 lack sufficient resources to maintain their living standard in retirement.”

  2. Recent work by Aguiar and Hurst (2013) challenges “retirement-consumption” puzzle and shows that the decline in consumption at retirement belies important heterogeneity across different types of consumption goods—a large part of the consumption decline at retirement is driven by declines in food and work-related expenses suggesting agents substitute away from market expenditures toward household production as the opportunity cost of time declines post retirement. See Olafsson and Pagel (2018) for an updated take on this puzzle. Our analysis is not about this puzzle. If anything, it suggests how government initiatives may prevent any consumption declines.

  3. Myopia means the agent places less weight on the future than his true preferences does. Time-inconsistent preferences imply preference reversal: the relative weight placed by the current self on current versus future utility changes as the life cycle proceeds.

  4. Goda et al. (2015) present evidence on the ubiquity of present-biasedness (roughly, 55%) seen in Americans. They also find a robust negative relationship between retirement savings and the extent of present bias.

  5. Many countries (Australia, Netherlands, Denmark, Sweden, Mexico, Norway, Poland, Singapore, and many others) have mandatory pension schemes, either mandated by law or via labor market negotiations or contracts, requiring individuals to contribute a certain fraction of their income during their entire work career toward their own retirement. (OECD 2015). These range from 6% in New Zealand to 33% in Italy, once employer and employee mandates are added up. The contribution rates are typically age-independent, and are, therefore, the same for the young, the middle-aged and those close to retirement. One exception is Switzerland which has employee pension contribution rates increasing with age (four age groups) rising from 7% for individual in the age group 25–34 to 18% for the age group 55–65 (55–64 for women). Bateman et al. (2001) contains a detailed review of mandatory saving schemes across OECD countries.

  6. See Fig. 3.2 in Coeurdacier et al. (2015) for data on the USA

  7. The agents at the zero savings corner look a lot like the hand-to-mouth consumers in Kaplan et al. (2014) who “spend all of their available resources in every pay period.” To avoid discontinuities, Findley and Caliendo (2016) “smooth” away the interest rate spread. This allows them to stay away from zero-saving corners. In other words, the agents in their model cannot be “passive” in the sense of Chetty et al. (2014) as each one of them would actively respond to changes in the policy.

  8. Cremer and Pestieau (2011) consider a PAYG scheme in a two-period model with homogeneous agents where, in the absence of a no-borrowing constraint, there is no welfare case for such pensions. Their concern is more about redistribution via a PAYG scheme (seen most clearly, in the case where all agents are non-myopic) and not about whether such schemes solve the present-bias problem.

  9. One interpretation of “passive savers” is that they behave like agents at the zero-saving corner alluded to above; there may be other interpretations. It bears emphasis that when we say the zero-saving corner, we have in mind zero savings for life-cycle purposes. These people may have positive levels of savings for other reasons. Chetty et al. (2014) stay away from these nitty-gritties.

  10. In an online working paper version, we allow \(R_{b}\) to depend on the amount borrowed. That is, if s is the amount saved, then

    $$\begin{aligned} R(s)=\left\{ \begin{array}[c]{l} R\quad \text { for }s\ge 0\\ R(s)>R\quad \text { for }s<0,\;R^{\prime }(s)>0 \end{array} \right. . \end{aligned}$$
  11. The government is assumed to pre-commit to these contribution rates. For an insightful analysis of these issues in the absence of such precommittment, see Findley and Caliendo (2015).

  12. To make voluntary and mandatory savings non-perfect substitutes, Gale and Scholz (1994) presents a three-period OLG model with income uncertainty in period 2. This creates a legitimate precautionary demand for saving that mandated pensions do not satisfy. Chetty et al. (2014) introduce a specific utility gain from the flexibility available with voluntary saving. This is discussed in the online working paper version.

  13. In reality, it may be that pension wealth is not accepted as collateral by lenders. We touch on this below.

  14. The alternative case has so-called naive myopics, who do not perceive the upcoming change in their preferences. In an online working paper version, we briefly consider this case and argue that results remain unchanged qualitatively.

  15. As an online working paper makes clear, if \(R_{b}\) is permitted to smoothly vary with borrowing (and is equal to R at zero borrowing), then the corner is removed; all our results go through in this case.

  16. Of course, if \(\tau _{y}=\tau _{m}=0\), the middle-aged will save at any R to ensure some consumption when old.

  17. Also, as mentioned in the introduction, the zero retirement saving corner refers to zero voluntary saving for retirement purely due to a life-cycle motive. The online working paper makes clear that our results go through even if other motives for saving, such as a need for flexibility (as in Chetty et al. 2014) are included, in which case there would be positive voluntary saving on net but none for life-cycle reasons.

  18. Obviously, this holds for \(w_{y}=0\). However, we need a positive wage income for Self 1so as to be able to pose the question, does it make sense for the young to be mandated to save for pensions.

  19. The different saving decisions of the middle-aged under choice and true preferences is because \({\widetilde{\delta }}\ne \) \(\delta ^{*}\). The borrowing decisions when young are also different, not only because \({\widetilde{\delta }}\ne \) \(\delta ^{*}\) but also the sophisticated young under choice preferences is cognizant that his middle-aged self will attempt to undo his action, a concern the young under true preferences does not have to contend with.

  20. In the limit, letting \(R_{b}\rightarrow \infty \) (no borrowing allowed, as in most of the literature discussed in the introduction) eliminates borrowing. In that case, the optimal saving level can always be implemented.

  21. Guo and Caliendo (2014) argue that a time-inconsistent mandated saving policy, one which deviates from the stated \(\left( \tau _{y},\tau _{m}\right) \) and “misleads” the middle-aged as to their required contribution rate, may deliver the optimal (\(b_{y}^{*},s_{m}^{*}\)).

  22. The parameters chosen are \(\delta ^{*}=0.9,\) \(\delta =0.85,\) \(\beta =0.8,\) \(w_{y}=4,\) \(w_{m}=8,\) \(R=1.5,\) and \(R_{b}=1.75.\)

  23. In practice, governments could simply exempt those who can show adequate saving-for-retirement from the scheme.

  24. Caliendo and Findley (2019) study the issue of multiple-self Pareto efficiency and find that much depends on the frequency of choice—if large, as in a full-blown life-cycle model, it is more likely that the commitment allocation is preferred by later selves. It would be interesting—an issue we leave to future research—to compute the possible set of commitment allocations that satisfy multi-self Pareto efficiency.

  25. This was not the case in Andersen and Bhattacharya (2011) where the alternative to private saving was return-dominated unfunded social security. As such, as private capital got crowded out, its return rose, thereby preventing agents from hitting the zero-capital corner. There too, sufficient myopia was needed to get a welfare role for PAYG pensions.

References

  • Aguiar, M., Hurst, E.: Deconstructing life cycle expenditure. J. Polit. Econ. 121(3), 437–492 (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  • Alessie, R., Angelini, V., Van Santen, P.: Pension wealth and household savings in Europe: evidence from SHARELIFE. Eur. Econ. Rev. 63, 308–328 (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, A.L., Christensen, A.M., Nielsen, N. F., Koob, S. A., Oksbjerg, M., Kaarup, R.: Income and debt for families, Danish Central Bank. Q. Rev. 2012.2—part 2, 1–40 (2012)

  • Andersen, T.M., Bhattacharya, J.: On myopia as rationale for social security. Econ. Theory 47, 135–158 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-010-0528-z

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • André, C.: Household Debt in OECD Countries: Stylised Facts and Policy Issues, Economics Department WP no. 1277. OECD, Paris (2016)

  • Attanasio, O.P., Weber, G.: Consumption and saving: models of intertemporal allocation and their implications for public policy. J. Econ. Lit. 48(3), 693–751 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Basu, K.: A behavioral model of simultaneous borrowing and saving. Oxford Econ. Pap. 68(4), 1166–1174 (2016)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateman, H., Kingston, G., Piggott, J.: Forced Saving: Mandating Private Retirement Incomes. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2001)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim, B. D.: Taxation and saving. In: Handbook of Public Economics, vol. 3, pp. 1173–1249. Elsevier, New York (2002)

  • Blau, D.M.: Pensions, household saving, and welfare: a dynamic analysis of crowd out. Quant. Econ. 7(1), 193–224 (2016)

    Google Scholar 

  • Caliendo, F.N., Findley, T.S.: Commitment and welfare. J. Econ. Behav. Organ. 159, 210–234 (2019)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chetty, R.: Behavioral economics and public policy: a pragmatic perspective. Am. Econ. Rev. 105(5), 1–33 (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chetty, R., Friedman, J.N., Leth-Petersen, S., Nielsen, T.H., Olsen, T.: Active vs. passive decisions and crowd-out in retirement savings accounts: evidence from Denmark. Q. J. Econ. 129(3), 1141–1219 (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  • Coeurdacier, N., Guibuad, S., Keyu, J.: Credit constraints and growth in a global economy. Am. Econ. Rev. 105(9), 2838–2881 (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cremer, H., Pestieau, P.: Myopia, redistribution and pensions. Eur. Econ. Rev. 55, 165–175 (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cremer, H., De Donder, P., Maldonado, D., Pestieau, P.: Designing a linear pension scheme with forced savings and wage heterogeneity. Int. Tax Public Finance 15(5), 547–562 (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Danish Ministry for Economic and Interior Affairs: The economic situation for families: distribution, poverty, and incentives. Copenhagen (2014)

  • Diamond, P.: A framework for social security analysis. J. Public Econ. VIII, 275–298 (1977)

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, P., Köszegi, B.: Quasi-hyperbolic discounting and retirement. J. Public Econ. 87, 1839–1872 (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  • Eckstein, Z., Eichenbaum, M.S., Peled, D.: Uncertain lifetimes and welfare enhancing properties of annuity markets and social security. J. Public Econ. 26, 303–326 (1985)

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt, G.V., Kumar, A.: Employer matching and 401 (k) saving: evidence from the health and retirement study. J. Public Econ. 91(10), 1920–1943 (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  • Engen, E.M., Gale, W.G., Scholz, J.K.: The illusory effects of saving incentives on saving. J. Econ. Perspect. 10(4), 113–138 (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldstein, M.: The optimal level of social security benefits. Q. J. Econ. 100(2), 303–320 (1985)

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldstein, M., Leibman, J.: Social security. In: Auerbach, A., Feldstein, M. (eds.) Chapter 32: Handbook of Public Economics, vol. 4. Elsevier, Amsterdam (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  • Findley, T.S., Caliendo, F.N.: Time inconsistency and retirement choice. Econ. Lett. 129, 4–8 (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  • Findley, T.S., Caliendo, F.N.: Time-Inconsistent Preferences, Borrowing Costs, and Social Security. mimeo Utah State University (2016)

  • Gale, W.G.: The effects of pensions on household wealth: a reevaluation of theory and evidence. J. Polit. Econ. 106(4), 706–723 (1998)

    Google Scholar 

  • Gale, W.G., Scholz, J.K.: Intergenerational transfers and the accumulation of wealth. J. Econ. Perspect. 8(4), 145–160 (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghilarducci, T., James, T.: Americans Haven’t Saved Enough for Retirement. What Are We Going to Do About It? Harvard Business Review (2018)

  • Gillers, H., Tergessen, A., Scism, L.: A generation of americans is entering old age the least prepared in decades. Wall Street J. (2018)

  • Goda, G.S., Levy, M., Manchester, C.F., Sojourner, A., Tasoff, J.: The Role of Time Preferences and Exponential-Growth Bias in Retirement Savings (No. 15-04). National Bureau of Economic Research (2015)

  • Gul, F., Pesendorfer, W.: Temptation and self-control. Econometrica 69(6), 1449–76 (2001)

    Google Scholar 

  • Gul, F., Pesendorfer, W.: Self-control and the theory of consumption. Econometrica 72, 119–158 (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  • Guo, N.L., Caliendo, F.N.: Time-inconsistent preferences and time-inconsistent policies. J. Math. Econ. 51, 102–8 (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hubbard, R.G., Skinner, J.S.: Assessing the effectiveness of saving incentives. J. Econ. Perspect. 10(4), 73–90 (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  • Imrohoroglu, A., Imrohoroglu, S., Joines, D.H.: Time-inconsistent preferences and social security. Q. J. Econ. 118(2), 745–784 (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, G., Violante, G.L.: A model of the consumption response to fiscal stimulus payments. Econometrica 82(4), 1199–1239 (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, G., Violante, G.L., Weidner, J.: The wealthy hand-to-mouth. Brook. Pap. Econ. Act. 2014(1), 77–138 (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplow, L.: The Theory of Taxation and Public Economics. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumru, Ç.S., Thanopoulos, A.C.: Social security and self control preferences. J. Econ. Dyn. Control 32(3), 757–778 (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Laibson, D.: Golden eggs and hyperbolic discounting. Q. J. Econ. 112, 443–77 (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  • Laibson, D., Repetto, A., Tobacman, J., Hall, R., Gale, W., Akerlof, G.: Self-control and saving for retirement. Brook. Pap. Econ. Act. 1998(1), 91–196 (1998). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-019-01228-1

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindbeck, A., Persson, M.: The gains from pension reform. J. Econ. Lit. XLI, 74–112 (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, L., Niu, Y., Wang, Y., Yang, J.: Optimal consumption with time-inconsistent preferences. Economic Theory 1–31 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-019-01228-1

  • Luttmer, E., Mariotti, T.: Efficiency and equilibrium when preferences are time-inconsistent. J. Econ. Theory 132(1), 493–506 (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  • Malin, B.A.: Hyperbolic discounting and uniform savings floors. J. Public Econ. 92, 1986–2002 (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Morduch, J.: Borrowing to save. J. Glob. Dev. 1(2), 1–11 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, C.K.: Rational overconfidence and social security: subjective beliefs, objective welfare. Econ. Theory 65(2), 179–229 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-016-1022-z

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Donoghue, T., Rabin, M.: Doing it now or later. Am. Econ. Rev. 89(1), 103–24 (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  • OECD: Improving Financial Education and Awareness on Insurance and Private Pensions. OECD, Paris (2008)

  • OECD: Pensions at a Glance. OECD, Paris (2015)

  • Olafsson, A., Pagel, M.: The retirement-consumption puzzle: new evidence from personal finances (No. w24405). National Bureau of Economic Research (2018)

  • Pestieau, P., Possen, U.: Prodigality and myopia—two rationales for social security. Manch. Sch. Econ. 76(6), 629–652 (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Poterba, J.M.: Retirement security in an aging population. Am. Econ. Rev. 104(5), 1–30 (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  • Poterba, J., Venti, S.F., Wise, D.A.: How retirement saving programs increase saving. J. Econ. Perspect. 10(4), 91–112 (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  • St-Amant, P.-A.B., Garon, J.-D.: Optimal redistribitive pensions and the costs of self-control. Int. Tax Public Finance 22, 723–740 (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  • Statistics Denmark: Statistics on Labour, Income and Wealth (2017). www.statistikbanken.dk, series: Formue7 accessed June 18th 2017)

  • Summers, L.H.: Some simple economics of mandated benefits. Am. Econ. Rev. 79(2), 177–183 (1989)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joydeep Bhattacharya.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

The paper has benefitted tremendously from the generous and constructive comments of an anonymous referee. The authors graciously acknowledge financial support from the Danish Council for Independent Research (Social Sciences) under the Danish Ministry of Science, Technology and Innovation.

Appendices

Appendix

Borrowing by the young

The savings decision of the middle-aged (\(s_{m}\)) depends on borrowing as young (\(b_{y}\)), and this is perceived by the (sophisticated) young. Hence, the two decisions are interconnected. The main text works with the case where agents in the absence of mandatory pension savings are borrowers as young (\(b_{y}>0\)) and savers as middle-aged (\(s_{m}>0\)), since this is the case where the welfare rationale for mandatory savings (especially for the young) may be called into question. If the young are savers, there is no essential difference between being young and middle-aged.

In the absence of mandatory savings, it is trivial that the middle-aged are saving (\(s_{m}>0\)) since this is the only way of ensuring consumption when old. From the main text—see Eq. (10), we have that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \Omega }{\partial b_{y}}=u^{\prime }\left( c_{y}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}\left[ \delta -{\widetilde{\delta }}\right] Ru^{\prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial b_{y}}-\widetilde{\delta }R_{b}u^{\prime }\left( c_{m}\right) . \end{aligned}$$

If \(\frac{\partial \Omega }{\partial b_{y}}\mid _{b_{y}=0}>0\) it follows that \(b_{y}>0\) which in turn requires

$$\begin{aligned} u^{\prime }\left( w_{y}\right) >{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}u^{\prime }\left( w_{m}-s_{m}\right) -{\widetilde{\delta }}\left[ \delta -\widetilde{\delta }\right] Ru^{\prime }\left( Rs_{m}\right) \frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial b_{y}}, \end{aligned}$$

or using \({\widetilde{\delta }}Ru^{\prime }\left( Rs_{m}\right) =u^{\prime }\left( w_{m}-s_{m}\right) ,\)

$$\begin{aligned} u^{\prime }\left( w_{y}\right) >u^{\prime }\left( w_{m}-s_{m}\right) \left[ {\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}-\left( \delta -{\widetilde{\delta }}\right) \frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial b_{y}}\right] . \end{aligned}$$

Note that \({\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}-\left( \delta -{\widetilde{\delta }}\right) \frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial b_{y}}<\delta R_{b}\) since \(\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial b_{y}}>-R_{b}\). Thus, a sufficient condition ensuring \(b_{y}>0\) is

$$\begin{aligned} u^{\prime }\left( w_{y}\right) >u^{\prime }\left( w_{m}-s_{m}\right) \delta R_{b}, \end{aligned}$$
(18)

where \(s_{m}\) is determined from \(u^{\prime }\left( w_{m}-s_{m}\right) =R{\widetilde{\delta }}u^{\prime }\left( Rs_{m}\right) \); hence \(0<s_{m}<w_{m}\). Hence, condition (18) holds if the wage as young is not too high, i.e.,

$$\begin{aligned} w_{y}\le {\overline{w}}_{y}(w_{m},\delta ,{\widetilde{\delta }},R,R_{b}) \end{aligned}$$
(19)

Overborrowing by the young and undersaving by the middle-aged

This appendix proves that agents “overborrow” when young (\(b_{y}>b_{y}^{*} \)) and “undersave” when middle-aged (\(s_{m}<s_{m}^{*}\)) in the absence of any pension scheme (\(\tau _{y}=\tau _{m}=0\)). The savings decision of the middle-aged is determined by: \(-u^{\prime }\left( w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y} -s_{m}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}Ru^{\prime }\left( Rs_{m}\right) =0\) and since \(u^{\prime }\left( Rs_{m}\right) \rightarrow \infty \) for \(s_{m} \rightarrow 0\), it follows that \(s_{m}>0\). Intuitively, the only way by which the individual can ensure consumption as old is by saving as middle-aged. Under the true preferences we have that savings is determined by \(-u^{\prime }\left( w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y}^{*}-s_{m}^{*}\right) +\delta ^{*} Ru^{\prime }\left( Rs_{m}^{*}\right) =0\). The savings as middle-aged depends on borrowing as young and we have \(s_{m}=\psi (b_{y}),\) \(s_{m}^{*}=\psi ^{*}(b_{y}^{*})\). Notice, that \(\psi (b_{y})<\psi ^{*}(b_{y})\) since \({\widetilde{\delta }}R<\delta ^{*}R\), and both functions are decreasing in their argument.

The first-order condition for the borrowing decision by the young (11)

$$\begin{aligned} -u^{\prime }\left( c_{y}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}R\left[ \left( {\widetilde{\delta }}-\delta \right) \left( \frac{\partial D\left( b_{y}\right) }{\partial b_{y}}\right) +R_{b}{\widetilde{\delta }}\right] u^{\prime }\left( c_{o}\right) =0 \end{aligned}$$

can by use of \(u^{\prime }(c_{m})={\widetilde{\delta }}Ru^{\prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \) be written

$$\begin{aligned} -u^{\prime }\left( w_{y}+b_{y}\right) +\left[ \left( \widetilde{\delta }-\delta \right) \left( \frac{\partial D\left( b_{y}\right) }{\partial b_{y}}\right) +R_{b}{\widetilde{\delta }}\right] u^{\prime }\left( w_{m} -R_{b}b_{y}-\psi (b_{y})\right) =0; \end{aligned}$$

denote the solution by \(b_{y}^{c}\).

For the true preferences, lifetime utility depends on borrowing as young as

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial b_{y}^{*}}=u^{\prime }\left( w_{y}+b_{y}^{*}\right) -\delta ^{*}R_{b}u^{\prime }\left( w_{m} -R_{b}b_{y}^{*}-\psi ^{*}(s_{y}^{*})\right) . \end{aligned}$$

Evaluate this derivative, for the borrowing decision of the young under the choice preferences \(b_{y}^{c}\)

$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial b_{y}^{*}}\mid _{b_{y}^{c}}=u^{\prime }\left( w_{y}+b_{y}\right) -\delta ^{*}R_{b}u^{\prime }\left( w_{m} -R_{b}b_{y}-\psi ^{*}(b_{y})\right) \nonumber \\&\quad =\left[ -\left( {\widetilde{\delta }}-\delta \right) \left( -\frac{\partial D\left( b_{y}\right) }{\partial b_{y}}\right) +R_{b}\widetilde{\delta }\right] u^{\prime }\left( w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y}-\psi (b_{y})\right) \nonumber \\&\qquad -\delta ^{*}R_{b}u^{\prime }\left( w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y}-\psi ^{*}(b_{y})\right) \end{aligned}$$
(20)

Note that the largest possible value of \(-\frac{\partial D\left( b_{y}\right) }{\partial b_{y}}=R_{b}\) which implies

$$\begin{aligned} \left[ -\left( {\widetilde{\delta }}-\delta \right) \left( -\frac{\partial D\left( b_{y}\right) }{\partial b_{y}}\right) +R_{b}\widetilde{\delta }\right] \le -\left( {\widetilde{\delta }}-\delta \right) \left( R_{b}\right) +R_{b}{\widetilde{\delta }}=\delta R_{b}<\delta ^{*}R_{b}\nonumber \\ \end{aligned}$$
(21)

Since \(\psi ^{*}(b_{y})>\psi (b_{y})\Leftrightarrow \) \(u^{\prime }\left( w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y}-\psi (b_{y})\right) <u^{\prime }\left( w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y} -\psi ^{*}(b_{y})\right) ,\) using (21) in (20) yields

$$\begin{aligned} \left. \frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial b_{y}^{*}}\right| _{b_{y}^{c}}<0. \end{aligned}$$

It follows \(b_{y}^{*}<b_{y}\) and, therefore, by implication \(s_{m}^{*}>s_{m}\).

Appendix: Age-dependent contribution rates

The following considers whether the young should be mandated to contribute to pension savings, when the middle-aged are doing so (\(\tau _{m}>0\)). To this end, we first need to establish that it is optimal to make the middle-aged contribute, and next consider whether the young should. Similar to above, define \({\underline{\tau }}_{m}^{a}\) and \({\overline{\tau }}_{m}^{a}\) as the critical contribution rates which delineates the positive savings, savings corner and negative savings for the middle-aged, i.e.,

$$\begin{aligned} {\underline{\tau }}_{m}^{a}&:u^{\prime }\left( \left( 1-{\underline{\tau }} _{m}^{a}\right) w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y}\right) ={\widetilde{\delta }}Ru^{\prime }\left( R{\underline{\tau }}_{m}^{a}w_{m}\right) \\ {\overline{\tau }}_{m}^{a}&:u^{\prime }\left( \left( 1-{\overline{\tau }} _{m}^{a}\right) w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y}\right) ={\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}u^{\prime }\left( R{\overline{\tau }}_{m}^{a}w_{m}\right) \end{aligned}$$

Case I Middle-aged are saving (\(s_{m}>0\))

When the middle-aged are savers (\(s_{m}>0\)), we have that savings (\(b_{y} ,s_{m}\)) for \(\tau _{y}=0\),\(\tau _{m}>0\) are determined by

$$\begin{aligned}&u^{\prime }\left( w_{y}+b_{y}\right) ={\widetilde{\delta }}R\left[ \left( {\widetilde{\delta }}-\delta \right) \left( \frac{\partial D\left( b_{y}\right) }{\partial b_{y}}\right) +R_{b}{\widetilde{\delta }}\right] u^{\prime }\left( Rs_{m}+R\tau _{m}w_{m}\right) \\&u^{\prime }\left( w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y}-\tau _{m}w_{m}-s_{m}\right) ={\widetilde{\delta }}Ru^{\prime }\left( Rs_{m}+R\tau _{m}w_{m}\right) \end{aligned}$$

This system determines borrowing as young \(b_{y}\) and total savings as middle-aged \(D\equiv s_{m}+\tau _{m}w_{m}\), hence \(\frac{\partial s_{m} }{\partial \tau _{m}}=-w_{m}\) as long as \(s_{m}>0\) holds, and therefore \(\frac{\partial \left( s_{m}+\tau _{m}w_{m}\right) }{\partial \tau _{m}}=0\) which in turn implies \(\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{m}}=0\). To obtain the comparative statics with respect to \(\tau _{y},\) differentiate each of the optimality conditions above. Tedious algebra shows

$$\begin{aligned}&-u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) \frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{y} }+R\Lambda _{a}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \frac{\partial s_{m} }{\partial \tau _{y}}=-w_{y}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) -u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) R^{2}w_{y}\Lambda _{a}\\&R_{b}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) \frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{y}}+\left[ u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) +\widetilde{\delta }R^{2}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \right] \frac{\partial s_{m} }{\partial \tau _{y}}=-{\widetilde{\delta }}RR^{2}w_{y}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \end{aligned}$$

from where the signs of \(\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{y}}\) and \(\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau _{y}}\) are established.

Case II Middle-aged at the corner (\(s_{m}=0\))

For \({\underline{\tau }}_{m}^{a}\le \tau _{m}\le {\overline{\tau }}_{m}^{a},s_{m}=0\) and a change in the contribution rate for the middle-aged affect true lifetime utility as

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial \tau _{m}}\mid _{s_{m}=0}=-u^{\prime } (c_{m})w_{m}+\delta ^{*}u^{\prime }(c_{o})w_{m}R. \end{aligned}$$

Assessing the marginal welfare effect for \(\tau _{m}={\underline{\tau }}_{m}^{a}\) using \(u^{\prime }(c_{m})=R{\widetilde{\delta }}u^{\prime }(c_{o})\) we find

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial \tau _{m}}\mid _{s_{m}=0,\tau _{m}={\underline{\tau }}_{m}}=\left( \delta ^{*}-{\widetilde{\delta }}\right) u^{\prime }(c_{o})w_{m}R>0 \end{aligned}$$

i.e., true welfare can be improved by setting a contribution rate \(\tau _{m}>{\underline{\tau }}_{m}^{a}\).

Case III Middle-aged as borrowers (\(s_{m}<0\))

Assume that \(\tau _{m}^{*}>{\overline{\tau }}_{m}^{a}\) in this case the middle-aged are borrowers. The lifetime utility as perceived when young reads

$$\begin{aligned} \text { }u\left( (1-\tau _{y})w_{y}+b_{y}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}\left[ u\left( (1-\tau _{m})w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y}-s_{m}\right) +\delta u\left( b+R_{b}s_{m}\right) \right] \end{aligned}$$

and the first-order condition reads

$$\begin{aligned} u^{\prime }\left( c_{y}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}\left[ -u^{\prime }\left( c_{m}\right) +\delta R_{b}u^{\prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \right] \left. \frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial b_{y}}\right| _{s_{m}<0}-\widetilde{\delta }R_{b}u^{\prime }\left( c_{m}\right) =0 \end{aligned}$$

by use of \(u^{\prime }\left( c_{m}\right) ={\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}u^{\prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \) it can be written

$$\begin{aligned} u^{\prime }\left( c_{y}\right) =\Lambda _{b}u^{\prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \end{aligned}$$

where

$$\begin{aligned} \Lambda _{b}\equiv \left[ \left( {\widetilde{\delta }}-\delta \right) \left. \frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial b_{y}}\right| _{s_{m}<0}+\widetilde{\delta }R_{b}\right] R_{b}{\widetilde{\delta }} \end{aligned}$$

Note that

$$\begin{aligned} \left. \frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial b_{y}}\right| _{s_{m}<0} =-\frac{R_{b}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) }{u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}^{2}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) } \end{aligned}$$

implying that \(\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial b_{y}}>-R_{b},\) and hence it follows that \(0<\Lambda _{b}<\delta R_{b}R_{b}{\widetilde{\delta }}\). With homothetic preferences \(\Lambda _{a}\) is independent of \(c_{m}\) and \(c_{o} \).

Writing the first-order condition for the borrowing and savings decisions, we have

$$\begin{aligned} u^{\prime }\left( \left( 1-\tau _{y}\right) w_{y}+b_{y}\right)&=\Lambda _{b}u^{\prime }\left( R^{2}\tau _{y}w_{y}+R\tau _{m}w_{m}+R_{b} s_{m}\right) \\ u^{\prime }\left( \left( 1-\tau _{m}\right) w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y}-s_{m}\right)&={\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}u^{\prime }\left( R^{2}\tau _{y}w_{y}+R\tau _{m} w_{m}+R_{b}s_{m}\right) \end{aligned}$$

Differentiating w.r.t \(\tau _{y}\) yields

$$\begin{aligned} u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) \left[ -w_{y}+\frac{\partial b_{y} }{\partial \tau _{y}}\right]&=\Lambda _{b}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \left[ R^{2}w_{y}+R_{b}\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau _{y} }\right] ,\\ u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) \left[ -R_{b}\frac{\partial b_{y} }{\partial \tau _{y}}-\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau _{y}}\right]&={\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \left[ R^{2}w_{y}+R_{b}\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau _{y}}\right] , \end{aligned}$$

and w.r.t \(\tau _{m}\)

$$\begin{aligned} u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) \left[ \frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{m}}\right]&=\Lambda _{b}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \left[ Rw_{m}+R_{b}\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau _{m} }\right] ,\\ u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) \left[ -w_{m}-R_{b}\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{m}}-\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau _{m}}\right]&={\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \left[ Rw_{m}+R_{b}\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau _{m}}\right] . \end{aligned}$$

Writing this in matrix form we have

$$\begin{aligned} \left[ \begin{array}[c]{cc} u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) &{} -\Lambda _{b}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) R_{b}\\ -u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) R_{b} &{} -\left[ u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}^{2}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \right] \end{array} \right] \left[ \begin{array}[c]{c} \frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{m}}\\ \frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau _{m}} \end{array} \right] =\left[ \begin{array}[c]{c} \Lambda _{b}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) Rw_{m}\\ {\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) Rw_{m} +u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) w_{m} \end{array} \right] , \end{aligned}$$

implying

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{m}}=\frac{\left| \begin{array}[c]{cc} \Lambda _{b}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) Rw_{m} &{} -\Lambda _{b}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) R_{b}\\ {\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) Rw_{m} +u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) w_{m} &{} -\left[ u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}^{2}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \right] \end{array} \right| }{\left| \begin{array}[c]{cc} u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) &{} -\Lambda _{b}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) R_{b}\\ -u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) R_{b} &{} -\left[ u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}^{2}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \right] \end{array} \right| }<0. \end{aligned}$$

It follows from the expressions above

$$\begin{aligned}&sign\left[ -w_{m}-R_{b}\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{m}}-\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau _{m}}\right] =sign\left[ Rw_{m}+R_{b}\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau _{m}}\right] \\&sign\left[ \frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{m}}\right] =sign\left[ -w_{m}-R_{b}\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{m}}-\frac{\partial s_{m} }{\partial \tau _{m}}\right] \end{aligned}$$

Since \(\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{m}}<0\) it follows that \(-w_{m}-R_{b}\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{m}}-\frac{\partial s_{m} }{\partial \tau _{m}}<0\) and \(w_{m}R+R_{b}\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau _{m}}<0\). Next note

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial \tau _{m}}=\left[ \Lambda _{a} \frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{m}}-\delta ^{*}{\widetilde{\delta }} R_{b}\left[ w_{m}+R_{b}\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{m}}+\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau _{m}}\right] +\left( \delta ^{*}\right) ^{2}\left[ w_{m}R+R_{b}\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau _{m}}\right] \right] u^{\prime }(c_{o}) \end{aligned}$$

and hence \(\frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial \tau _{m}}<0\) for \(\tau _{m}>{\overline{\tau }}_{m}^{a}\). This proves the optimal \(\tau _{m}\in \left[ {\underline{\tau }}_{m}^{a},{\overline{\tau }}_{m}^{a}\right] \).

1.1 Pension contributions by the young

Assume that the optimal \(\tau _{m}^{*}\in \left[ {\underline{\tau }}_{m} ^{a},{\overline{\tau }}_{m}^{a}\right] .\) Can welfare be improved by setting a \(\tau _{y}>0\)? We have (recall \(s_{m}=0\)) or

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial \tau _{y}}=-u^{\prime }(c_{y})w_{y}-\left[ \delta ^{*}u^{\prime }(c_{m})R_{b}-u^{\prime }(c_{y})\right] \frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{y}}+\left( \delta ^{*}\right) ^{2}u^{\prime } (c_{o})R^{2}w_{y} \end{aligned}$$

Since \(u^{\prime }(c_{y})={\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}u^{\prime }(c_{m})\) it follows that

$$\begin{aligned} \delta ^{*}u^{\prime }(c_{m})R_{b}-u^{\prime }(c_{y})=\left( \delta ^{*}-{\widetilde{\delta }}\right) R_{b}u^{\prime }(c_{m})>0 \end{aligned}$$

and therefore

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial \tau _{y}}>-u^{\prime }(c_{y})w_{y}-\left[ \delta ^{*}u^{\prime }(c_{m})R_{b}-u^{\prime }(c_{y})\right] w_{y}+\left( \delta ^{*}\right) ^{2}u^{\prime }(c_{o})R^{2}w_{y} \end{aligned}$$

since \(\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau _{y}}<w_{y}\). Hence a sufficient condition that \(\frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial \tau _{y}}>0\) is

$$\begin{aligned} -u^{\prime }(c_{y})w_{y}-\left[ \delta ^{*}u^{\prime }(c_{m})R_{b}-u^{\prime }(c_{y})\right] w_{y}+\left( \delta ^{*}\right) ^{2}u^{\prime } (c_{o})R^{2}w_{y}>0, \end{aligned}$$

or

$$\begin{aligned} \delta ^{*}w_{y}\left[ \delta ^{*}u^{\prime }(c_{o})R^{2}-u^{\prime } (c_{m})R_{b}\right] >0. \end{aligned}$$

This inequality holds if

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\delta ^{*}R^{2}}{R_{b}}u^{\prime }(c_{o})>u^{\prime }(c_{m} )\Leftrightarrow \frac{\delta ^{*}R^{2}}{{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}R_{b} }u^{\prime }(c_{o}){\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}>u^{\prime }(c_{m}) \end{aligned}$$

For the middle-aged to at the zero savings corner we require

$$\begin{aligned} u^{\prime }(c_{o}){\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}>u^{\prime }(c_{m})>\widetilde{\delta }Ru^{\prime }(c_{o}) \end{aligned}$$

and hence a sufficient condition that \(\frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial \tau _{y}}>0\) is

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\delta ^{*}R^{2}}{{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}R_{b}}>1\Leftrightarrow \delta ^{*}R^{2}>{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}^{2} \end{aligned}$$

1.2 Implementing (\(b_{y}^{*},s_{m}^{*}\))

Is it possible to implement the optimal choice under the true preferences (\(b_{y}^{*},s_{m}^{*}\))and the associated consumption levels (\(c_{y}^{*},c_{m}^{*},c_{o}^{*}\)) by some choice of \(\tau _{y}\) and \(\tau _{m}\)? To address this question, first write the consumption levels for the optimal choices under the true preferences, i.e.,

$$\begin{aligned} c_{y}^{*}&=w_{y}+b_{y}^{*}\\ c_{m}^{*}&=w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y}^{*}-s_{m}^{*}\\ c_{o}^{*}&=Rs_{m}^{*} \end{aligned}$$

and under the choice preference for given values of \(\tau _{y}\) and \(\tau _{m} \).

$$\begin{aligned} c_{y}&=(1-\tau _{y})w_{y}+b_{y}\\ c_{m}&=(1-\tau _{m})w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y}-s_{m}\\ c_{o}&=R^{2}\tau _{y}w_{y}+R\tau _{m}w_{m}+Rs_{m} \end{aligned}$$

For \(c_{y}\) \(=c_{y}^{*}\), we require

$$\begin{aligned} w_{y}+b_{y}^{*}=(1-\tau _{y})w_{y}+b_{y} \end{aligned}$$

or

$$\begin{aligned} b_{y}-b_{y}^{*}=\tau _{y}w_{y} \end{aligned}$$
(22)

For \(c_{m}=c_{m}^{*}\) we require

$$\begin{aligned} w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y}^{*}-s_{m}^{*}=(1-\tau _{m})w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y}-s_{m} \end{aligned}$$

or

$$\begin{aligned} s_{m}-s_{m}^{*}=-\tau _{m}w_{m}-R_{b}\left( b_{y}-b_{y}^{*}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(23)

Finally, for \(c_{o}=c_{o}^{*}\) we require

$$\begin{aligned} Rs_{m}^{*}=R^{2}\tau _{y}w_{y}+R\tau _{m}w_{m}+Rs_{m} \end{aligned}$$

or

$$\begin{aligned} s_{m}-s_{m}^{*}=-\left( R\tau _{y}w_{y}+\tau _{m}w_{m}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(24)

Combining (23) and (24) gives

$$\begin{aligned} -\left( R\tau _{y}w_{y}+\tau _{m}w_{m}\right) =-\tau _{m}w_{m}-R_{b}\left( b_{y}-b_{y}^{*}\right) \end{aligned}$$

or \(R\tau _{y}w_{y}=R_{b}\left( b_{y}-b_{y}^{*}\right) \) and using (22) this requires \(R\tau _{y}w_{y}=R_{b}\tau _{y}w_{y}\) which cannot hold for \(R<R_{b}\), showing that it is not possible to implement (\(b_{y}^{*},s_{m}^{*}\))and the associated consumption levels (\(c_{y}^{*},c_{m}^{*},c_{o}^{*}\)) by some choice of \(\tau _{y}\) and \(\tau _{m}\).

Age-independent contribution rates

When the middle-aged are savers, savings decisions are determined by

$$\begin{aligned} u^{\prime }\left( (1-\tau )w_{y}+b_{y}\right)&=\Lambda _{i}u^{\prime }\left( Rs_{m}+R^{2}\tau w_{y}+R\tau w_{m}\right) \\ u^{\prime }\left( (1-\tau )w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y}-s_{m}\right)&=\widetilde{\delta }Ru^{\prime }\left( Rs_{m}+R^{2}\tau w_{y}+R\tau w_{m}\right) \end{aligned}$$

where

$$\begin{aligned} \Lambda _{I}\equiv {\widetilde{\delta }}R\left[ \left( {\widetilde{\delta }} -\delta \right) \left( \frac{\partial D\left( b_{y}\right) }{\partial b_{y}}\right) +R_{b}{\widetilde{\delta }}\right] \end{aligned}$$

Note that \(0<\Lambda _{I}<RR_{b}\delta {\widetilde{\delta }}\) and \(\Lambda _{I} \) is independent of \(b_{y}\) and \(s_{m}\) under homothetic preferences.

Hence, differentiating the optimality conditions above with respect to \(\tau \), we get

$$\begin{aligned} u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) \left[ -w_{y}+\frac{\partial b_{y} }{\partial \tau }\right]&=\Lambda _{I}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \left[ R\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau }+R^{2}w_{y}+Rw_{m}\right] \\ u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) \left[ -w_{m}-R_{b}\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau }-\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau }\right]&={\widetilde{\delta }}Ru^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \left[ R\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau }+R^{2}w_{y}+Rw_{m}\right] \end{aligned}$$

implying

$$\begin{aligned} \text {sign}\left[ w_{y}-\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau }\right]&=-\text {sign}\left[ R\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau }+R^{2}w_{y} +Rw_{m}\right] ,\\ \text {sign}\left[ -w_{m}-R_{b}\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau } -\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau }\right]&=\text {sign}\left[ R\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau }+R^{2}w_{y}+Rw_{m}\right] . \end{aligned}$$

To solve for \(\frac{\partial s_{y}}{\partial \tau }\) and\(\frac{\partial s_{m} }{\partial \tau }\) the above expression can be written in matrix form as which implies that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau }=\frac{\left| \begin{array}[c]{cc} u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) w_{y}+\Lambda _{I}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \left[ R^{2}w_{y}+Rw_{m}\right] &{} -\Lambda _{I}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) R\\ u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) w_{m}+{\widetilde{\delta }}Ru^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \left[ R^{2}w_{y}+Rw_{m}\right] &{} -\left[ u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}R^{2}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \right] \end{array} \right| }{\left| \begin{array}[c]{cc} u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) &{} -\Lambda _{I}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) R\\ -u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) R_{b} &{} -\left[ u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}R^{2}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) \right] \end{array} \right| }, \end{aligned}$$

implying

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau }=\frac{u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) +R^{2}\widetilde{\delta }u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) +\Lambda _{I}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) R^{2}}{u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) +R^{2}{\widetilde{\delta }}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) +\Lambda _{I} u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{o}\right) u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) RR_{b}}w_{y}<w_{y}. \end{aligned}$$

From this, it can be inferred by use of the above sign-relations: \(w_{y} -\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau }>0;\) \(w_{m}+R_{b}\frac{\partial b_{y} }{\partial \tau }+\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau }>0;\) \(R\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau }+R^{2}w_{y}+Rw_{m}<0\). Considering the welfare effects from a change in \(\tau \) we have

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial \tau }= & {} -u^{\prime }(c_{y})\left[ w_{y}-\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau }\right] -\delta ^{*}u^{\prime }(c_{m})\left[ w_{m}+R_{b}\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau }+\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau }\right] \\&\quad +\left( \delta ^{*}\right) ^{2}u^{\prime }(c_{o})\left[ R\frac{\partial s_{m}}{\partial \tau }+R^{2}w_{y}+Rw_{m}\right] <0, \end{aligned}$$

and it follows that \(\frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial \tau }<0\) for \(\tau <{\underline{\tau }}\).

Consider next \(\tau \in \left[ {\underline{\tau }},{\overline{\tau }}\right] \) where the middle-aged are at a corner. In this case, borrowing as young is determined by

$$\begin{aligned} u^{\prime }\left( (1-\tau )w_{y}+b_{y}\right) ={\widetilde{\delta }} R_{b}u^{\prime }\left( (1-\tau )w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y}\right) \end{aligned}$$

and the corner condition reads

$$\begin{aligned} u^{\prime }(R^{2}\tau w_{y}+R\tau w_{m}){\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}>u^{\prime }((1-\tau )w_{m}-R_{b}b_{y})>{\widetilde{\delta }}Ru^{\prime }(R^{2}\tau w_{y}+R\tau w_{m}). \end{aligned}$$

It follows straightforwardly that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau }=\frac{u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) w_{y}+{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) w_{m}}{u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) +\widetilde{\delta }R_{b}^{2}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) }. \end{aligned}$$

Note for later

$$\begin{aligned} w_{y}-\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau }=\frac{{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b} ^{2}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) w_{y}-{\widetilde{\delta }} R_{b}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) w_{m}}{u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}^{2}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) }. \end{aligned}$$

For \(\tau \in \left[ {\underline{\tau }},{\overline{\tau }}\right] \) and thus \(s_{m}=0\) we have that welfare is affected by a change in the contribution rate as:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial \tau }&=-u^{\prime }(c_{y})\left[ w_{y}-\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau }\right] -\delta ^{*}u^{\prime }(c_{m})\left[ w_{m}+R_{b}\frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau }\right] +\left( \delta ^{*}\right) ^{2}u^{\prime }(c_{o})\left[ R^{2}w_{y} +Rw_{m}\right] \\&=\left[ -{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}\left[ w_{y}-\frac{\partial b_{y} }{\partial \tau }\right] -\delta ^{*}\left[ w_{m}+R_{b}\frac{\partial b_{y} }{\partial \tau }\right] \right] u^{\prime }(c_{m})+\left( \delta ^{*}\right) ^{2}u^{\prime }(c_{o})\left[ R^{2}w_{y}+Rw_{m}\right] \\&=\left[ -{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}w_{y}-\delta ^{*}w_{m}-\left[ \delta ^{*}R_{b}-{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}\right] \frac{\partial b_{y} }{\partial \tau }\right] u^{\prime }(c_{m})+\left( \delta ^{*}\right) ^{2}u^{\prime }(c_{o})\left[ R^{2}w_{y}+Rw_{m}\right] , \end{aligned}$$

evaluated for \({\underline{\tau }}\) and using \(u^{\prime }(c_{m} )={\widetilde{\delta }}Ru^{\prime }(c_{o})\) we get

$$\begin{aligned} \left. \frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial \tau }\right| _{{\underline{\tau }}}=\left[ \left[ -{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}w_{y}-\delta ^{*}w_{m}-\left[ \delta ^{*}R_{b}-{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}\right] \frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau }\right] {\widetilde{\delta }}R+\left( \delta ^{*}\right) ^{2}\left[ R^{2}w_{y}+Rw_{m}\right] \right] u^{\prime }(c_{o}), \end{aligned}$$

or

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\left. \frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial \tau }\right| _{{\underline{\tau }}}}{u^{\prime }(c_{o})}&=-{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b} {\widetilde{\delta }}Rw_{y}-{\widetilde{\delta }}R\delta ^{*}w_{m} -{\widetilde{\delta }}R\left[ \delta ^{*}R_{b}-{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}\right] \frac{\partial b_{y}}{\partial \tau }+\left( \delta ^{*}\right) ^{2}\left[ R^{2}w_{y}+Rw_{m}\right] \\&=\left[ \left( \delta ^{*}\right) ^{2}R^{2}-{\widetilde{\delta }} R_{b}{\widetilde{\delta }}R-{\widetilde{\delta }}R\left[ \delta ^{*} R_{b}-{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}\right] \frac{u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) }{u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }} R_{b}^{2}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) }\right] w_{y}\\&\quad +\left[ R\delta ^{*}\left[ \delta ^{*}-{\widetilde{\delta }}\right] +{\widetilde{\delta }}R\left[ \delta ^{*}-{\widetilde{\delta }}\right] \frac{{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}^{2}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) }{u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}^{2} u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) }\right] w_{m}, \end{aligned}$$

where

$$\begin{aligned} \left( \delta ^{*}\right) ^{2}R-{\widetilde{\delta }}R\delta ^{*}+{\widetilde{\delta }}R\left[ \delta ^{*}-{\widetilde{\delta }}\right] \frac{{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}^{2}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) }{u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}^{2} u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) }>0. \end{aligned}$$

Consider the term

$$\begin{aligned} \left( \delta ^{*}\right) ^{2}R^{2}-{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b} {\widetilde{\delta }}R-{\widetilde{\delta }}R\left[ \delta ^{*}-\widetilde{\delta }\right] R_{b}\frac{u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) }{u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}^{2}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) }. \end{aligned}$$

Since \(\frac{u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) }{u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}^{2}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) }<1\) it follows that

$$\begin{aligned} \left( \delta ^{*}\right) ^{2}R^{2}-{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b} {\widetilde{\delta }}R-{\widetilde{\delta }}R\left[ \delta ^{*}-\widetilde{\delta }\right] R_{b}\frac{u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) }{u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{y}\right) +{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}^{2}u^{\prime \prime }\left( c_{m}\right) }>R\delta ^{*}\left[ \delta ^{*}R-{\widetilde{\delta }} R_{b}\right] . \end{aligned}$$

Hence, this expression is positive if \(\delta ^{*}R-{\widetilde{\delta }} R_{b}>0\), and it follows that a sufficient condition that\(\frac{\partial \Omega ^{*}}{\partial \tau }\mid _{{\underline{\tau }}}>0\) is \(\delta ^{*}R-{\widetilde{\delta }}R_{b}>0\).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Andersen, T.M., Bhattacharya, J. Why mandate young borrowers to contribute to their retirement accounts?. Econ Theory 71, 115–149 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-019-01235-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-019-01235-2

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation