Skip to main content

PERSPECTIVE article

Front. Hum. Neurosci., 05 October 2022
Sec. Brain Health and Clinical Neuroscience
Volume 16 - 2022 | https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2022.987051

Are we really unconscious in “unconscious” states? Common assumptions revisited

Andre Sevenius Nilsen1* Bjørn E. Juel1,2* Benjamin Thürer1 Arnfinn Aamodt1 Johan F. Storm1*
  • 1Department of Physiology, Institute of Basic Medicine, University of Oslo, Oslo, Norway
  • 2School of Medicine and Public Health, Wisconsin Institute for Sleep and Consciousness, University of Wisconsin-Madison, Madison, WI, United States

In the field of consciousness science, there is a tradition to categorize certain states such as slow-wave non-REM sleep and deep general anesthesia as “unconscious”. While this categorization seems reasonable at first glance, careful investigations have revealed that it is not so simple. Given that (1) behavioral signs of (un-)consciousness can be unreliable, (2) subjective reports of (un-)consciousness can be unreliable, and, (3) states presumed to be unconscious are not always devoid of reported experience, there are reasons to reexamine our traditional assumptions about “states of unconsciousness”. While these issues are not novel, and may be partly semantic, they have implications both for scientific progress and clinical practice. We suggest that focusing on approaches that provide a more pragmatic and nuanced characterization of different experimental conditions may promote clarity in the field going forward, and help us build stronger foundations for future studies.

Introduction

Empirical research is based on the ideal of objective (observer-invariant) measurements and observations of phenomena. Studying consciousness, i.e., subjective experience, or “what it is like to be…” (Nagel, 1974), is a special case, since the phenomena of conscious experience are essentially subjective (observer-variant), i.e., only directly observable from “within” by the individual having the experience. As directly investigating the internal perspective of a system from the outside is believed to be epistemologically impossible—an issue often referred to as the “Leibniz’s gap”—empirical consciousness research depends on inference from objectively observable properties and events, including behavior.1 From such research, the common-sense view that our brain is essential for our conscious experience, is supported by a range of empirical studies (Koch et al., 2016; Northoff and Lamme, 2020; Sarasso et al., 2021). Essentially, conventional empirical consciousness science is based on the physicalist presupposition that “there can be no change in the mental states of a person without a change in brain states”2 (Pinker, 2003).

Just as in other scientific fields, studying mechanisms of consciousness, i.e., the necessary and sufficient mechanisms distinguishing between unconscious and conscious states, requires a minimal contrast (Revach and Salti, 2021). That is, in addition to examples of truly conscious brain states (states in which it is “like something to be”), we need to identify at least one at least one example of a truly unconscious brain state (a state in which it is “not like anything to be”).3 It seems intuitively obvious and uncontroversial that we are conscious during normal, alert wakefulness, whereas brain death with an isoelectric encephalogram (EEG) implies complete unconsciousness. Other states such as deep sleep, dreaming, anesthesia, and different disorders of consciousness (DOC), are considered to exist on some continuum between these two extremes (e.g., Laureys, 2005), and/or are often grouped as either states of consciousness or unconsciousness (implying a dichotomy or threshold, at least in the way it is phrased; see Supplementary material for some examples).

These intuitions have for long shaped experimental research (Searle, 1998) and commonalities in neural dynamics between states classified as “unconscious” (such as slow-wave activity in EEG) have been proposed as potential “markers of unconsciousness” (Gibbs et al., 1935; Posner et al., 2007; Voss and Sleigh, 2007; Casey et al., 2022). However, how confident can we be that these states are, in fact, examples of unconsciousness? From the subjective perspective, only the presence of consciousness is epistemologically accessible (one cannot experience non-experience). And although we can all think of situations where we seem to have been unconscious in the past (what was it like to be you at 4 a.m. last night?), there is a possibility that we might have been conscious but just don’t remember it. Thus, from the third person perspective, while we may have high confidence in inferences about the presence of consciousness in normally awake humans (e.g., based on reports of experience), we cannot have the same confidence in inferences about unconsciousness (e.g., lack of report and behavior; even reports of no subjective experience, may be confounded by memory issues).

What we’ve discussed so far is of course not novel and relates to the “hard problem” (Chalmers, 1995) and the explanatory gap (Levine, 1983), among other philosophical issues (for a more formal treatment see also Kleiner and Hoel, 2021). It has been argued that the above issues can be discounted (for now) and empirical research should instead focus on the “easy” or “real” problems of consciousness to see how far we can get (Varela et al., 2017; Chalmers, 1995; Crick and Koch, 1998; Seth, 2016, 2021). While there is much merit in the “easy” and “real” problems approaches, or working toward establishing the “full neural correlate of consciousness” (Crick and Koch, 1998; Koch et al., 2016), we here argue that common, implicit assumptions about unconscious states ought to be critically re-examined.

Studying unconsciousness empirically

Physiological, behavioral, and experiential states such as wakefulness, deep slow-wave sleep, REM sleep with vivid dreams, anesthesia, hallucinations, and DOC, intuitively seem to differ in terms of subjective experience, i.e., “what it is like” to be in these states. Accordingly, much of modern consciousness science is based on the distinction between the experiential content and “level” of such states. In particular, general anesthesia induced by certain anesthetics,4 deep slow-wave sleep, and certain DOCs (e.g., coma and unresponsive wakefulness syndrome; UWS), have been studied extensively using a wide range of measurement techniques (e.g., Gibbs et al., 1935; Ferenets et al., 2006; Palanca et al., 2009; Nicolaou and Georgiou, 2011; Casali et al., 2013; Lee et al., 2013; Schartner et al., 2015; Juel et al., 2018). In the last 15 years alone, over 200 different EEG-based measures of consciousness (or degrees thereof) have been employed to investigate neural dynamics during these conditions (Nilsen et al., 2020), in addition to measures based on other techniques.

Crucially, in such studies it has typically been assumed that (or phrased as if) certain brain states, particularly coma, deep slow-wave sleep, and deep general anesthesia, are genuinely unconscious, or that they have significantly reduced level/degree of consciousness (e.g., Crick and Koch, 1990; Casali et al., 2013; Oizumi et al., 2014; MacDonald et al., 2015; Nieminen et al., 2016; Siclari et al., 2017; Juel et al., 2018; Casey et al., 2022). These explicit or implicit assumptions are often based on lack of complex behavior/communication during the state, no recollection of any experience after returning to wakefulness, and/or marked differences in neural dynamics relative to wakefulness (e.g., Crick and Koch, 1990; Searle, 1998; Ferrarelli et al., 2010; Gosseries et al., 2011; Casali et al., 2013; Oizumi et al., 2014; Schartner et al., 2015, 2017; Bonhomme et al., 2019). From a common-sense and pragmatic point of view, these assumptions may seem perfectly reasonable, but are these inferences and assumptions sound? Even if we ignore the epistemological issues discussed earlier, there are empirical reasons to re-examine our categorizations of certain states as states of unconsciousness:

1) Behavioral signs of (un-)consciousness can be unreliable: It is of course well known that any behavioral assessment of the degree of (un-)consciousness based on responsiveness to sensory stimuli (e.g., as captured by the Glasgow Coma Scale; Sternbach, 2000, or Richmond Agitation Sedation Scale; Sessler et al., 2002) can be confounded by various sensory or motor deficits. For example, when surgical anesthesia is combined with muscle relaxants, motor responses are prevented. However, by using the isolated forearm technique (IFT), which permits motor reporting by bypassing the neuromuscular blockade, it has been shown that participants undergoing levels of general anesthesia adequate for surgery can still give complex behavioral responses to commands (e.g., “squeeze my hand if you can hear me”) (Russell, 2006; Sanders et al., 2012, 2017; Gaskell et al., 2017; Linassi et al., 2018). This suggests that a level of consciousness sufficient for some voluntary actions (even without postoperative recall) is often maintained in general anesthesia (according to some estimates, IFT responses can be seen in as much as ∼44% of cases5; Pandit et al., 2015). For this reason, various neurological measures have been developed to be independent of behavioral inference (e.g., Sleigh et al., 1999; Bekinschtein et al., 2009; Casali et al., 2013; Schartner et al., 2015). However, some such measures have been shown to not detect capacity for behavioral response to commands using the IFT paradigm (Russell, 2006; Gaskell et al., 2017), even when only applying neuromuscular blockade without anesthetics (Schuller et al., 2015). Even if complex motor responses cannot be achieved, such as in certain DOCs, it is in some cases possible to detect volitional behavior through brain computer interfaces, which can then be used as a means of communication (Owen et al., 2006; Monti et al., 2010), although this requires certain stimulus-evoked neural responses to be similar to those in wakefulness6 (Gibson et al., 2014). On the other hand, it has been argued that even the presence of complex behavior is not always a reliable indicator of conscious experience (inferred from subjective report), as suggested e.g., by blind sight experiments (Stoerig and Cowey, 1997, but see Phillips, 2021, for an alternative view7) or sleepwalking (Oudiette et al., 2009).

2) Subjective reports of (un-)consciousness can be unreliable: Subjective retrospective reports (e.g., as used in experiments with intermittent awakening from sleep to probe dreaming; Noreika et al., 2009; Siclari et al., 2018; Aamodt et al., 2021; Casey et al., 2022) are confounded by unreliable recall. For example, propofol and many other anesthetic agents are found to be highly amnesic (Veselis et al., 2008), causing dreams to fade quickly from memory. Thus, obviously, a lack of retrospective report, or report of no experience, can be confounded by a lack of recall (Sanders et al., 2017). This is well known from, e.g., retrograde amnesia induced by scopolamine (Rush, 1988) and anterograde amnesia following hippocampectomy (Dossani et al., 2015). Further, the capacity of iconic memory (sensory memory) has been shown to be much higher than what can be retrospectively reported (Sligte et al., 2008), and this has been suggested to cause phenomenological overflow (Block, 2007). Inherent biases in reporting vague experiences might also mask their presence, as has been argued for blindsight (Phillips, 2021). Finally, even positive reports might be unreliable for many reasons (for a discussion see Schwitzgebel, 2008), including a common tendency to confabulate immediately after waking from sleep or anesthesia (Rosen, 2013).

3) States presumed to be unconscious are not always devoid of experience: Careful studies have provided evidence that dreaming occurs surprisingly often in deep non-REM slow-wave sleep stages (Suzuki et al., 2004; McNamara et al., 2010; Windt et al., 2016; Siclari et al., 2017, 2018), as well as during general anesthesia (Käsmacher et al., 1996; Brandner et al., 1997; Leslie et al., 2007, 2009; Eer et al., 2009; Noreika et al., 2011; Leslie, 2017). However, these conditions have often been termed “dreamless” and “unconscious” (e.g., Tononi and Massimini, 2008; MacDonald et al., 2015; Nieminen et al., 2016). Specifically, studies show that the proportion of awakenings from deep non-REM sleep (stage 2–4) that yield immediate reports of dreaming varies from 20 to 70% (Nielsen, 2000; McNamara et al., 2010), and from 11 up to 74% in general anesthesia (Wilson et al., 1975; Leslie et al., 2007; Noreika et al., 2011; Gyulaházi et al., 2015). The reasons for the varying proportion of awakenings with a dream report might be due to methodology (e.g., different delays between awakening and report; Leslie et al., 2007; or how reports are prompted; Stickgold et al., 2001), anesthetic depth (Leslie, 2010), and individual differences such as the propensity to remember dreams in general (Hejja and Galloon, 1975; Eer et al., 2009). For example, a study (Hejja and Galloon, 1975) of dreaming during ketamine anesthesia (which often induces vivid dreams and neural dynamics similar to REM sleep; e.g., Cheong et al., 2011; Sarasso et al., 2015), found that only those who frequently reported dreaming at home also did so following ketamine anesthesia. Similar results were found for propofol anesthesia (Eer et al., 2009). In general, while these observations might be confounded by confabulation or recall of experiences outside of anesthesia, the burden of proving this falls on the claimant. Moreover, the widely varying frequency of dream reports after awakenings from deep sleep or anesthesia, might suggest that more systematic and thorough methods could have obtained reports even more frequently.

In summary, to be able to empirically study the mechanisms enabling conscious experience, requires at least some examples of known changes in degree or presence of consciousness. However, we argue that some of the most widely used current assumptions about such changes are problematic. Specifically, careful experiments have revealed that complex behavior (in the form of volitional communication) and retrospective reports of some kinds of experience (sometimes even vivid and complex) can be obtained from certain conditions more often than our assumptions about the state of consciousness in these conditions would dictate. However, since retrospective reports following anesthesia or sleep can be unreliable due to recall failure and confabulation, it is uncertain to what extent such reports can be trusted. While we do not argue that consciousness never disappears or that there are no brain states that are most correctly described as unconscious (e.g., brain death or catastrophic brain injury that show similar pathological signs of severely disrupted brain activity, such as isoelectric EEG), we do argue that the terminology used when describing various states has implications for clinical practice and basic research.

Implications

While many of the above empirical points have been raised before (e.g., Hudetz, 2008; Sanders et al., 2012, 2017; Windt et al., 2016), there are still reasons to critically discuss these issues. For example, although it is well known that there are often reports of dreaming following general anesthesia (e.g., Leslie et al., 2009; Noreika et al., 2011; Sanders et al., 2012), many authors still describe general anesthesia as a state of “unconsciousness” (see Supplementary material for some examples). In the last decade alone, 292 papers have been published using the words “unconsciousness” and “anesthesia” in the title or abstract, and 104 papers with “sleep” (with many more using similar wording in the body text), often implying that general anesthesia or deep slow-wave sleep are states of “unconsciousness” (Pubmed search 02.05.2022). While this use of terms may be more appropriate in some contexts than others, it increases the problem of heterogeneous definitions and operationalizations, making it difficult to review the literature. Furthermore, common general differences between wakefulness and states such as deep slow-wave sleep, general anesthesia, and certain DOCs, may be viewed as features associated with loss of consciousness requiring theoretical explanation (e.g., items 1–3 in Table 1 in Seth et al., 2006). However, it has been argued that this may lead to circular reasoning, where theories aiming to explain such features are validated against our “common sense intuition” about consciousness in the very same cases in which the features were detected (Revach and Salti, 2021). While any given theory might not explicitly draw from research assuming the traditional, common sense differentiation between unconscious and conscious states, the theory may be implicitly influenced by this tradition.8 Thus, assuming that deep slow-wave sleep, general anesthesia, and certain DOCs, are unconscious states, might lead theoretical development astray. Finally, if we consider as “fully unconscious” states that actually contain frequent dreaming or “other kinds” of experiences, we may miss opportunities to study such “other kinds” of conscious experience (as may be found in deep sleep; Windt et al., 2016).

On the other hand, avoiding our intuitive categorizations of conscious/unconscious states (and the research enabled by their use) has clinical consequences. For example, the question of whether a DOC patient is conscious or not has direct relevance for ongoing and future treatment, and is important for the patient’s caretakers and next of kin. Moving away from the term “unconscious” might then weaken the support for clinical tools developed to help diagnose DOC patients. Therefore, criticisms of current use of the concept and term “unconsciousness” should avoid hasty conclusions, else risking “throwing the baby out with the bathwater.”

Possible solutions

The primary purpose of this perspective is to suggest that, given the evidence of disconnected or covert experiences occurring surprisingly often in states commonly labeled as “unconscious” (and the multiple confounds in inferring the absence of consciousness), one should be more cautious in how one uses the concept and term “unconsciousness”, primarily, in basic consciousness research.

However, if states like general anesthesia, slow-wave sleep, and certain DOCs, are no longer valid as contrastive paradigm cases of unconsciousness in consciousness science, it seems hard to identify mechanisms necessary and sufficient for consciousness. We believe that current approaches that focus more on “degree of similarity” to normal wakefulness, or on how confident we can be that there is some conscious experience (and perhaps of what), can avoid the issues discussed above. Here we outline three such approaches.

1. Pragmatic approach: Rather than working from prior assumptions, we can classify states based on how they differ from normal wakefulness, or based on the confidence we have that they might support any form of consciousness. Most studies following a “state-based” approach (i.e., contrasting system level global changes) already do this when using wakefulness in healthy subjects as a reference (control) condition. Accordingly, several measures used in the clinic are more appropriately described as “positive markers,” that is, markers capturing the “degree of similarity” to wakefulness in healthy subjects (e.g., King et al., 2013; Casarotto et al., 2016; Demertzi et al., 2019). In other words, such markers help build confidence in the inference that a subject is conscious. While researchers using such markers are more or less explicitly clear on this, it is still too common to employ the term “unconsciousness” when referring to states different enough from wakefulness when, we argue, one should rather be explicitly agnostic about the ground truth in these cases. This approach entails avoiding generalizing across various states and conditions under the assumption that they share the underlying property of unconsciousness. Alternatively, one can sidestep the issue by clearly defining consciousness (or particularly the absence thereof) in more operational terms (as in e.g., Siclari et al., 2018, Sarasso et al., 2021). While this may be a step in the right direction, it depends on the field agreeing on definitions and operationalizations to avoid confusion, which still seems some ways off (Francken et al., 2022).

2. Descriptive approach: Extending the pragmatic approach, we can systematically describe states and conditions functionally, behaviorally, cognitively, and physiologically (e.g., as in Sanders et al., 2012), to obtain a more complete and nuanced picture of the states, while remaining agnostic as to whether consciousness is truly present/absent (in the Nagelian sense) (see also Bayne et al., 2016, 2020; Engemann et al., 2018; Walter, 2021). For example, a moderate level of propofol anesthesia could be characterized as a state of partial responsiveness and partially connected awareness (IFT shows command following), partial/occasional recall (it is possible to obtain some dream reports), impaired explicit memory formation (ability to report dreams quickly declines after awakening), and partial capacity for communication (through IFT). Then, such properties can be empirically determined and compared between different states and conditions. For example, vivid “dream” reports (much like those following REM sleep) are currently thought to be more common after ketamine anesthesia than other anesthetics (Leslie, 2010), and the propensity of dream reports has been observed to increase with sedation depth for propofol, but not for other anesthetics (Eer et al., 2009). The latter study also illustrates which kinds of questions a more descriptive approach could incentivize, e.g., sedation-depth/report relationships.

Further, characterizing states and conditions in this manner allows: (1) large scale contrasting and comparison of the outcome of various neurological measures between different states (e.g., as in Gordillo et al., 2020; Nilsen et al., 2020); (2) studying memory, confabulation, perception, meta-cognition, etc., within various states in order to build a basis for estimation of reliability of subjective reports and the inferences that can be drawn from such reports (e.g., evidence of at least implicit learning in anesthesia; Ghoneim and Block, 1997); and, (3) mapping the heterogenous causes and effects of various states and conditions allowing for more nuanced treatment of patients. For example, Gibson et al. (2014) show how individual DOC patients differ in volitional mental imagery ability and where in the cortex such imagery might be detected. Such individual variation might otherwise be lost if a single axis of conscious-unconscious or cognitive capacity is assumed.

Finally, the specific characterizations of various states, as exemplified above, can then be updated accordingly in a more iterative fashion as new knowledge is acquired.

3. Predictive approach: In order to support a more pragmatic and descriptive approach, one may focus on predicting what contents are experienced by subjects in specific situations based on their neural activity, i.e., developing and applying “mind-readers.” This approach may help build confidence in the validity of subjective reports of phenomenological experience in wakefulness. From there, one can gradually approach states and conditions in which we have reason to doubt subjective reports. Although the field is still in its infancy, there have been several advances in this regard, for example decoding dreams (Horikawa et al., 2013; Smith, 2013; Horikawa and Kamitani, 2017), movie watching (Huth et al., 2016; Nishida and Nishimoto, 2018), speech (Wang et al., 2021), and other sensory modalities (Hatamimajoumerd et al., 2022). This approach is similar to solving the “real” problem of consciousness (Seth, 2016). However, a “mind-reader” faces similar criticisms as that of “consciousness-meters” (Latham et al., 2017) in that it’s in principle impossible to validate in general, but especially in states and conditions where reports are lacking or unclear. Furthermore, decodable neural activity is not necessarily associated with conscious processing per se (Lepauvre and Melloni, 2021). On the other hand, a predictive approach can of course be beneficial beyond the study of consciousness; e.g., objective indications that someone experiences pain can be of major importance in the clinic.

For more generalized forms of “mind-readers,” one might identify basic dimensions of conscious experience (e.g., as in Bayne et al., 2016; Fazekas and Overgaard, 2016), e.g., differences in abstraction level of percepts, the range of possible qualia, or the “richness”/ “vividness”/“resolution” of those experiences or experience as a whole. Insofar as these concepts can be mapped reliably to behavior, subjective reports, or neuroimaging, with testable outcomes, this approach might be used for measures that track general properties of representational content (e.g., Siclari et al., 2018; Farnes et al., 2020; Aamodt et al., 2021). While this approach doesn’t solve the issue raised here—e.g., it is unclear whether a “less vivid” experience is “less conscious”—it can allow for investigation into experiential states that are far removed from normal wakefulness.

Conclusion

In sum, we argue that there are strong reasons to take a step back and critically re-examine our “traditional” assumptions about different states of consciousness. Although such issues have been discussed for some time, there seems to remain a tendency to still use outdated assumptions and terminology, e.g., that general anesthesia and slow-wave sleep entail full or nearly full unconsciousness. We suggest that focusing on approaches that provide a more pragmatic and nuanced characterization of different states and conditions might be less controversial, promote clarity, and can help build a stronger foundation for future studies.

Data availability statement

The original contributions presented in this study are included in the article/Supplementary material, further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding authors.

Author contributions

ASN wrote the first draft and did most of the work on the manuscript. All authors contributed to the ideas and arguments, writing, and revision of the manuscript.

Funding

This research was funded by the ConsciousBrainConcepts project under the Life Science Convergence Projects initiative of University of Oslo, and the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Framework Programme for Research and Innovation under the Specific Grant Agreements No. 945539 (Human Brain Project SGA3), No. 785907 (Human Brain Project SGA2; JFS, ASN, BEJ), and the Norwegian Research Council (NRC grant 262950/F20).

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher’s note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

Supplementary material

The Supplementary Material for this article can be found online at: https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fnhum.2022.987051/full#supplementary-material

Footnotes

  1. ^ A “phenomenology-first approach” (infer objective properties from subjective properties) has been proposed to sidestep the issue of inference of subjective properties from objective properties (Ellia et al., 2021). However, this method has been criticized for being tautological or unfalsifiable (Doerig et al., 2019; Kleiner and Hoel, 2021), but see (Negro, 2020) for a defense.
  2. ^ Changes in “brain states” are here taken to include changes at the micro and/or macro levels.
  3. ^ If the central research question is to understand why, how, or when, a system is conscious or not, one needs an exemplar of a system or state that is in fact not conscious (there is “not like anything to be”). This is similar to the hard problem of consciousness (Chalmers, 1995).
  4. ^ Unless otherwise stated, general anesthesia refers to forms of anesthesia, such as propofol, xenon, thiopental, and iso-, sevo-, and des-flurane, that induce slow-wave activity (SWA) in the EEG. In contrast, ketamine does not induce SWA and is associated with reports of vivid dreams (Leslie, 2010), and common EEG-based anesthesia monitors are not indicative of sedation depth (Hirota, 2006), which has given ketamine anesthesia a special case in consciousness research.
  5. ^ Anesthetic regimens that use IFT during surgery often deepen sedation if detecting a sufficiently complex IFT response during or prior to surgery, as well as usually employing a mix of analgesics, muscle relaxants, and anesthetics. This can skew dose-response estimates. Further, while increased anesthetic concentration does seem to reduce degree of IFT responsivity, it is debatable whether this marks a gradual decline in consciousness, or a move into different “states” of consciousness (e.g., dysanesthesia) (Pandit et al., 2015).
  6. ^ In Owen et al. (2006), the presence of neural activation in response to spoken sentences, similar to that of healthy participants, encouraged the researchers to attempt using this for communication.
  7. ^ The “classic” interpretation of blindsight is no phenomenology but complex behavior. Phillips (2021), however, proposes that there is phenomenology and behavior, but normally no report. Specifically, Phillips argues that blindsight is severely degraded vision, but due to negative response bias is not reported as such. This supports our argument that what we do or do not say or do does not necessarily reflect our conscious experience.
  8. ^ Integrated information theory (IIT) specifically aims to start from first principles and thus avoid the issue discussed here (although the mentioned assumptions are used as supporting arguments; e.g., Tononi, 2012; Oizumi et al., 2014). In fact, IIT, and several other structural theories (Doerig et al., 2021), imply that the entire brain (or some parts of it) is never fully unconscious, or that there might be phenomenological experiences locally which are not accessible for report later (or currently) (Lamme, 2010). IIT does, however, imply a “graded” construct in its theoretical measure “Phi” which has inspired empirical measures that broadly support the theory’s predictions (Casali et al., 2013; Sarasso et al., 2021). However, in order to validate the theory, one must assume that states like deep slow-wave sleep or general anesthesia are states of, at least, reduced consciousness, which leads to falsification problems (Doerig et al., 2019; Kleiner and Hoel, 2021).

References

Aamodt, A., Nilsen, A. S., Thürer, B., Moghadam, F. H., Kauppi, N., Juel, B. E., et al. (2021). EEG signal diversity varies with sleep stage and aspects of dream experience. Front. Psychol. 12:655884. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2021.655884

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bayne, T., Hohwy, J., and Owen, A. M. (2016). Are there levels of consciousness? Trends Cogn. Sci. 20, 405–413. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2016.03.009

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bayne, T., Seth, A. K., and Massimini, M. (2020). Are there islands of awareness? Trends Neurosci. 43, 6–16. doi: 10.1016/j.tins.2019.11.003

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bekinschtein, T. A., Dehaene, S., Rohaut, B., Tadel, F., Cohen, L., and Naccache, L. (2009). Neural signature of the conscious processing of auditory regularities. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 106, 1672–1677. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0809667106

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Block, N. (2007). Overflow, access, and attention. Behav. Brain Sci. 30, 530–548. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X07003111

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bonhomme, V., Staquet, C., Montupil, J., Defresne, A., Kirsch, M., Martial, C., et al. (2019). General anesthesia: A probe to explore consciousness. Front. Syst. Neurosci. 13:36. doi: 10.3389/fnsys.2019.00036

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brandner, B., Blagrove, M., McCallum, G., and Bromley, L. M. (1997). Dreams, images and emotions associated with propofol anaesthesia. Anaesthesia 52, 750–755. doi: 10.1111/j.1365-2044.1997.161-az0171.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Casali, A. G., Gosseries, O., Rosanova, M., Boly, M., Sarasso, S., Casali, K. R., et al. (2013). A theoretically based index of consciousness independent of sensory processing and behavior. Sci. Transl. Med. 5:198ra105. doi: 10.1126/scitranslmed.3006294

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Casarotto, S., Comanducci, A., Rosanova, M., Sarasso, S., Fecchio, M., Napolitani, M., et al. (2016). Stratification of unresponsive patients by an independently validated index of brain complexity. Ann. Neurol. 80, 718–729. doi: 10.1002/ana.24779

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Casey, C. P., Tanabe, S., Farahbakhsh, Z., Parker, M., Bo, A., White, M., et al. (2022). Distinct EEG signatures differentiate unconsciousness and disconnection during anaesthesia and sleep. Br. J. Anaesth. 128, 1006–1018. doi: 10.1016/j.bja.2022.01.010

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Chalmers, D. (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. J. Conscious. Stud. 2, 200–219.

Google Scholar

Cheong, S. H., Lee, K. M., Lim, S. H., Cho, K. R., Kim, M. H., Ko, M. J., et al. (2011). The effect of suggestion on unpleasant dreams induced by ketamine administration. Anesth. Analg. 112:1082. doi: 10.1213/ANE.0b013e31820eeb0e

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Crick, F., and Koch, C. (1990). Towards a neurobiological theory of consciousness. Semin. Neurosci. 2, 263–275.

Google Scholar

Crick, F., Koch, C. (1998). “The problem of consciousness,” in Consciousness and Emotion in Cognitive Science, eds Toribio, J., and Clark, A. (Abingdon: Routledge), 63–69. doi: 10.4324/9780203826430-4

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Demertzi, A., Tagliazucchi, E., Dehaene, S., Deco, G., Barttfeld, P., Raimondo, F., et al. (2019). Human consciousness is supported by dynamic complex patterns of brain signal coordination. Sci. Adv. 5:eaat7603. doi: 10.1126/sciadv.aat7603

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Doerig, A., Schurger, A., and Herzog, M. H. (2021). Hard criteria for empirical theories of consciousness. Cogn. Neurosci. 12, 41–62.

Google Scholar

Doerig, A., Schurger, A., Hess, K., and Herzog, M. H. (2019). The unfolding argument: Why IIT and other causal structure theories cannot explain consciousness. Conscious. Cogn. 72, 49–59. doi: 10.1016/j.concog.2019.04.002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dossani, R. H., Missios, S., and Nanda, A. (2015). The Legacy of Henry Molaison (1926–2008) and the impact of his bilateral mesial temporal lobe surgery on the study of human memory. World Neurosurg. 84, 1127–1135. doi: 10.1016/j.wneu.2015.04.031

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Eer, A. S., Padmanabhan, U., and Leslie, K. (2009). Propofol dose and incidence of dreaming during sedation. Eur. J. Anaesth. 26, 833–836. doi: 10.1097/EJA.0b013e32832c500c

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ellia, F., Hendren, J., Grasso, M., Kozma, C., Mindt, G., and P Lang, J. (2021). Consciousness and the fallacy of misplaced objectivity. Neurosci. Conscious. 2021:niab032. doi: 10.1093/nc/niab032

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Engemann, D. A., Raimondo, F., King, J.-R., Rohaut, B., Louppe, G., Faugeras, F., et al. (2018). Robust EEG-based cross-site and cross-protocol classification of states of consciousness. Brain 141, 3179–3192. doi: 10.1093/brain/awy251

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Farnes, N., Juel, B., Nilsen, A., Romundstad, L., and Storm, J. (2020). Increased Signal Diversity/Complexity of Spontaneous EEG, but not evoked EEG Responses, in Ketamine-Induced Psychedelic State in Humans [Data set]. Durham, NC: Dryad. doi: 10.5061/dryad.j9kd51c9q

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fazekas, P., and Overgaard, M. (2016). Multidimensional models of degrees and levels of consciousness. Trends Cogn. Sci. 20, 715–716. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2016.06.011

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ferenets, R., Lipping, T., Anier, A., Jäntti, V., Melto, S., and Hovilehto, S. (2006). Comparison of entropy and complexity measures for the assessment of depth of sedation. IEEE Trans. BioMed. Eng. 53, 1067–1077. doi: 10.1109/TBME.2006.873543

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ferrarelli, F., Massimini, M., Sarasso, S., Casali, A., Riedner, B. A., Angelini, G., et al. (2010). Breakdown in cortical effective connectivity during midazolam-induced loss of consciousness. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 107, 2681–2686. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0913008107

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Francken, J. C., Beerendonk, L., Molenaar, D., Fahrenfort, J. J., Kiverstein, J. D., Seth, A. K., et al. (2022). An academic survey on theoretical foundations, common assumptions and the current state of consciousness science. Neurosci. Conscious. 2022:niac011. doi: 10.1093/nc/niac011

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gaskell, A. L., Hight, D. F., Winders, J., Tran, G., Defresne, A., Bonhomme, V., et al. (2017). Frontal alpha-delta EEG does not preclude volitional response during anaesthesia: prospective cohort study of the isolated forearm technique. Br. J. Anaesth. 119, 664–673. doi: 10.1093/bja/aex170

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ghoneim, M. M., and Block, R. (1997). Learning and memory during general anesthesia: An update. J. Am. Soc. Anesth. 87, 387–410.

Google Scholar

Gibbs, F. A., Davis, H., and Lennox, W. G. (1935). The electro-encephalogram in epilepsy and in conditions of impaired consciousnesS. Arch. Neurol. Psychiatry 34, 1133–1148. doi: 10.1001/archneurpsyc.1935.02250240002001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gibson, R. M., Fernández-Espejo, D., Gonzalez-Lara, L. E., Kwan, B. Y., Lee, D. H., Owen, A. M., et al. (2014). Multiple tasks and neuroimaging modalities increase the likelihood of detecting covert awareness in patients with disorders of consciousness. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 8:950. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2014.00950

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gordillo, D., Ramos, da Cruz, J., Chkonia, E., Lin, W.-H., Favrod, O., et al. (2020). The EEG multiverse of schizophrenia. bioRxiv [Preprint]. doi: 10.1101/2020.12.21.20248665

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gosseries, O., Schnakers, C., Ledoux, D., Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Bruno, M.-A., Demertzi, A., et al. (2011). Automated EEG entropy measurements in coma, vegetative state/unresponsive wakefulness syndrome and minimally conscious state. Funct. Neurol. 26, 25–30.

PubMed Abstract | Google Scholar

Gyulaházi, J., Varga, K., Iglói, E., Redl, P., Kormos, J., and Fülesdi, B. (2015). The effect of preoperative suggestions on perioperative dreams and dream recalls after administration of different general anesthetic combinations: A randomized trial in maxillofacial surgery. BMC Anesth. 15:11. doi: 10.1186/1471-2253-15-11

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hatamimajoumerd, E., Apurva Ratan, Murty, N., Pitts, M., and Cohen, M. A. (2022). Decoding perceptual awareness across the brain with a no-report fMRI masking paradigm. Curr. Biol. [Epub ahead of print]. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2022.07.068

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hejja, P., and Galloon, S. (1975). A consideration of ketamine dreams. Can. Anaesth. Soc. J. 22, 100–105. doi: 10.1007/BF03004825

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hirota, K. (2006). Special cases: Ketamine, nitrous oxide and xenon. Best Pract. Res. Clin. Anaesthesiol. 20, 69–79. doi: 10.1016/j.bpa.2005.08.014

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Horikawa, T., and Kamitani, Y. (2017). Hierarchical neural representation of dreamed objects revealed by brain decoding with deep neural network features. Front. Comput. Neurosci. 11:4. doi: 10.3389/fncom.2017.00004

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Horikawa, T., Tamaki, M., Miyawaki, Y., and Kamitani, Y. (2013). Neural decoding of visual imagery during sleep. Science 340, 639–642. doi: 10.1126/science.1234330

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hudetz, A. G. (2008). Are we unconscious during general anesthesia? Int. Anesthesiol. Clin. 46, 25–42. doi: 10.1097/AIA.0b013e3181755db5

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Huth, A. G., Lee, T., Nishimoto, S., Bilenko, N. Y., Vu, A. T., and Gallant, J. L. (2016). Decoding the semantic content of natural movies from human brain activity. Front. Syst. Neurosci. 10:81. doi: 10.3389/fnsys.2016.00081

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Juel, B. E., Romundstad, L., Kolstad, F., Storm, J. F., and Larsson, P. G. (2018). Distinguishing anesthetized from awake state in patients: A new approach using one second segments of raw EEG. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 12:40. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2018.00040

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Käsmacher, H., Petermeyer, M., and Decker, C. (1996). Incidence and quality of dreaming during anesthesia with propofol in comparison with enflurane. Der Anaesthesist 45, 146–153. doi: 10.1007/s001010050249

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

King, J. R., Faugeras, F., Gramfort, A., Schurger, A., El Karoui, I., Sitt, J. D., et al. (2013). Single-trial decoding of auditory novelty responses facilitates the detection of residual consciousness. NeuroImage 83, 726–738. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2013.07.013

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kleiner, J., and Hoel, E. (2021). Falsification and consciousness. Neurosci. Conscious. 2021:niab001. doi: 10.1093/nc/niab001

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Koch, C., Massimini, M., Boly, M., and Tononi, G. (2016). Neural correlates of consciousness: progress and problems. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 17, 307–321. doi: 10.1038/nrn.2016.22

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lamme, V. A. (2010). How neuroscience will change our view on consciousness. Cogn. Neurosci. 1, 204–220.

Google Scholar

Latham, A. J., Ellis, C., Chan, L.-C., and Braddon-Mitchell, D. (2017). The validation of consciousness meters: The idiosyncratic and intransitive sequence of conscious levels. J. Conscious. Stud. 24, 103–111.

Google Scholar

Laureys, S. (2005). The neural correlate of (un)awareness: Lessons from the vegetative state. Trends Cogn. Sci. 9, 556–559. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2005.10.010

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lee, U., Ku, S., Noh, G., Baek, S., Choi, B., and Mashour, G. A. (2013). Disruption of frontal-parietal communication by ketamine, propofol, and sevoflurane. Anesthesiology 118, 1264–1275. doi: 10.1097/ALN.0b013e31829103f5

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lepauvre, A., and Melloni, L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress and challenges. Philos. Mind Sci. 2, 1–28.

Google Scholar

Leslie, K. (2010). “Dreaming during anesthesia,” in Consciousness, Awareness, and Anesthesia, ed. G. A. Mashour (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 74–89.

Google Scholar

Leslie, K. (2017). “Awareness and dreaming during TIVA,” in Total Intravenous Anesthesia and Target Controlled Infusions: A Comprehensive Global Anthology, eds A. R. Absalom and K. P. Mason (Berlin: Springer International Publishing), 783–796. doi: 10.1007/978-3-319-47609-4_44

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Leslie, K., Skrzypek, H., Paech, M. J., Kurowski, I., and Whybrow, T. (2007). Dreaming during anesthesia and anesthetic depth in elective surgery patients: a prospective cohort study. Anesthesiology 106, 33–42. doi: 10.1097/00000542-200701000-00010

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Leslie, K., Sleigh, J., Paech, M. J., Voss, L., Lim, C. W., and Sleigh, C. (2009). Dreaming and electroencephalographic changes during anesthesia maintained with propofol or desflurane. Anesthesiology 111, 547–555. doi: 10.1097/ALN.0b013e3181adf768

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. Pac. Philos. Q. 64, 354–361. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0114.1983.tb00207.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Linassi, F., Zanatta, P., Tellaroli, P., Ori, C., and Carron, M. (2018). Isolated forearm technique: A meta-analysis of connected consciousness during different general anaesthesia regimens. Br. J. Anaesth. 121, 198–209. doi: 10.1016/j.bja.2018.02.019

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

MacDonald, A. A., Naci, L., MacDonald, P. A., and Owen, A. M. (2015). Anesthesia and neuroimaging: Investigating the neural correlates of unconsciousness. Trends Cogn. Sci. 19, 100–107. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2014.12.005

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

McNamara, P., Johnson, P., McLaren, D., Harris, E., Beauharnais, C., and Auerbach, S. (2010). “Rem and nrem sleep mentation,” in International Review of Neurobiology, eds A. Clow and P. McNamara (Cambridge: Academic Press), 69–86. doi: 10.1016/S0074-7742(10)92004-7

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Monti, M. M., Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Coleman, M. R., Boly, M., Pickard, J. D., Tshibanda, L., et al. (2010). Willful modulation of brain activity in disorders of consciousness. N. Engl. J. Med. 362, 579–589. doi: 10.1056/NEJMoa0905370

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philos. Rev. 83, 435–450.

Google Scholar

Negro, N. (2020). Phenomenology-first versus third-person approaches in the science of consciousness: the case of the integrated information theory and the unfolding argument. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 19, 979–996. doi: 10.1007/s11097-020-09681-3

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nicolaou, N., and Georgiou, J. (2011). The use of permutation entropy to characterize sleep electroencephalograms. Clin. EEG Neurosci. 42, 24–28. doi: 10.1177/155005941104200107

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nieminen, J. O., Gosseries, O., Massimini, M., Saad, E., Sheldon, A. D., Boly, M., et al. (2016). Consciousness and cortical responsiveness: A within-state study during non-rapid eye movement sleep. Sci. Rep. 6:30932. doi: 10.1038/srep30932

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nielsen, T. A. (2000). A review of mentation in REM and NREM sleep: “Covert” REM sleep as a possible reconciliation of two opposing models. Behav. Brain Sci. 23, 851–866. doi: 10.1017/s0140525x0000399x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nilsen, A. S., Juel, B. Thürer, B., and Storm, J. F. (2020). Proposed EEG measures of consciousness: A systematic, comparative review. PsyArXiv [Preprint]. doi: 10.31234/osf.io/sjm4a

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nishida, S., and Nishimoto, S. (2018). Decoding naturalistic experiences from human brain activity via distributed representations of words. NeuroImage 180, 232–242. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2017.08.017

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Noreika, V., Jylhänkangas, L., Móró, L., Valli, K., Kaskinoro, K., Aantaa, R., et al. (2011). Consciousness lost and found: Subjective experiences in an unresponsive state. Brain Cogn. 77, 327–334. doi: 10.1016/j.bandc.2011.09.002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Noreika, V., Valli, K., Lahtela, H., and Revonsuo, A. (2009). Early-night serial awakenings as a new paradigm for studies on NREM dreaming. Int. J. Psychophysiol. 74, 14–18. doi: 10.1016/j.ijpsycho.2009.06.002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Northoff, G., and Lamme, V. (2020). Neural signs and mechanisms of consciousness: Is there a potential convergence of theories of consciousness in sight? Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 118, 568–587. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2020.07.019

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Oizumi, M., Albantakis, L., and Tononi, G. (2014). From the phenomenology to the mechanisms of consciousness: Integrated information theory 3.0. PLoS Comput. Biol. 10:e1003588. doi: 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1003588

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Oudiette, D., Leu, S., Pottier, M., Buzare, M.-A., Brion, A., and Arnulf, I. (2009). Dreamlike mentations during sleepwalking and sleep terrors in adults. Sleep 32, 1621–1627. doi: 10.1093/sleep/32.12.1621

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Owen, A. M., Coleman, M. R., Boly, M., Davis, M. H., Laureys, S., and Pickard, J. D. (2006). Detecting awareness in the vegetative state. Science 313:1402. doi: 10.1126/science.1130197

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Palanca, B. J. A., Mashour, G. A., and Avidan, M. S. (2009). Processed electroencephalogram in depth of anesthesia monitoring. Curr. Opin. Anaesthesiol. 22, 553–559. doi: 10.1097/ACO.0b013e3283304032

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pandit, J. J., Russell, I. F., and Wang, M. (2015). Interpretations of responses using the isolated forearm technique in general anaesthesia: A debate. Br. J. Anaesth. 115, i32–i45. doi: 10.1093/bja/aev106

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Phillips, I. (2021). Blindsight is qualitatively degraded conscious vision. Psychol. Rev. 128, 558–584. doi: 10.1037/rev0000254

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pinker, S. (2003). How the Mind Works. New York, NY: Penguin UK.

Google Scholar

Posner, J. B., Plum, F., Saper, C. B., and Schiff, N. (2007). Plum and posner’s diagnosis of stupor and coma. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Revach, D., and Salti, M. (2021). Expanding the discussion: Revision of the fundamental assumptions framing the study of the neural correlates of consciousness. Conscious. Cogn. 96:103229. doi: 10.1016/j.concog.2021.103229

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rosen, M. G. (2013). What I make up when I wake up: Anti-experience views and narrative fabrication of dreams. Front. Psychol. 4:514. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00514

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rush, D. K. (1988). Scopolamine amnesia of passive avoidance: A deficit of information acquisition. Behav. Neural Biol. 50, 255–274. doi: 10.1016/s0163-1047(88)90938-7

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Russell, I. F. (2006). The Narcotrend “depth of anaesthesia” monitor cannot reliably detect consciousness during general anaesthesia: An investigation using the isolated forearm technique. Br. J. Anaesth. 96, 346–352. doi: 10.1093/bja/ael017

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sanders, R. D., Gaskell, A., Raz, A., Winders, J., Stevanovic, A., Rossaint, R., et al. (2017). Incidence of connected consciousness after tracheal intubation: A prospective, international, multicenter cohort study of the isolated forearm technique. Anesthesiology 126, 214–222. doi: 10.1097/ALN.0000000000001479

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sanders, R. D., Tononi, G., Laureys, S., and Sleigh, J. W. (2012). Unresponsiveness ≠ unconsciousness. Anesthesiology 116, 946–959. doi: 10.1097/ALN.0b013e318249d0a7

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sarasso, S., Boly, M., Napolitani, M., Gosseries, O., Charland-Verville, V., Casarotto, S., et al. (2015). Consciousness and complexity during unresponsiveness induced by propofol. xenon, and ketamine. Curr. Biol. 25, 3099–3105. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2015.10.014

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sarasso, S., Casali, A. G., Casarotto, S., Rosanova, M., Sinigaglia, C., and Massimini, M. (2021). Consciousness and complexity: a consilience of evidence. Neurosci. Conscious. 1–24. doi: 10.1093/nc/niab023

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schartner, M. M., Pigorini, A., Gibbs, S. A., Arnulfo, G., Sarasso, S., Barnett, L., et al. (2017). Global and local complexity of intracranial EEG decreases during NREM sleep. Neurosci. Conscious. 2017:niw022. doi: 10.1093/nc/niw022

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schartner, M. M., Seth, A., Noirhomme, Q., Boly, M., Bruno, M.-A., Laureys, S., et al. (2015). Complexity of multi-dimensional spontaneous EEG decreases during propofol induced general anaesthesia. PLoS One 10:e0133532. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0133532

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schuller, P. J., Newell, S., Strickland, P. A., and Barry, J. J. (2015). Response of bispectral index to neuromuscular block in awake volunteers. Br. J. Anaesth. 115(Suppl. 1):i95–i103. doi: 10.1093/bja/aev072

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schwitzgebel, E. (2008). The unreliability of naive introspection. Philos. Rev. 117, 245–273.

Google Scholar

Searle, J. R. (1998). How to study consciousness scientifically. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. Series B Biol. Sci. 353, 1935–1942. doi: 10.1098/rstb.1998.0346

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sessler, C. N., Gosnell, M. S., Grap, M. J., Brophy, G. M., O’Neal, P. V., Keane, K. A., et al. (2002). The Richmond agitation–sedation scale. Am. J. Respir. Crit. Care Med. 166, 1338–1344. doi: 10.1164/rccm.2107138

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Seth, A. (2021). Being you: a new science of consciousness. New York, NY: Penguin.

Google Scholar

Seth, A. K. (2016). The hard problem of consciousness is a distraction from the real one–anil k seth| aeon essays. Aeon. Available online at: https://aeon.co/essays/the-Hard-Problem-of-Consciousness-Is-a-Distraction-from-the-Real-One (accessed November 25, 2019).

Google Scholar

Seth, A. K., Izhikevich, E., Reeke, G. N., and Edelman, G. M. (2006). Theories and measures of consciousness: An extended framework. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 103, 10799–10804. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0604347103

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Siclari, F., Baird, B., Perogamvros, L., Bernardi, G., LaRocque, J. J., Riedner, B., et al. (2017). The neural correlates of dreaming. Nat. Neurosci. 20, 872–878. doi: 10.1038/nn.4545

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Siclari, F., Bernardi, G., Cataldi, J., and Tononi, G. (2018). Dreaming in NREM sleep: A high-density eeg study of slow waves and spindles. J. Neurosci. 38, 9175–9185. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.0855-18.2018

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sleigh, J. W., Andrzejowski, J., Steyn-Ross, A., and Steyn-Ross, M. (1999). The bispectral index: a measure of depth of sleep? Anesth. Analg. 88, 659–661. doi: 10.1097/00000539-199903000-00035

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sligte, I. G., Scholte, H. S., and Lamme, V. A. F. (2008). Are there multiple visual short-term memory stores? PLoS One 3:e1699. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0001699

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Smith, K. (2013). Brain decoding: Reading minds. Nature 502, 428–430. doi: 10.1038/502428a

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sternbach, G. L. (2000). The Glasgow coma scale. J. Emerg. Med. 19, 67–71. doi: 10.1016/s0736-4679(00)00182-7

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Stickgold, R., Malia, A., Fosse, R., Propper, R., and Hobson, J. A. (2001). Brain-mind states: I. Longitudinal field study of sleep/wake factors influencing mentation report length. Sleep 24, 171–179. doi: 10.1093/sleep/24.2.171

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Stoerig, P., and Cowey, A. (1997). Blindsight in man and monkey. Brain 120, 535–559. doi: 10.1093/brain/120.3.535

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Suzuki, H., Uchiyama, M., Tagaya, H., Ozaki, A., Kuriyama, K., Aritake, S., et al. (2004). Dreaming during non-rapid eye movement sleep in the absence of prior rapid eye movement sleep. Sleep 27, 1486–1490. doi: 10.1093/sleep/27.8.1486

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tononi, G. (2012). Integrated information theory of consciousness: An updated account. Arch. Ital. Biol. 150, 293–329.

Google Scholar

Tononi, G., and Massimini, M. (2008). Why does consciousness fade in early sleep? Ann. N.Y.Acad. Sci. 1129, 330–334. doi: 10.1196/annals.1417.024

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., and Rosch, E. (2017). The embodied mind, revised edition: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge: MIT press.

Google Scholar

Veselis, R. A., Pryor, K. O., Reinsel, R. A., Mehta, M., Pan, H., and Johnson, R. (2008). Low-dose propofol–induced amnesia is not due to a failure of encodingleft inferior prefrontal cortex is still active. Anesthesiology 109, 213–224. doi: 10.1097/ALN.0b013e31817fd8ae

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Voss, L., and Sleigh, J. (2007). Monitoring consciousness: The current status of EEG-based depth of anaesthesia monitors. Best Pract. Res. Clin. Anaesthesiol. 21, 313–325. doi: 10.1016/j.bpa.2007.04.003

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Walter, J. (2021). Consciousness as a multidimensional phenomenon: Implications for the assessment of disorders of consciousness. Neurosci. Conscious. 2021:niab047. doi: 10.1093/nc/niab047

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wang, L., Wu, E. X., and Chen, F. (2021). EEG-based auditory attention decoding using speech-level-based segmented computational models. J. Neural. Eng. 18, 1–17. doi: 10.1088/1741-2552/abfeba

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wilson, S. L., Vaughan, R. W., and Stephen, C. R. (1975). Awareness, dreams, and hallucinations associated with general anesthesia. Anesth. Analg. 54, 609–617. doi: 10.1213/00000539-197509000-00010

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Windt, J. M., Nielsen, T., and Thompson, E. (2016). Does consciousness disappear in dreamless sleep? Trends Cogn. Sci. 20, 871–882. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2016.09.006

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: consciousness, unconsciousness, anesthesia, sleep, disorders of consciousness

Citation: Sevenius Nilsen A, Juel BE, Thürer B, Aamodt A and Storm JF (2022) Are we really unconscious in “unconscious” states? Common assumptions revisited. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 16:987051. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2022.987051

Received: 05 July 2022; Accepted: 08 September 2022;
Published: 05 October 2022.

Edited by:

Joel Frohlich, University of Tübingen, Germany

Reviewed by:

Simone Sarasso, University of Milan, Italy
Vladyslav Vyazovskiy, University of Oxford, United Kingdom
Geoffrey Laforge, Western University, Canada

Copyright © 2022 Sevenius Nilsen, Juel, Thürer, Aamodt and Storm. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Andre Sevenius Nilsen, sevenius.nilsen@gmail.com; Bjørn E. Juel, bjorneju@gmail.com; Johan F. Storm, j.f.storm@medisin.uio.no

Download