Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-jr42d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T00:11:34.090Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

4 - The Role of Information Sampling in Risky Choice

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 February 2010

Ralph Hertwig
Affiliation:
University of Basel, Switzerland
Greg Barron
Affiliation:
Harvard Business School
Elke U. Weber
Affiliation:
Columbia University
Ido Erev
Affiliation:
Technion, Israel Institute of Technology
Klaus Fiedler
Affiliation:
Ruprecht-Karls-Universität Heidelberg, Germany
Peter Juslin
Affiliation:
Umeå Universitet, Sweden
Get access

Summary

Life is a gamble. True to the cliché, we can rarely be certain of the consequences of our everyday actions. Presumably because of life's lack of certainty, much of the psychological research on decision making under risk is devoted to the study of choices between monetary gambles or prospects. With few exceptions, the outcomes and outcome probabilities of such gambles are explicitly described to the decision maker before he or she makes a choice. How often are life's gambles described in this way? When we decide whether to back up our computer's hard drive, cross a busy street, or go out on a date, we often do not know the complete range of the possible outcomes, let alone their probabilities. Yet we routinely make such decisions, usually without difficulty. We do so by drawing upon our experience with the relevant prospects, for instance, by recalling the outcomes of previous choices. Though effective, sampling from experience brings with it the potential to generate a skewed picture of the risky prospects we face. As we will argue here, this potential is greatest when the outcome probabilities are small and relatively few outcomes have been experienced by the decision maker. Under these circumstances, decisions derived from experience are likely to be systematically different from those made in full knowledge of the outcomes and outcome probabilities.

In this chapter, we investigate risky decisions made on the basis of sampled experience. Three findings deserve emphasis.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anderson, N. H. (1981). Foundations of information integration theory. New York: Academic PressGoogle Scholar
Atkinson, R. C., & Shiffrin, R. M. (1968). Human memory: A proposed system and its control processes. In Spence, K. W. & Spence, J. T. (Eds.), The psychology of learning and motivation: Advances in research and theory (Vol 2., 89–195). New York: Academic PressGoogle Scholar
Barkan, R., Zohar, D., & Erev, I. (1998). Accidents and decision making under uncertainty: A comparison of four models. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 74, 118–144CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Barron, G., & Erev, I. (2003). Small feedback-based decisions and their limited correspondence to description-based decisions. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 16, 215–233CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Big News. (2004, May 22). The Economist, 371, 87
Bush, R., & Mosteller, F. (1955). Stochastic models for learning. New York: WileyCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Camerer, C. F. (2000). Prospect theory in the wild: Evidence from the field. In Kahneman, D. & Tversky, A. (Eds.), Choices, values, and frames (pp. 288–300). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Davis, J. H. (1984). Order in the courtroom. In Miller, D. J., Blackman, D. G., & Chapman, A. J. (Eds.), Perspectives in psychology and law. New York: WileyGoogle Scholar
Dubner, S. J. (2004, May 17). The silver thief. The New Yorker, 74–85Google Scholar
Fiedler, K. (2000). On mere considering: The subjective experience of truth. In H. Bless & J. P. Forgas (Eds.), The message within: The role of subjective experience in social cognition and behavior (pp. 13–36)
Fiedler, K., Armbruster, T., Nickel, S., Walther, E., & Asbeck, J. (1996). Constructive biases in social judgment: Experiments on the self-verification of question contents. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71, 861–873CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Goldstein, W. M., & Weber, E. U. (1997). Content and discontent: Indications and implications of domain specificity in preferential decision making. In Goldstein, W. M. & Hogarth, R. M. (Eds.), Research on judgment and decision making: Currents, connections, and controversies (pp. 566–617). New York: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Gonzalez, R., & Wu, G. (1999). On the shape of the probability weighting function. Cognitive Psychology, 38, 129–166CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gregory, W. L., Cialdini, R. B., & Carpenter, K. M. (1982). Self-relevant scenarios as mediators of likelihood estimates and compliance: Does imagining make it so?Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 43, 89–99CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hertwig, R., Barron, G., Weber, E. U., & Erev, I. (2004). Decisions from experience and the effect of rare events in risky choice. Psychological Science, 15, 534–539CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hogarth, R. M., & Einhorn, H. J. (1992). Order effects in belief updating: The belief-adjustment model. Cognitive Psychology, 24, 1–55CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kareev, Y. (2000). Seven (indeed, plus or minus two) and the detection of correlations. Psychological Review, 107, 397–402CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kareev, Y., Arnon, S., & Horwitz-Zeliger, R. (2002). On the misperception of variability. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 131, 287–297CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kunreuther, H., Ginsberg, R., Miller, L., Sagi, P., Slovic, P., Borkin, B., & Katz, N. (1978). Disaster insurance protection: Public policy lessons. New York: WileyGoogle Scholar
Lopes, L. L. (1983). Some thoughts on the psychological concept of risk. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 9, 137–144Google Scholar
March, J. G. (1996). Learning to be risk averse. Psychological Review, 103, 309–319CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Melville, H. (1993). Moby Dick. New York: Barnes & Noble Books. (Original work published 1851.)Google Scholar
Nisbett, R., & Ross, L. (1980). Human inference: Strategies and shortcomings of human judgment. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-HallGoogle Scholar
Real, L. A. (1991). Animal choice behavior and the evolution of cognitive architecture. Science, 253, 980–986CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Savage, L. J. (1954). The foundations of statistics. New York: WileyGoogle Scholar
Slovic, P., & Weber, E. U. (2002). Perception of risk posed by extreme events. White paper for conference “Risk Management Strategies in an Uncertain World,” Palisades, NY, April 12, 2002
Stern, L., Iqbal, N., Seshadri, P., Chicano, K. L., Daily, D. A., McGrory, J., Williams, M., Gracely, E. J., Samaha, F. F. (2004). The effects of low-carbohydrate versus conventional weight loss diets in severely obese adults: One-year follow-up of a randomized trial. Annals of Internal Medicine, 140, 778–785CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weber, E. U., & Kirsner, B. (1996). Reasons for rank-dependent utility evaluation. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 14, 41–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weber, E. U., Shafir, S., & Blais, A.-R. (2004). Predicting risk-sensitivity in humans and lower animals: Risk as variance or coefficient of variation. Psychological Review, 111, 430–445CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wegner, D. M., Wenzlaff, R., Kerker, R. M., & Beattie, A. E. (1981). Incrimination through innuendo: Can media questions become public answers?Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 40, 822–832CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yancy, W. S. Jr., Olsen, M. K., Guyton, J. R., Bakst, R. P., Westman, E. C. (2004). A low-carbohydrate, ketogenic diet versus a low-fat diet to treat obesity and hyperlipidemia. Annals of Internal Medicine, 140, 769–777CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×