Skip to main content
Log in

Embryo experimentation: is there a case for moving beyond the ‘14-day rule’

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Monash Bioethics Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent scientific advances have indicated that it may be technically feasible to sustain human embryos in vitro beyond 14 days. Research beyond this stage is currently restricted by a guideline known as the 14-day rule. Since the advances in embryo culturing there have been calls to extend the current limit. Much of the current debate concerning an extension has regarded the 14-day rule as a political compromise and has, therefore, focused on policy concerns rather than assessing the philosophical foundations of the limit. While there are relevant political considerations, I maintain that the success of extension arguments will ultimately depend on the strength of the justifications supporting the current 14-day limit. I argue that the strongest and most prevalent justifications for the 14-day rule—an appeal to individuation and neural development—do not provide adequate support for the limit of 14 days. I instead suggest that an alternative justification based on sentience would constitute a more defensible basis for embryo protection and that a consideration of such grounds appears to support an amendment to the current limit, rather than the retention of it. While these conclusions do not establish conclusively that the current limit should be extended; they do suggest that an extension may be warranted and permissible. As such, this paper offers grounds on which a reassessment of the 14-day rule may be justified.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As to what specific standards are relevant will depend on the type of restriction being revised (e.g. legislation, institutional guidelines, professional standards). However, a common theme that has emerged in the debate is that any revision ought to involve a slow, deliberative and inclusive dialogue between the public, experts, and policy makers (Hyun 2016; Warnock 2017; Sample 2016; Appleby and Bredenoord 2018; Cavaliere 2017).

  2. See for example Devolder and Savulescu’s (2006) views on the moral imperative to conduct beneficial research.

  3. The earliest mention of a 14-day limit on embryo research is found in a 1979 U.S. report. Although, due to various political reasons the recommendation was never given the opportunity to be properly reviewed (Ethics Advisory Board, Department of Health, Education, and Welfare 1979; Hyun 2016).

  4. The primitive streak is a thickened linear band on the epiblast that is formed by cell growth and migration. This signals the beginning of gastrulation, a process in which the body plan of the embryo is formed (Moore et al. 2015).

  5. For a discussion on the relevance of implantation see: Fischbach and Fischbach (2004), Harris (2007), Pera (2017), or Singer and Dawson (1990).

  6. In the introduction to a 1985 publication of the Warnock Report, Mary Warnock has offered a contradicting position, stating that: “The majority of the Committee was not moved by the argument that these cells could, if certain conditions were satisfied, become human beings. They did not rely, that is to say, as the minority did, on “potentiality”, but on consideration of what the embryo was at a particular time immediately after fertilisation.” (Warnock 1985, p. xv). Michael Lockwood has proposed two possible ways in which the apparent contradiction may be resolved. The first is that the mention of the potential of the embryo to become a human being in the Warnock Report is an acknowledgment and dismissal of the common argument for protection. The second is that in the 1985 introduction, Mary Warnock is suggesting that the majority of the committee only rejected the significance of potentiality immediately after fertilisation, and not at some later point. Lockwood does not consider either to be plausible and suggests that the mention of potential may be somewhat unintended (Lockwood 1988, p. 211).

  7. Such reasons included practical and theoretical challenges associated with settling moral questions, and also philosophical views of Mary Warnock. Specifically, her opinions regarding moral sentimentalism, intuitionalism and moral authority, see for example (Wilson 2014, pp. 140–186).

  8. There are other non-individuation arguments that appeal to the lack of distinction between embryoblast and trophoblast, and to the totipotency of blastomeres. However, these arguments face similar problems. See for example: Oderberg (2008).

  9. Although there has been no conclusive evidence regarding the exact timing and process that results in conjoined twins—largely because of the inability to observe the embryo during the ‘black box’ period—according to the most widely held theory (fissure theory) conjoined twins are believed to form between day 13 to 17 of gestation (see for example: Hall 2003; Weber and Sebire 2010; McNamara et al. 2016). Until it is possible to observe embryo development beyond 14-days, the precise point at which twinning (of any kind) is no longer possible may indeed be contested.

  10. Although it is not made clear in the Warnock Report, I take it that “functional activity” refers to the development of active neural circuits. This would require, at a minimum, the differentiation of electrophysiologically active neurons and synapse formation. See: Johnson et al. (2007) and Zhang and Poo (2001).

  11. Because it is specifically acknowledged in the Warnock Report as the grounds for the protection of the embryo.

  12. For example: a prince is a potential king yet does not have the rights of a king until he becomes an actual king (Stier and Schoene-Seifert 2013, p. 20).

  13. See for example: French et al. (2008)

  14. While I do not necessarily endorse the reductio objection, the possibility for germ cells and somatic cells to develop into a human being (and possibly a human person) presents a problem for potentiality arguments for the protection of the embryo. To avoid such a problem, it has been argued that there is a morally relevant difference in potential between a human embryo and human somatic cells or germ cells (e.g. by making a distinction between proximate and remote, or active and passive potential) (Condic and Condic 2018). However, these proposals still face a number of challenges. See for example: Stier and Schoene-Seifert (2013).

  15. I use the term ‘procreative embryo’ to refer to in vitro and in vivo embryos that are part of a procreative project. Namely, those that are intended for gestation and eventual birth.

  16. Sentience as a criterion of moral considerability is generally defined as the capacity to feel pleasure or pain (Kuhse and Singer 1990; Warren 1997). However, there is some ambiguity concerning the concept, particularly regarding the aspect of ‘feeling’. Interpretations of sentience range from the rudimentary capacity to respond to external stimuli, to self-conscious awareness (van Bogaert 2004; Bortolotti and Harris 2005). My use of ‘sentience’ will refer to ‘pain sensation’, a capacity that sits somewhere between these two extremes. Specifically, I am referring to a capacity for the (conscious) sensation of pain that is more complex than a simple reflex response yet does not involve any higher-level self-conscious pain awareness. I suggest that this form of ‘minimal’ sentience should be considered as sufficient and not necessary to prohibit research. That is, there may be other sufficient criteria that would prohibit research even in the absence of pain sensation (e.g. future interests of the embryo). Furthermore, I am suggesting that this conception of sentience may serve only as a criterion for moral considerability and not full moral status.

  17. A limit based on sentience could also be formulated as a temporal limit, thereby satisfying what many consider to be a particularly useful characteristic of the 14-day rule. Namely, that it relies on an easily tracked period of time (i.e. number of days) (Chan 2018).

  18. This is my own term, used to designate the types of properties or features relevant for my proposed criterion. A version of this proposal has also been presented as a possible strategy to address the difficulties current regulations face when dealing with Synthetic Human Entities with Embryo-like Features (SHEEFs) (see: Aach et al. 2017).

References

  • Aach, J., J. Lunshof, E. Iyer, and G. Church. 2017. Addressing the Ethical Issues Raised by Synthetic Human Entities with Embryo-like Features. Elife 6: e20674.

    Google Scholar 

  • Appleby, J.B., and A.L. Bredenoord. 2018. Should the 14-day rule for embryo research become the 28-day rule? EMBO Molecular Medicine 10 (9): e9437.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bortolotti, L., and J. Harris. 2005. Stem cell research, personhood and sentience. Reproductive Biomedicine Online 10: 68–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckle, S. 1990. Arguing from Potential. In Embryo Experimentation, ed. P. Singer, H. Kuhse, S. Buckle, and K. Dawson, 90–108. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavaliere, G. 2017. A 14-day Limit for Bioethics: The Debate Over Human Embryo Research. BMC Medical Ethics 18 (1): 38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chan, S. 2017. How to Rethink the 14-day rule. Hastings Center Report 47 (3): 5–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chan, S. 2018. How and Why to Replace the 14-Day Rule. Current Stem Cell Reports 4 (3): 228–234.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, C., and Chisholm, A. 2017. Human development between 14 and 28 days. In Human Embryo Culture, 48–49. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics.

  • Condic, S.B., and M.L. Condic. 2018. Human Embryos, Human Beings: A Scientific and Philosophical Approach. Washington, D.C.: CUA Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Connor, S. 2016. Inside the ‘Black Box’ of Human Development. Retrieved from https://www.theguardian.com/science/2016/jun/05/human-development-ivf-embryos-14-day-legal-limit-extend-inside-black-box.

  • Dawson, K. 1990. Segmentation and Moral Status: A Scientific Perspective. In Embryo Experimentation, ed. P. Singer, H. Kuhse, S. Buckle, K. Dawson, and P. Kasimba, 53–64. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deglincerti, A., G.F. Croft, L.N. Pietila, M. Zernicka-Goetz, E.D. Siggia, and A.H. Brivanlou. 2016. Self-organization of the In Vitro Attached Human Embryo. Nature 533 (7602): 251–254.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia, D. 2006. Moral Status, Human Identity, and Early Embryos: A Critique of the President's Approach. The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 34 (1): 49–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Department of Health and Social Security. 1984. Report of the Committee of Inquiry into Human Fertilisation and Embryology. London: Her Majesty’s Stationary Office.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derbyshire, S. 2006. Can Fetuses Feel Pain? BMJ 332 (7546): 909–912.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devolder, K., and J. Harris. 2007. The Ambiguity of the Embryo: Ethical Inconsistency in the Human Embryonic Stem Cell Debate. Metaphilosophy 38 (2–3): 153–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devolder, K., and J. Savulescu. 2006. The moral imperative to conduct embryonic stem cell and cloning research. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 15 (01): 7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elves, C., and S. McGuinness. 2017. Background paper: The Statutory Time Limit for Maintaining Human Embryos in Culture. Human Embryo Culture, 13–35. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ethics Advisory Board, Department of Health, Education, and Welfare. 1979. HEW Support of Research Involving Human In Vitro Fertilization and Embryo Transfer. US Government Printing Office.

  • Fischbach, G., and R. Fischbach. 2004. Stem Cells: Science, Policy, and Ethics. Journal of Clinical Investigation 114 (10): 1364–1370.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flaman, P. 1991. When did I begin? Another critical response to Norman Ford. The Linacre Quarterly 58 (4): 39–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ford, N. 1988. When Did I Begin? Conception of the Human Individual in History, Philosophy and Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, A.J., C.A. Adams, L.S. Anderson, J.R. Kitchen, M.R. Hughes, and S.H. Wood. 2008. Development of Human Cloned Blastocysts Following Somatic Cell Nuclear Transfer with Adult Fibroblasts. Stem Cells 26: 485–493.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guenin, L. 2006. The Nonindividuation Argument Against Zygotic Personhood. Philosophy 81 (3): 463–504.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, J. 2003. Twinning. The Lancet 362 (9385): 735–743.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. 1990. Embryos and Hedgehogs: On the Moral Status of the Embryo. In Experiments on Embryos, ed. A. Dyson and J. Harris, 52–65. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. 2007. Enhancing Evolution: The Ethical Case for Making Better People. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. (2016). It’s Time to Extend the 14-day Limit for Embryo Research. Retrieved from https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2016/may/06/extend-14-day-limit-embryo-research

  • Hurlbut, J.B., I. Hyun, A.D. Levine, R. Lovell-Badge, J.E. Lunshof, K.R. Matthews, et al. 2017. Revisiting the Warnock rule. Nature Biotechnology 35 (11): 1029.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyun, I. 2013. The Embryo Potentiality Argument Revisited: “Once More unto the Breach, Dear Friends”. The American Journal of Bioethics 13 (1): 28–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyun, I. 2016. The 14-Day Rule: Historical and Ethical Underpinnings. Paper presented at the The Ethics of Early Embryo Research & the Future of the 14-Day Rule, The Petrie-Flom Center for Health Law Policy, Biotechnology, and Bioethics at Harvard Law School.

  • Hyun, I., A. Wilkerson, and J. Johnston. 2016. Embryology Policy: Revisit the 14-day Rule. Nature 533 (7602): 169–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M.A., J.P. Weick, R.A. Pearce, and S.C. Zhang. 2007. Functional Neural Development from Human Embryonic Stem Cells: Accelerated Synaptic Activity via Astrocyte Coculture. Journal of Neuroscience 27 (12): 3069–3077.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kingma, E. 2017. Moral Status and the Properties of the Embryo. Human Embryo Culture, 73–77. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhse, H., and P. Singer. 1990. Individuals, Humans and Persons: The Issue of Moral Status. In Embryo Experimentation, ed. P. Singer, H. Kuhse, S. Buckle, K. Dawson, and P. Kasimba, 65–75. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee, S.J., H.J.P. Ralston, E.A. Drey, J.C. Partridge, and M.A. Rosen. 2005. Fetal pain: A Systematic Multidisciplinary Review of the Evidence. JAMA 294 (8): 947–954.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lockwood, M. 1988. Warnock Versus Powell (and Harradine): When Does Potentiality Count? Bioethics 2 (3): 187–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowery, C.L., M.P. Hardman, N. Manning, B. Clancy, R.W. Hall, and K.J.S. Anand. 2007. Neurodevelopmental Changes of Fetal Pain. Seminars in Perinatology 31 (5): 275–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGee, A. 2014. The Potentiality of the Embryo and the Somatic Cell. Metaphilosophy 45 (4–5): 689–706.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKie, R. 2016. A leap forward or a step too far? The new debate over embryo research. The Guardian. Retrieved from https://www.theguardian.com/science/2016/dec/04/embryo-research--leap-forward-step-too-far.

  • McNamara, H.C., S.C. Kane, J.M. Craig, R.V. Short, and M.P. Umstad. 2016. A review of the mechanisms and evidence for typical and atypical twinning. American Journal of Obstetrics and Gynecology 214 (2): 172–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, K., T.V.N. Persaud, and M.G. Torchia. 2015. The Developing Human: Clinically Oriented Embryology, 10th ed. Saint Louis: Elsevier Health Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munthe, C. 2001. Divisibility and the Moral Status of Embryos. Bioethics 15 (5–6): 382–397.

    Google Scholar 

  • Napier, S. 2010. Vulnerable Embryos: A Critical Analysis of Twinning, Rescue, and Natural-loss Arguments. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 84 (4): 781–810.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D.S. 1997. Modal Properties, Moral Status, and Identity. Philosophy & Public Affairs 26 (3): 259–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D.S. 2008. The Metaphysical Status of the Embryo: Some Arguments Revisited. Journal of Applied Philosophy 25 (4): 263–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pera, M. 2017. Human embryo research and the 14-day rule. Development 144 (11): 1923–1925.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pera, M.F., G. de Wert, W. Dondorp, R. Lovell-Badge, C.L. Mummery, M. Munsie, and P.P. Tam. 2015. What if Stem Cells Turn into Embryos in a Dish? Nature Methods 12 (10): 917–919.

    Google Scholar 

  • Powell, A. 2016. Updating embryo research guidelines. Harvard Gazette. Retrieved from https://news.harvard.edu/gazette/story/2016/11/updating-embryo-research-guidelines/.

  • Sagan, A., and P. Singer. 2007. The Moral Status of Stem Cells. Metaphilosophy 38 (2–3): 264–284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sample, I. (Presenter). 2016. The ethics of growing human embryos in the lab. [Audio Podcast]. In I. Chambers (Producer), The Guardian's Science Weekly. Retrieved from https://www.theguardian.com/science/audio/2016/may/27/the-ethics-of-growing-human-embryos-in-the-lab-podcast.

  • Shahbazi, M.N., A. Jedrusik, S. Vuoristo, G. Recher, A. Hupalowska, V. Bolton, et al. 2016. Self-organization of the Human Embryo in the Absence of Maternal Tissues. Nature Cell Biology 18 (6): 700–708.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P., and K. Dawson. 1990. IVF Technology and the Argument from Potential. In Embryo Experimentation, ed. P. Singer, H. Kuhse, S. Buckle, K. Dawson, and P. Kasimba, 76–89. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P., H. Kuhse, S. Buckle, K. Dawson, and P. Kasimba (eds.). 1990. Embryo Experimentation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stier, M., and B. Schoene-Seifert. 2013. The Argument from Potentiality in the Embryo Protection Debate: Finally “Depotentialized”? The American Journal of Bioethics 13 (1): 19–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Surani, A. 2017. How might scientific opportunities change if the limit were redrawn? Human Embryo Culture, 56–58. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tonti-Filippini, N. 1989. A critical note. The Linacre Quarterly 56 (3): 36–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Bogaert, L. 2004. Sentience and moral standing. South African Journal of Philosophy 23 (3): 292–301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warnock, M. 1985. A question of life. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warnock, M. 2007. The Ethical Regulation of Science. Nature 450 (7170): 615.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warnock, M. 2017. Should the 14-day limit on human embryo research be extended?. Bionews. Retrieved from http://www.bionews.org.uk/page_755759.asp

  • Warren, M. 1997. Moral status: Obligations to persons and other living things. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. A., and Sebire, N. J. 2010. Genetics and developmental pathology of twinning. In Seminars in Fetal and Neonatal Medicine Vol. 15, No. 6, pp. 313–318. Philadelphia: WB Saunders.

  • Williams, K., and M.H. Johnson. 2020. Adapting the 14-day rule for embryo research to encompass evolving technologies. Reproductive Biomedicine & Society Online 10: 1–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D. 2014. The making of British bioethics. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zernicka-Goetz, M. 2017. A need to expand our knowledge of early development. In Human Embryo Culture, 50–55. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics.

  • Zhang, L., and M. Poo. 2001. Electrical Activity and Development of Neural Circuits. Nature Neuroscience 4 (11s): 1207–1214.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Dr. Mianna Lotz for her supportive and helpful discussions and feedback on previous drafts.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Grant Castelyn.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Castelyn, G. Embryo experimentation: is there a case for moving beyond the ‘14-day rule’. Monash Bioeth. Rev. 38, 181–196 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40592-020-00117-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40592-020-00117-x

Keywords

Navigation