Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Suing for Peace in the War Against Mentalism

  • Published:
Perspectives on Behavior Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The antimentalists’ war against mentalism has not vanquished it. To examine why, we focus on two theses—mind as causal and internal—and three standard attacks against mentalism as defined by both theses: 1) mentalism implies dualism; 2) mind is unobservable, which hinders its scientific study; and 3) mentalism is impractical. These salients fail because: 1) if the mind is causal and internal, it must be material; 2) the observable/unobservable distinction is too problematic, with antimentalists equivocal about where to draw that line, with some even embracing publicly unobservable behavior as causally relevant; and 3) mentalism has not been demonstrated to be less practical than antimentalism. For the war on mentalism to succeed, stronger attacks must be devised, both scientific and philosophical. We contemplate some possibilities, while expressing doubts as to the wisdom of continuing the war. Peace may be better than war, and the resulting intellectual commerce may be good for both sides.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Uttal suggests that no side of the “war between mentalism and behaviorism” can ever claim victory because both are deeply mistaken in their attacks and defenses on one key issue: the scientific tractability of the mind, which the author sees as an epistemological issue. The scientific tractability of the mind will be part of our analysis later on, but in a different direction.

  2. Antimentalists might worry that this noun forces viewing mind as “substance” (technical philosophical lingo for “thing”) and therefore takes us too close to substance dualism. Substance dualists do use the noun in that way, but many others, like us, use it only as a convenient shorthand to refer to “minding” as a process consisting of (perhaps causally connected) states and events. In most current ontologies of mind, the noun is used in this way. This is similar to the observation that the rotation (or “rotating”) of a wheel is not the same as the wheel (a thing), but a process of the wheel. Descartes used the analogy to weight—it is not a thing added to a body, but rather a property of the body. We use “mind” as a harmless reification of “minding,” just as behavior analysts use “behavior” as a harmless reification of “behaving.”

  3. Some antimentalists may still view us as mentalists because we hypothesize processes measured in different dimensions than behavior, or because of other things we have said. Evaluate our work on its own merits, which is fairer than dismissing it by branding us turncoats.

  4. We use these two terms and “nonmaterial” interchangeably in Descartes’s sense, to refer to the lack of all spatial dimensions (“length, breadth, and height,” as he often put it). Such things are said to “lack extension” or “be unextended.” This use echoes those in some of the above quotations.

  5. We also use these two terms equivalently, also following Descartes, to refer to things extended in Euclidean space, in the sense of having all three spatial dimensions. All everyday-life medium-sized entities, as well as most entities scientists study (including human bodies), are material or physical in this sense. It is arguable whether entities such as singularities, quarks, and bosons satisfy this criterion. The criterion is therefore imperfect, like all category boundaries.

  6. Some have argued that Descartes was not a Cartesian (e.g., Baker & Morris, 1996; Christofidou, 2001, 2016). They argue that Cartesian dualism is a misinterpretation of Descartes’s view by one of his contemporaries (Antoine Arnauld’s so-called “Argument from Doubt”). We will not get into this discussion here. We will speak just of “Cartesian dualism,” a standard label, acknowledging the possibility that it is a misnomer and that Descartes may not have held such position.

  7. Much hinges on what causation is, but we cannot delve into this vast topic here, as mentalism does not entail any particular view of causation. Nor does any current view of causation propound nonphysical causation.

  8. Obviously, this makes sense if pain is different from pain behavior, as all ontologies of mind propose, except for a mind-behavior identity theory according to which “[p]ain is pain overt behavior” (Rachlin, 2014, p. 56). In this theory, there cannot be pain without pain behavior. Therefore, there cannot be zombies, because if they exhibit pain behavior, pace Rachlin, they experience pain. We are not defending the possibility of zombies here. We only mention it to illustrate how causation is incompatible with a contemporary defense of property dualism that calls up the undead as arguments. The impossibility of zombies, as implied by a mind-behavior identity, does not invalidate our pedagogical use of them here. Causation also implies their impossibility, again supporting our point. A mind-behavior identity theory (denying feelings absent overt feeling behavior), then, is not the only way to kill zombies. Embracing mental causation is another.

  9. This use also applies to “inside” and “inner.” Often, these terms are interchangeable with “in” (e.g., “My mind is in my head”). We are not concerned with other uses of “in” (e.g., ones that describe a state of the organism: “I am in love,” “I am in good health”) that are not interchangeable with the standard one we adopt here, legitimate though they might be. Such other uses of “in” are not at work in assertions that the mind is internal or inner to, or inside, the body.

  10. Nor can ordinary mentalistic language be dualistic either, as Ryle (1949) famously argued. This argument allows antimentalists to indulge in ordinary mentalistic talk without committing to mentalism.

  11. To be fair to Uttal, he never denied the existence of the mind; just its accessibility to scientific treatment. See (Killeen, 2017) for an appreciation of his work and life.

  12. Peirce (1901/1958) anticipated this by noting that scientists regularly cycle through abductive, deductive, and inductive inferences (in that order), viewing the three as equally integral to science. During the first half of the twentieth century, philosophers of science dismissed this methodological pluralism in favor of a methodological reductionism where one side (the Carnapian logical positivists) defended the primacy of the inductive method and the other side (Popperian falsificationists) did the same for the hypothetico-deductive method. Not anymore. After the demise of logical positivism, philosophers of science have leaned towards Peirce’s methodological pluralism (not without controversy and further elaboration of Peirce’s initial ideas).

  13. Popper (1963) said: “A false theory may be as great an achievement as a true one. And many false theories have been more helpful in our search for truth than some less interesting theories which are still accepted. For false theories can be helpful in many ways; they may for example suggest some more or less radical modifications, and they may stimulate criticism” (p. 190). In fact, Popper (1974) never said that a theory should be abandoned as soon as it is falsified: “. . . I have used the terms ‘elimination’, and even ‘rejection’ when discussing ‘refutation.’ But it is clear . . . . that these terms mean, when applied to a scientific theory, that it is eliminated as a contender for the truth—that is, refuted, but not necessarily abandoned. . . . I have often pointed out that any such refutation is fallible. . . . I do not conflate even admitted falsity with the need to abandon a theory. . .” (p. 1009).

References

  • Adams, C. D., & Dickinson, A. (1981). Instrumental responding following reinforcer devaluation. Quarterly journal of experimental psychology, 33B, 109–121. https://doi.org/10.1080/14640748108400816.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amsel, A. (1989). Behaviorism, neobehaviorism, and cognitivism in learning theory: Historical and contemporary perspectives. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aoyama, K., & McSweeney, F. K. (2001). Habituation may contribute to within-session decreases in responding under high-rate schedules of reinforcement. Animal learning and behavior, 29, 79–91. https://doi.org/10.3758/BF03192817.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, G., & Morris, K. J. (1996). Descartes’ dualism. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bandura, A. (1999). Social cognitive theory of personality. In L. A. Pervin & O. P. John (Eds.), Handbook of personality: Theory and research (2nd ed., pp. 154–196). New York, NY: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baum, W. M. (2011). What is radical behaviorism? A review of Jay Moore’s conceptual foundations of radical behaviorism. Journal of the experimental analysis of behavior, 95, 119–126. https://doi.org/10.1901/jeab.2011.95-119.

    Article  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Baum, W. M. (2012). Rethinking reinforcement: allocation, induction, and contingency. Journal of the experimental analysis of behavior, 97, 101–124. doi: 10.1901%2Fjeab.2012.97–101.

  • Baum, W. M. (2017). Understanding behaviorism: behavior, culture, and evolution (3rd ed.). Malden, MA: Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Baum, W. M., & Heath, J. L. (1992). Behavioral explanations and intentional explanations in psychology. American psychologist, 47, 1312–1317. https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.47.11.1312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Breland, K., & Breland, M. (1961). The misbehavior of organisms. American psychologist, 16, 681–684. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0040090.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buechner, J. (2008). Gödel, Putnam, and functionalism: a new reading of “Representation and Reality”. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M., & Ardila, R. (1987). Philosophy of psychology. New York, NY: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Burgos, J. E. (2015). Antidualism and antimentalism in radical behaviorism. Behavior & philosophy, 43, 1–37 Retrieved from http://www.behavior.org/resource.php?id=915.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burgos, J. E. (2016). Mentalism versus dualism: replies to commentaries. Behavior & philosophy, 44, 46–79 Retrieved from http://www.behavior.org/resource.php?id=997.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burgos, J. E., & Donahoe, J. W. (2016). Unified principle of reinforcement: a reply to N. T. Calvin and J. J. McDowell. Behavioural processes, 126, 46–54. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.beproc.2016.03.003.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Burnham, K. P., Anderson, D. R., & Huyvaert, K. P. (2010). AIC model selection and multimodel inference in behavioral ecology: some background, observations, and comparisons. Behavioral ecology & sociobiology, 65, 23–35. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00265-010-1029-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind: in search of a fundamental theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiesa, M. (1994). Radical behaviorism: the philosophy and the science. Boston, MA: Authors Cooperative.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christofidou, A. (2001). Descartes’ dualism: Correcting some misconceptions. Journal of the history of philosophy, 39, 215–238. https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2003.0098.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christofidou, A. (2016). Jose E. Burgos “Antidualism and antimentalism in radical behaviourism”: critical discussion. Behaviour & philosophy, 43, 6–17 Retrieved from http://www.behavior.org/resource.php?id=993.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of philosophy, 78, 67–90 Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/2025900.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 7–19 Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/3328150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colwill, R. M., & Rescorla, R. A. (1990). Evidence for the hierarchical structure of instrumental learning. Animal learning & behavior, 18, 71–82. https://doi.org/10.3758/BF03205241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Critchfield, T. S., & Miller, J. R. (2017). Editorial: are theories of reinforcement necessary? Behavior analyst, 40, 11–16. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40614-017-0113-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1970). Mental events. In L. Foster & J. W. Swanson (Eds.), Experience and theory (pp. 79–101). Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press & Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davison, M., & Baum, W. M. (2006). Do conditional reinforcers count? Journal of the experimental analysis of behavior, 86, 269–283. doi: 10.1901%2Fjeab.2006.56-05.

  • Davison, M., & Jones, B. M. (1995). A quantitative analysis of extreme choice. Journal of the experimental analysis of behavior, 64, 147–162. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1350107/.

  • Day, W. (1983). On the difference between radical and methodological behaviorism. Behaviorism, 1, 89–102 Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/27759016.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1978). Brainstorms: philosophical essays on mind and psychology. Cambridge, MA: Bradford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donahoe, J. W. (1996). On the relation between behavior analysis and biology. Behavior analyst, 19, 71–73. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03392740.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Dougher, M. J. (2016). Still some explaining to do: a review of the escape of the mind by Howard Rachlin. Journal of the experimental analysis of behavior, 106, 254–264. https://doi.org/10.1002/jeab.229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dror, I. E., & Harnad, S. (2008). Offloading cognition onto cognitive technology. In cognition distributed: how cognitive technology extends our minds (Vol. 16). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, J. L. (1961). Production of polydipsia in normal rats by an intermittent food schedule. Science, 133, 195–196. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.133.3447.195.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, W. W., Groff, R. A., & Roane, H. S. (2011). Applied behavior analysis: history, philosophy, principles, and basic methods. In W. E. Fisher, C. C. Piazza, & H. S. Roane (Eds.), Handbook of applied behavior analysis (pp. 3–13). New York, NY: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiske, S. T., & Taylor, S. E. (2017). Social cognition: from brains to culture (3rd ed.). London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1968). Psychological explanation: an introduction to the philosophy of psychology. New York, NY: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (2011). Evidentialism and truth. In T. Dougherty (Ed.), Evidentialism and its discontents (pp. 179–191). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Greenwald, A. G. (2012). There is nothing so theoretical as a good method. Perspectives on psychological science, 7, 99–108. https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691611434210.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hayes, S. C. (1993). Analytic goals and the varieties of scientific contextualism. In S. C. Hayes, L. J. Hayes, H. W. Reese, & T. R. Sarbin (Eds.), Varieties of scientific contextualism (pp. 11–27). Reno, NV: Context Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayes, L. J., & Fryling, M. (2009). Overcoming the pseudo-problem of private events in the analysis of behavior. Behavior & philosophy, 37, 39–57 Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/41472421.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holland, J. G. (1958). Counting by humans on a fixed-ratio schedule of reinforcement. Journal of the experimental analysis of behavior, 1(2), 179–181.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, C. (1943). Principles of behavior. New York, NY: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. The philosophical quarterly, 32, 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kantor, J. R. (1933). A survey of the science of psychology. Bloomington, IN: Principia Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kantor, J. R. (1981). Interbehavioral philosophy. Chicago, IL: Principia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kihlstrom, J. F. (1999). The psychological unconscious. In L. A. Pervin & O. P. John (Eds.), Handbook of personality: theory and research (2nd ed., pp. 424–442). New York, NY: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Killeen, P. R. (2004). Minding behavior. Behavior & philosophy, 32(1), 125–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Killeen, P. R. (2011). Models of trace decay, eligibility for reinforcement, and delay of reinforcement gradients, from exponential to hyperboloid. Behavioural processes, 87, 57–63. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.beproc.2010.12.016.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Killeen, P. (2017). One of us. Psychological record, 67, 133–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Killeen, P. R., & Jacobs, K. W. (2017). Coal is not black, snow is not white, food is not a reinforcer: the roles of affordances and dispositions in the analysis of behavior. Behavior analyst, 40, 1–22. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40614-016-0080-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kline, M. (1980). Mathematics, the loss of certainty. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Köhler, W. (1938). Simple structural functions in the chimpanzee and in the chicken. In W. D. Ellis (Ed.), A source book of Gestalt psychology (pp. 217–227). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul (Original work published 1918).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lamal, P. A. (1993). Friends? Allies? A review of Newman’s the reluctant alliance: Behaviorism and humanism. Behavior analyst, 16, 331–334. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf03392640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lazareva, O. F. (2012). Relational learning in a context of transposition: a review. Journal of the experimental analysis of behavior, 97, 231–248. https://doi.org/10.1901%2Fjeab.2012.97-231.

  • Leigland, S. (1999). Pragmatism, science, and society: a review of Rorty’s objectivity, relativism, and truth: Philosophical papers, Vol. 1. Journal of the experimental analysis of behavior, 71, 483–500.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Leigland, S. (2016). Comments on burgos’ (2015) antidualism and antimentalism in radical behaviorism. Behavior & philosophy, 44, 18–24 Retrieved from http://www.behavior.org/resource.php?id=994.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1988). What experience teaches. In J. Copley-Coltheart (Ed.), proceedings of the russellian society (pp. 29–35). Sydney: University of Sydney.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, C. F., & Horne, P. J. (1985). On the generality of behavioural principles: human choice and the matching law. In C. F. Lowe, M. Richelle, D. E. Blackman, & C. M. Bradshaw (Eds.), Behaviour analysis and contemporary psychology (pp. 97–115). London: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr, J. (1996). A mingled yarn. Behavior analyst, 19, 19–33. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03392736.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Marr, J. (2016). The escape from metaphysics: commentary on Burgos (2015). Behavior & philosophy, 44, 25–31 Retrieved from http://www.behavior.org/resource.php?id=995.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, G. (1962). On the ontological status of theoretical entities. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Scientific explanation, space, and time. minnesota Studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 3; pp. 3–15). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

  • McSweeney, F. K., Roll, J. M., & Weatherly, J. N. (1994). Within-session changes in responding during several simple schedules. Journal of the experimental analysis of behavior, 62, 109–132. https://doi.org/10.1901/jeab.1994.62-109.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • McSweeney, F. K., & Murphy, E. S. (2017). Understanding operant behavior: Still experimental analysis of the three-term contingency. Behavior analyst, 40(1), 39–47. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40614-017-0088-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J., & Dallery, J. (1999). Falsification of matching theory: changes in the asymptote of Herrnstein’s hyperbola as a function of water deprivation. Journal of the experimental analysis of behavior, 72, 251–268. https://doi.org/10.1901/jeab.1999.72-251.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Mazur, J. E. (2016). Learning and behavior (7th ed.). New York, NY: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J. (1975). On the principle of operationism in the science of behavior. Behavior, 3, 120–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J. (1999). The basic principles of behaviorism. In B. A. Thyer (Ed.), The philosophical legacy of behaviorism (pp. 41–68). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J. (2001). On psychological terms that appeal to the mental. Behavior & philosophy, 29, 167–186 Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/27759426.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J. (2003). Behavior analysis, mentalism, and the path to social justice. Behavior analyst, 26, 181–193. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03392075.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J. (2007). Comments on “Intentional behaviorism” by G. R. Foxall. Behavior & philosophy, 35, 113–130 Retrieved from http://www.behavior.org/resource.php?id=203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J. (2008). Conceptual foundations of radical behaviorism. Cornwall-on-Hudson, NY: Sloan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J. (2010). What do mental terms mean? The psychological record, 60, 699–714.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J. (2011). A review of baum’s review of conceptual foundations of radical behaviorism. Journal of the experimental analysis of behavior, 95, 127–140.

    Article  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J. (2015). From a behavioral point of view: a psychological primer. Cornwall-on-Hudson, NY: Sloan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moxley, R. A. (2001). Sources for skinner’s pragmatic selectionism in 1945. Behavior analyst, 24, 201–212. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03392031.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Moxley, R. A. (2002). Some more similarities between peirce and skinner. Behavior analyst, 25, 201–214. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03392058.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Nevin, J. A., Craig, A. R., Cunningham, P. J., Podlesnik, C. A., Shahan, T. A., & Sweeney, M. M. (2017). Quantitative models of persistence and relapse from the perspective of behavioral momentum theory: fits and misfits. Behavioural processes, 141(1), 92–99. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.beproc.2017.04.016.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • O’Donohue, W., & Kitchener, R. (Eds.). (1999). Handbook of behaviorism. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paivio, A. (1990). Mental representations: a dual coding approach. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pearce, J. M. (1987). A model for stimulus generalization in pavlovian conditioning. Psychological review, 94, 61–73. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.94.1.61.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1958). On the logic of drawing history from ancient documents, especially from testimonies. In A. W. Burks (Ed.), The collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vol. VII (pp. 89–164). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Originally published 1901).

  • Pockett, S., Banks, W. P., & Gallagher, S. (2006). Introduction. In S. Pockett, W. P. Banks, & S. Gallagher (Eds.), Does consciousness cause behavior? (pp. 1–6). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Poldrack, R. A., Halchenko, Y. O., & Hanson, S. J. (2009). Decoding the large-scale structure of brain function by classifying mental states across individuals. Psychological science, 20(11), 1364–1372. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9280.2009.02460.x.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Polger, T. W. (2004). Natural minds. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1963). Conjectures and refutations. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1974). Replies to my critics. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Karl Popper, book II (pp. 961–1197). La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1962). What theories are not. In E. Nagel, P. Suppes, & A. Tarski (Eds.), Logic, methodology and philosophy of science (pp. 240–251). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1974). The roots of reference: the Paul Carus Lectures. La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachlin, H. (2014). The escape of the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rachlin, H. (2017). In defense of teleological behaviorism. Journal of theoretical & philosophical psychology, 37, 65–76. https://doi.org/10.1037/teo0000060.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescorla, R. A. (1976). Stimulus generalization: some predictions from a model of pavlovian conditioning. Journal of experimental psychology: Animal behavior processes, 2, 88–96. https://doi.org/10.1037/0097-7403.2.1.88.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Rescorla, R. A., & Wagner, A. R. (1972). A theory of Pavlovian conditioning: variations in the effectiveness of reinforcement and nonreinforcement. In A. H. Black & W. F. Prokasky (Eds.), Classical conditioning (Vol. 2, pp. 64–99). New York, NY: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rockwell, W. T. (2005). Neither brain, nor ghost: a non-dualist alternative to the mind-brain identity theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Chicago: The university of chicago press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, M. (1949). Causality in everyday life and recent science. In H. Feigl, & W. Sellars (Eds.), Readings in philosophical analysis (pp. 515–533). New York, NY: Appleton-Century-Crofts. (Originally published 1932).

  • Schnaitter, R. (1978). Private causes. Behavior, 6(1), 1–12 Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/27758902.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1992). The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shahan, T. A. (2017). Beyond reinforcement and response strength. Behavior analyst, 40(1), 1–15. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40614-017-0092-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shettleworth, S. J., & Juergensen, M. R. (1980). Reinforcement and the organization of behavior in golden hamsters: Brain stimulation reinforcement for seven action patterns. Journal of experimental psychology: Animal behavior processes, 6, 352–375.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1950). Are theories of learning necessary? Psychological review, 57, 193–2016. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0054367.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science and human behavior. New York, NY: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1963). Behaviorism at fifty. Science, 140, 951–958. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.140.3570.951.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1969). Contingencies of reinforcement: a theoretical analysis. New York, NY: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1972). Beyond freedom and dignity. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1974). About behaviorism. New York, NY: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1977). Why I am not a cognitive psychologist. Behavior, 5, 1–10 Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/27758892.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1984). Methods and theories in the experimental analysis of behavior. Behavioral & brain sciences, 7, 511–523. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00026996.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1987). Whatever happened to psychology as the science of behavior? American psychologist, 42, 780–786. https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.42.8.780.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1983). Mentalism and behaviorism in comparative psychology. In D. W. Rajecki (Ed.), Comparing behavior: studying man studying animals (pp. 113–142). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperry, R. W. (1980). Commentary: mind-brain interaction: mentalism, yes; dualism, no. Neuroscience, 5, 195–206. https://doi.org/10.1016/0306-4522(80)90098-6.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Staddon, J. (2001). The new behaviorism: mind, mechanism, and society. Philadelphia, PA: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. P. (1996). Deconstructing the mind. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppe, F. (1977). The search for a philosophic understanding of scientific theories. In F. Suppe (Ed.), The structure of scientific theories (2nd ed., pp. 3–233). Chicago, IL: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taubes, G. (2008). Good calories, bad calories: fats, carbs, and the controversial science of diet and health. New York: Anchor Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Terrace, H. S. (1984). A behavioral theory of mind? Behavioral & brain sciences, 7, 569–571. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00027370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todd, J. T., & Morris, E. K. (1983). Misconception and miseducation: presentations of radical behaviorism in psychology textbooks. Behavior analyst, 6, 153–160. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03392394.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Uttal, W. R. (2000). The war between mentalism and behaviorism: on the accessibility of mental processes. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uttal, W. R. (2004). Dualism: the original sin of cognitivism. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Uttal, W. R. (2011). Mind and brain: a critical appraisal of cognitive neuroscience. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Valentine, E. R. (1992). Conceptual issues in psychology (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, J. S. (2013). Behavior analysis for effective teaching (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. P. (1979). Symmetries and reflections. Woodbridge, CT: Ox Bow Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. G. E. M. Anscombe & R. Rhees (Eds.), G.E.M. Anscombe (trans.). Oxford, England: Blackwell.

  • Watson, J. B. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. Psychological review, 20, 158–177. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0074428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wundt, W. (1897). Outlines of psychology (C. H. Judd, Trans.). London: Williams & Norgate.

  • Zentall, T. R. (Ed.). (2013). Animal cognition: A tribute to Donald A. Riley. New York: Psychology Press.

  • Zuriff, G. (1979). Ten inner causes. Behavior, 7(1), 1–8 Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/27758925.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zuriff, G. E. (1980). Radical behaviorist epistemology. Psychological bulletin, 87(2), 337–350. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-2909.87.2.337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zuriff, G. (1985). Behaviorism: a conceptual reconstruction. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank two anonymous reviewers and Thomas Critchfield for valuable commentaries to a previous draft.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to José E. Burgos.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Ethical Approval

No animals were used or participated in this article, excepting the authors, who did not mistreat one another; nor does it cite any studies with animals performed by any of the authors.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Burgos, J.E., Killeen, P.R. Suing for Peace in the War Against Mentalism. Perspect Behav Sci 42, 241–266 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40614-018-0169-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40614-018-0169-2

Keywords

Navigation