Skip to main content
Log in

Beyond Generalized Darwinism. II. More Things in Heaven and Earth

  • Thematic Issue Article: How Evolutionary is Evolutionary Economics?
  • Published:
Biological Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This is the second of two articles in which I reflect on “generalized Darwinism” as currently discussed in evolutionary economics. In the companion article (Callebaut, Biol Theory 6. doi:10.1007/s13752-013-0086-2, 2011, this issue) I approached evolutionary economics from the naturalistic perspectives of evolutionary epistemology and the philosophy of biology, contrasted evolutionary economists’ cautious generalizations of Darwinism with “imperialistic” proposals to unify the behavioral sciences, and discussed the continued resistance to biological ideas in the social sciences. Here I assess Generalized Darwinism as propounded by Geoffrey Hodgson, Thorbjørn Knudsen, and others, concentrating on the roles of theory and model building in science (and the roles of analogy and metaphor therein), generative replication, and the relation between selection and self-organization. I then point to advances in current biology that promise to be more fruitful as sources of inspiration for evolutionary economics than the project to generalize Darwinism in its current, “hardened Modern Synthesis” form; and I draw some conclusions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In his Nobel Prize acceptance speech, Konrad Lorenz (1974) recalled that as a student of the comparative anatomist and embryologist Ferdinand Hochstetter he had the benefit of a very thorough instruction in the methodological procedure of distinguishing similarities caused by common descent from those due to parallel adaptation. Only much later in life he realized that in human cultural evolution, the interaction between homologies and analogies “was very much the same as in the phylogeny of species and that it posed very much the same problems” (p. 231). Or, to take another example: Campbell (1997, p. 6) relates “the many independent discoveries” of the notion, usually associated with Lorenz, that the a priori categories of perception and intuition result from biological evolution: Darwin (in his notebooks), Spencer, James, Vaihinger, von Bertalanffy, “and a hundred others.”

  2. Contrary to Simon’s older behavioral theory of organizations, behavioral economics à la Kahneman lacks an evolutionary perspective. Witt (2011, this issue) points out that this is rather surprising “given that important parts of the behavioral repertoire of animals and presumably also of humans are innate, i.e., develop as an expression of their genes.” I will argue below that such a linear view of development is outdated.

  3. Epigenetic phenomena at the level of the structure and function of the gene such as methylation and imprinting of gene sequences, sometimes referred to as the “phenotype” of the gene, likewise blur the distinction between genotype and phenotype (Hallgrímsson and Hall 2011, p. 1).

  4. Self-reproducing systems have been thought possible only if they can store information about themselves, which would require them to simplify their “experiences” by means of a language such as the genetic code that maintains the system against entropy. “At first, replication occurs in a relatively simple fashion, and then becomes more complicated as the gap between genotype and phenotype emerges. The function of the genotype is supposed to be one of storing information for the phenotype so that the negentropic commitment (in the form of complexity) represented by the phenotype can be somewhat minimized by allowing lower negentropic factors (chemical bonding, for example) to be at the service of replication. As a result of the economy brought about by self-simplification of the phenotype in the genotype, higher phenotypic levels of complexity … then become possible” (Esposito 1975, p. 136; my italics). Maybe the idea of an energetic/informational self-simplification of the phenotype in the genotype could be extended fruitfully to discussions of levels and their interrelations, while sidestepping the pitfalls of the replicator/interactor formalism. Notice that this idea allows for recursion (“genotypes within genotypes”); cf. also note 3.

  5. Despite a century-old tradition that had “yielded tantalizing insights into the evolution of organismal form” (Pigliucci and Müller 2010, p. 8), developmental biology (formerly embryology) was not incorporated in the Modern Synthesis, and the importance of proximate as opposed to ultimate causation continues to be downplayed by evolutionists and “their” philosophers (as discussed in Callebaut et al. 2007; Callebaut 2009a); but see Müller (2005); Gilbert and Epel (2009); Laland et al. (2011).

  6. The existence of many departments of “ecology and evolutionary biology” notwithstanding, ecology, which missed out on the Modern Synthesis, has “kept developing with little to add to, or import from, evolutionary biology” (Pigliucci and Müller 2010, p. 8). Many ideas in ecology have more in common with economics than with anything in contemporary biology (Callebaut 2010, p. 468).

  7. “In view of the strong anti-theoretical stance of most of biology, it is remarkable that, in the absence of much evidence, the concept of natural selection of units other than the individual is so widely accepted” (Lewontin 1970, p. 2).

  8. In a way, facts are a lot like cows: if you stare them in the face hard enough, they generally run away (Dorothy Sayers, Clouds of Witness, 1926)!

  9. In a letter to Henry Fawcett of 18 September 1861 (quoted in Gould 1992), Darwin already wrote: “About thirty years ago there was much talk that geologists ought only to observe and not theorize; and I well remember someone saying that at this rate a man might as well go into a gravel-pit and count the pebbles and describe the colours. How odd it is that any-one should not see that all observation must be for or against some view if it is to be of any service!”

  10. Numerous models in economics (and biology), including game theoretical ones, explore “the logical or empirical implications of sets of constraints and interactions without application to carefully curated data sets” (Krakauer et al. 2011, p. 271).

  11. On the other hand, Hodgson and Knudsen’s “odd focus on increasing complexity” (Gers 2012, p. 599) already leaves its mark at this highest level.

  12. On Vromen’s (2007, p. 19) hypothetical interpretation, which I endorse on the basis of my reading of subsequent publications by Hodgson and Knudsen (e.g., 2011, this issue), GD is tendentially being sized down from a “selection-type theory” to “something like population thinking.” If you oppose this kind of hypothetical reasoning, consider the “epicycle upon epicycle” argument instead.

  13. If the basic explanatory form in science is—revisable—theory rather than law, a view that most evolutionary economists adhere to, then retroduction not induction should be the main form of scientific validation (McMullin 1983, p. 14). What Nelson (2011, this issue) has in mind is that theorizing should proceed from paying close attention to the empirical phenomena, and then coming to a plausible explanation that is consistent with other things known empirically.

  14. The “evolutionary contingency thesis” states that all generalizations about the living world are either of a mathematical, physical, or chemical nature, or distinctively biological, in which case they describe contingent outcomes of evolution (Beatty 1995, pp. 46–47).

  15. François Jacob, who coined the metaphor of bricolage, argued for a grounding of biology in economics or engineering (Krakauer et al. 2011, p. 270).

  16. Even if one believes that “for inheritance to exist, there has to be some way of reliably producing similarity (along some dimension) between relatives across generations,” which I reject as far as the sheer “logic” of evolution à la Lewontin is concerned, “this mechanism need not involve an underlying population of entities (like genes) that are copied in the wholesale and direct sense associated with the (Dawkins-Hull) concept of a replicator” (Godfrey-Smith 2001, p. 538). To avoid misunderstanding, let me add that I personally don’t think Ghiselin and Hull have had the last word on similarity (Callebaut 2010, p. 471).

  17. Thus Wimsatt (2006) adds two more requirements to Lewontin’s three: (4) “developmental trajectories show sequential dependencies” (generativity), and (5) “systemic elements differ in downstream consequences and magnitude of effect” (differential generative entrenchment). These he takes to provide “a minimal but absolutely general account of development” that is satisfied by all nontrivial evolutionary systems.

  18. In a similar vein, McCarthy (2004, p. 139) adds “struggle” to variation, selection, and retention as a process underpinning the evolution of organizations. For Ross (2006, p. 31), “in the absence of competition for resources, there would be no selection, and all biological change would be random”—a claim that may have to be reconsidered in the light of EvoDevo (McGhee 2011) and niche construction theory.

  19. A non-Malthusian stance similar to Lewontin’s is sketched in Simon (1983): in principle, niche construction allows populations to evolve indefinitely while avoiding encounters “red in tooth and claw” (Callebaut 2007). To avoid any possible misunderstanding: I am considering only the “logic” of evolution here (cf. Weiss et al. 2011).

  20. Hodgson and Knudsen (2010, Section 5.5.) have had little to say about what fitness amounts to in the cultural domain beyond “the propensity of a social replicator (such as a habit or routine) with a particular feature to produce copies and increase the frequency of similar replicators in a population.”

    Self-reflecting on his theory of group-level cultural adaptations, Campbell (1997, p. 23) wrote: “we must posit that the individually adaptive products are so valuable that a general tendency toward blind comformity has a net individual inclusive fitness advantage.” He admitted that this is “one of the most vulnerable parts” of his theory. Given the persistent difficulties with defining fitness in both biological and cultural contexts (Lennox 2008; McCarthy 2004; Stearns 1976; see also Peacock 2011), it may be worthwhile thinking about a formalization of GD that can dispense with this notion (David Hull, personal communication, 1 December 2000) of Victorian origin (Callebaut 2010, p. 469).

  21. "We are just starting to appreciate the full range of [prokaryotic organisms’] mechanisms for evolutionary change.… [G]iven the fascinating range of mechanisms of recombination in prokaryotes, processes that regulate evolutionary change in this wide array of organisms remain a fertile field of inquiry. In fact, we need to move very quickly to keep up with the speed with which microorganisms are changing. Whether we like it or not, these smallest of organisms have already inherited the earth" (Rita Colwell, quoted in Kane 2001, p. 468).

  22. (1) NS and SO are unrelated; (2) SO is auxiliary to NS; (3) SO constrains NS, which drives evolution; (4) NS constrains SO, which drives evolution; (5) NS instantiates SO; (6) NS generates SO; (7) NS and SO are aspects of a single process.

  23. I must ignore here the challenges for “language” views of theory posed by the increasing adoption of “non-statement views” since the 1970s; see Suppe (1977) for a general overview, and Hamminga (1983) and Hands (1985) for applications to economics.

  24. Only recently has philosophy of science begun to recover from the objectivist illusions of the logical positivists, as indicated in the shift away from “explanation” toward an emphasis on “understanding” (de Regt et al. 2009).

  25. I discuss the philosophical background to Griesemer’s perspectivism at some length in Callebaut (2012).

  26. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Harvard_Computers.

  27. Sterelny (2006) argues that human lifeways depend on “cognitive capital” that has been built over many generations, producing an adaptive fit between human agents and their environments that is the result of “hidden-hand,” evolutionary mechanisms.

  28. Emergence refers to phenomena outside the scope of variation, in particular to the modes of origination, innovation and novelty in phenotypic evolution (Müller 2007). On Müller’s view, a “theory of emergence” complements the theory of adaptation through its account for the appearance of phenotypic novelties in evolution.

  29. The “evolutionary developmental economics” proposed by Pelikan (2011) as an alternative to HKGD draws on a version of EvoDevo that is “less concerned with replication of genes than with genomic instructing of development of organisms.” The envisaged generalization of development “as instructed self-organizing with inputs from environments, and evolution as experimental search for instructions making the development successful” seems to me a first step in the right direction. Pelikan has moved up one step on the ladder of life, from the single gene to the genome; may more steps follow soon!

  30. Hull et al. (2001), reflecting on their comparison of selection processes in evolutionary biology, immunology, and operant behavior, also concluded that the organism plays a crucial role in all three cases.

  31. “More things in Heaven and Earth,” the subtitle of this article, is a tribute to Gould (2001b).

References

  • Aldrich HE, Hodgson GM, Hull DL, Knudsen T, Mokyr J, Vanberg VJ (2008) In defence of generalized Darwinism. J Evol Econ 18:577–596

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bailer-Jones (2002) Models, metaphors, and analogies. In: Machamer PK, Silberstein M (eds) The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of science. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 108–127

  • Batten D, Salthe S, Boschetti F (2008) Visions of evolution: self-organization proposes what natural selection disposes. Biol Theory 3:17–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beatty J (1995) The evolutionary contingency thesis. In: Wolters G, Lennox JG (eds) Concepts, theories, and rationality in the biological sciences. Universitätsverlag Konstanz/University of Pittsburgh Press, Konstanz/Pittsburgh, pp 45–81

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolhuis JJ, Brown GR, Richardson RC, Laland KN (2011) Darwin in mind: new opportunities for evolutionary psychology. PLoS 9(7):e1001109

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buenstorf G (2006) How useful is generalized Darwinism as a framework to study competition and industrial evolution? J Evol Econ 16:511–527

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bull JJ, Wang I-N (2010) Optimality models in the age of experimental evolution and genomics. J Evol Biol 23:1820–1838

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (1993) Taking the naturalistic turn, or how real philosophy of science is done. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (1998) Self-organization and optimization: conflicting or complementary approaches? In: Van de Vijver G, Salthe SN, Delpos M (eds) Evolutionary systems: biological and epistemological perspectives on selection and self-organization. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 79–100

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (2003) Lorenz’s philosophical naturalism in the mirror of contemporary science studies. Ludus Vitalis 11:27–55

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (2007) Simon’s silent revolution. Biol Theory 2:76–86

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (2009a) Contingency and inherency in evolutionary developmental biology. In: Suárez M et al (eds) EPSA philosophical issues in the sciences: launch of the European Philosophy of Science Association. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 1–7

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (2009b) Innovation from EvoDevo to culture. In: O’Brien MJ, Shennan SJ (eds) Innovation in cultural systems: contributions from evolutionary anthropology. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 81–95

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (2010) The dialectics of dis/unity in the Evolutionary Synthesis and its extensions. In: Pigliucci M, Müller GB (eds) Evolution: the extended synthesis. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 443–481

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (2011) Beyond generalized Darwinism. I. Evolutionary economics from the perspective of naturalistic philosophy of biology. Biol Theory 6. doi:10.1007/s13752-013-0086-2

  • Callebaut W (2012) Scientific perspectivism: a philosopher of science’s response to the challenge of big data biology. Stud Hist Phil Biol Biomed Sci 43:69–80

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W, Rasskin-Gutman D (eds) (2005) Modularity: understanding the development and evolution of natural complex systems. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W, Müller GB, Newman SA (2007) The organismic systems approach: Evo-Devo and the streamlining of the naturalistic agenda. In: Sansom R, Brandon RN (eds) Integrating evolution and development: from theory to practice. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 25–92

    Google Scholar 

  • Camazine S, Deneubourg J-L, Franks NR, Sneyd J, Theraulaz J, Bonabeau E (2001) Self-organization in biological systems. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell DT (1960) Blind variation and selective retention in creative thought as in other knowledge processes. Inquiry 2:152–182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell DT (1997) In: Heyes C, Frankel B (eds) From evolutionary epistemology via selection theory to a sociology of scientific validity. Evol Cogn 3:5–38

  • Carroll SB (2005) Endless forms most beautiful: the new science of Evo Devo and the making of the animal kingdom. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero A, Turvey MT (2007) Complexity, hypersets, and the ecological perspective on perception-action. Biol Theory 2:23–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1986) Evolutionary epistemology and the scientific method. Philosophica 37:151–162

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke E (2012) Plant individuality: a solution to the demographer’s dilemma. Biol Philos 27:321–361

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Debaise D (2011) Cerveaux. In: Azzouni S, Brandt C, Gausemeier B, Kursell J, Schmidgen H, Wittmann B (eds) Eine Naturgeschichte für das 21. Jahrhundert. Hommage à, zu Ehren von, in honor of Hans-Jörg Rheinberger. Max-Planck-Institut für Wissenschaftsgeschichte, Berlin, pp 22–23

  • Depew DJ, Weber BH (1995) Darwinism evolving: systems dynamics and the genealogy of natural selection. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • de Regt H, Leonelli S, Eigner K (eds) (2009) Scientific understanding: philosophical perspectives. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickins TE, Rahman Q (2012) The extended evolutionary synthesis and the role of soft inheritance in evolution. Proc R Soc B 279:2913–2921

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earnshaw E (2011) Evolution beyond biology: examining the evolutionary economics of Nelson and Winter. Biol Theory 6. doi:10.1007/s13752-012-0050-6

  • Esposito JL (1975) Remarks toward a general theory of organization. Int J Gen Syst 2:133–143

    Google Scholar 

  • Fogelman Soulié F (ed) (1991) Les théories de la complexité : autour de l’oeuvre d’Henri Atlan. Seuil, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Foster J (1997) The analytic foundations of evolutionary economics: from biological analogy to economic self-organization. Struc Chang Econ Dyn 8:427–451

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frenken K (2006) A fitness landscape approach to technological complexity, modularity, and vertical disintegration. Struct Chang Econ Dyn 17:288–305

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frenken K, Mendritzki S (2012) Optimal modularity: a demonstration of the evolutionary advantage of modular archictectures. J Evol Econ 22:935–956

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gavrilets S (2004) Fitness landscapes and the origins of species. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon J (2011) Economic natural selection: Which concept of selection? Biol Theory 6. doi:10.1007/s13752-012-0042-6

  • Gers M (2012) Overqualified: generative replicators as Darwinian reproducers. Biol Philos 27:595–605

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin MT (1987) Response to commentary on the individuality of species. Biol Philos 2:207–212

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere RN (2006) Modest evolutionary naturalism. Biol Theory 1:52–60

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert SF, Epel D (2009) Ecological developmental biology: integrating epigenetics, medicine, and evolution. Sinauer, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Gissis SB, Jablonka E (eds) (2011) Transformations of Lamarckism: from subtle fluids to molecular biology. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (1996) Complexity and the function of mind in nature. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2001) The role of information and replication in selection processes. Behav Brain Sci 24:538

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2011) Agents and acacias: replies to Dennett, Sterelny, and Queller. Biol Philos 26:501–515

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin BC (1984) Changing from an evolutionary to a generative paradigm in biology. In: Pollard JW (ed) Evolutionary theory: paths into the future. Wiley, Chichester, pp 99–120

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1992) Dinosaurs in the haystack. Nat Hist 3(92):2–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (2001a) The evolutionary definition of selective agency, validation of the theory of hierarchical selection, and fallacy of the selfish gene. In: Singh RS, Krimbas CB, Paul DB, Beatty J (eds) Thinking about evolution, vol 2. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 208–234

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (2001b) More things in Heaven and Earth. In: Rose H, Rose S (eds) Alas poor Darwin: arguments against evolutionary psychology. Vintage, London, pp 85–195

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer JR (2000a) The units of evolutionary transition. Selection 1:67–80

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer JR (2000b) Development, culture, and the units of inheritance. Philos Sci 67:S348–S368

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer JR (2005) The informational gene and the substantial body: on the generalization of evolutionary theory by abstraction. In: Jones MR, Cartwright N (eds), Idealizations XII. Correcting the model: idealization and abstraction in the sciences. Rodopi, Amsterdam, pp 59–115

  • Griesemer J (2012) Formalization and the meaning of “theory” in the inexact biological sciences. Biol Theory 7 (forthcoming)

  • Guinnane TW, Sundstrom WA, Whatley WC (eds) (2004) History matters: essays on economic growth, technology, and demographic change. Stanford University Press, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hallgrímsson B, Hall BK (eds) (2011) Epigenetics: linking genotype and phenotype in development and evolution. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamminga B (1983) Neoclassical theory structure and theory development: an empirical-philosophical case study concerning the theory of international trade. Springer, Berin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hands DW (1985) The structuralist view of economic theories: a review essay. Econ Philos 1:303–335

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2004) The firm as an interactor: firms as vehicles for habits and routines. J Evol Econ 14:281–307

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2006) Why we need a generalized Darwinism, and why generalized Darwinism is not enough. J Econ Behav Organ 61:1–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2010) Darwin’s conjecture: the search for general principles of social and economic evolution. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2011) Generalized Darwinism and evolutionary economics: from ontology to theory. Biol Theory 6. doi:10.1007/s13752-012-0043-5

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2012) Underqualified—maximal generality in Darwinian explanation: a response to Matt Gers. Biol Philos 27:607–614

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (1988) Science as a process: an evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Hull DL (2006) The essence of scientific theories. Biol Theory 1:17–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL, Langman R, Glenn S (2001) A general account of selection: biology, immunology and behavior. Behav Brain Sci 24:511–573

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E, Lamb MJ (2005) Evolution in four dimensions: genetic, epigenetic, behavioral, and symbolic variation in the history of life. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E, Lamb MJ (2010) Transgenerational epigenetic inheritance. In: Pigliucci M, Müller GB (eds) Evolution: the extended synthesis. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 137–174

    Google Scholar 

  • Kane MD (2001) The evolutionary biology of … everything. Syst Biol 50:468–469

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan J (2008) The end of the adaptive landscape metaphor. Biol Philos 23:625–638

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman S (1993) The origins of order: self-organization and selection in evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Koonin EV (2011) The logic of chance: the nature and origin of biological evolution. Pearson Education, Upper Saddle River

    Google Scholar 

  • Krakauer DC, Collins JP, Erwin D, Flack JC, Fontana W, Laubichler MD, Prohaska SJ, West GB, Stadler PF (2011) The challenges and scope of theoretical biology. J Theor Biol 276:269–276

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krohs U, Callebaut W (2007) Data without models merging with models without data. In: Boogerd FC, Bruggeman FJ, Hofmeyer J-H, Westerhoff HV (eds) Systems biology: philosophical foundations. Elsevier, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1970) The structure of scientific revolutions, 2nd edn. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff G, Johnson M (1980) Metaphors we live by. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Laland KN, Brown GR (2006) Niche construction, human behavior, and the adaptive-lag hypothesis. Evol Anthrop 15:95–104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland KN, O’Brien M (eds) (2011) Cultural niche construction. Biol Theory 6(3)

  • Laland KN, Sterelny K, Odling-Smee J, Hoppitt WJE, Uller T (2011) Cause and effect in biology revisited: is Mayr’s proximate-ultimate dichotomy still useful? Science 334:1512–1516

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laubichler MD, Müller GB (eds) (2007) Modeling biology: structures, behaviors, evolution. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawler J (2005) Making the point with metaphors: not just for poets. Editor Eye 28(4):1–3

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennox JG (2008) Darwinism and neo-Darwinism. In: Sarkar S, Plutynski A (eds) A companion to the philosophy of biology. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 77–98

    Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli S (2008) Bio-ontologies as tools for integration in biology. Biol Theory 3:7–11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levinthal DA (1997) Adaptation on rugged landscapes. Manag Sci 43:934–950

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levit GS, Hossfeld U, Witt U (2011) Can Darwinism be “generalized” and of what use would this be? J Evol Econ 21:545–562

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1963) Models, mathematics and metaphors. Synthese 15:222–244

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1970) The units of selection. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 1:1–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1996) Evolution as engineering. In: Collado-Vides J, Magasanik B, Smith TF (eds) Integrative approaches to molecular biology. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 1–10

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz K (1974) Analogy as a source of knowledge. Science 185:229–234

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann N (1988) Die Wirtschaft der Gesellschaft. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch M (2007) The frailty of adaptive hypotheses for the origins of organismal complexity. PNAS 1(Suppl 104):8597–8604

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J, Szathmáry E (1995) The major transitions in evolution. Freeman, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy IP (2004) Manufacturing strategy: understanding the fitness landscape. Int J Oper Prod Manag 24:124–150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGhee G (2011) Convergent evolution: limited forms most beautiful. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin E (1983) Values in science. In: Asquith PD, Nickles T (eds) PSA 1982. Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, pp 3–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Morange M (2009) Synthetic biology: a bridge between functional and evolutionary biology. Biol Theory 4:368–377

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan MS, Morrison M (eds) (1999) Models as mediators: perspectives on natural and social science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 10–37

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB (2005) Evolutionary developmental biology. In: Wuketits FM, Ayala FJ (eds) Handbook of evolution, vol 2. Wiley, San Diego, pp 87–115

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB (2007) Evo-devo: extending the evolutionary synthesis. Nat Rev Gen 8:943–949

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB (2008) Evo-devo as a discipline. In: Minelli A, Fusco G (eds) Evolving pathways: key themes in evolutionary developmental biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 3–29

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB, Newman SA (2003) Origination of organismal form: beyond the gene in development and evolutionary biology. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB, Olson L (2003) Epigenesis and epigenetics. In: Hall BK, Olson WM (eds) Keywords and concepts in evolutionary developmental biology. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 114–123

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson RR (2011) Human behavior and cognition in evolutionary economics. Biol Theory 6. doi:10.1007/s13752-012-0036-4

  • Nelson RR, Winter SG (1982) An evolutionary theory of economic change. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman SA, Müller GB (2006) Genes and form: inherency in the evolution of developmental mechanisms. In: Neumann-Held EM, Rehmann-Sutter C (eds) Genes in development. Duke University Press, Durham, pp 38–73

    Google Scholar 

  • Nicolis G, Nicolis C (2012) Foundations of complex systems: emergence, information and prediction. World Scientific, Singapore

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley MA, Boucher Y (2005) Paradigm change in evolutionary microbiology. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 36:183–208

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley M, Dupré J (2007) Size doesn’t matter: towards a more inclusive philosophy of biology. Biol Philos 22:155–191

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley M, Elliott KC, Burian RM (2010) From genetic to genomic regulation: iterativity in micro-RNA research. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 41:407–417

    Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee J (2010) Niche inheritance. In: Pigliucci M, Müller GB (eds) Evolution: the extended synthesis. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 175–207

    Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee FJ, Laland KN, Feldman MW (2003) Niche construction: the neglected process in evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Olendzenski L, Gogarten JP (2009) The tree/web of life in light of horizontal gene transfer. Ann NY Acad Sci 1178:137–145

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Padgett JF, Powell WW (2012) The emergence of organizations and markets. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacock KA (2011) The three faces of ecological fitness. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 42:99–105

    Google Scholar 

  • Pelikan P (2011) Evolutionary developmental economics: how to generalize Darwinism fruitfully to help comprehend economic change. J Evol Econ 21:341–366

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M, Müller GB (eds) (2010) Evolution: the extended synthesis. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (1979) Objective knowledge: an evolutionary approach, 2nd edn. orig. 1972. Clarendon Press, Oxford

  • Rice C, Smart J (2011) Interdisciplinary modeling: a case study of evolutionary economics. Biol Philos 26:655–675

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riedl R (1977) A systems-analytic approach to macroevolutionary phenomena. Q Rev Biol 52:351–370

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riedl R (1978) Order in living organisms: a systems analysis of evolution. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Rose MR, Oakley TH (2007) The new biology: beyond the modern synthesis. Biol Direct 2:30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross D (2006) Game theory in studies of evolution and development: prospects for deeper use. Biol Theory 1:31–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shennan S (2011) Property and wealth inequality as cultural niche construction. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B 366:918–926

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1983) Reason in human affairs. Stanford University Press, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Stearns SC (1976) Life history tactics: review of the ideas. Q Rev Biol 51:3–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2006) The evolution and evolvability of culture. Mind Lang 21:137–165

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2011) Darwinian spaces: peter Godfrey-Smith on selection and evolution. Biol Philos 26:489–500

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stoelhorst J-W (2008) Darwinian foundations for evolutionary economics. J Econ Issues 42:415–423

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppe F (1977) The structure of scientific theories, 2nd edn. University of Illinois Press, Urbana

    Google Scholar 

  • Swenson R (2010) Selection is entailed by self-organization and natural selection is a special case. Biol Theory 5:167–181

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swenson R, Turvey MT (1991) Thermodynamic reasons for perception-action cycles. Biol Psychol 15:115–133

    Google Scholar 

  • Tinbergen N (1963) On aims and methods of ethology. Z Tierpsych 20:410–433

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vromen J (2007) Generalized Darwinism in evolutionary economics: The devil is in the details. Papers on Economics and Evolution No. 0711. Max Planck Institute of Economics, Jena

  • Vromen J (2012) Ontological issues in evolutionary economics: the debate between Generalized Darwinism and the Continuity Hypothesis. In: Mäki U (ed) Handbook of the philosophy of science, vol 13., Philosophy of economicsElsevier, Amsterdam, pp 737–763

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP, Pavlicev M, Cheverud JM (2007) The road to modularity. Nat Rev Gen 8:921–931

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walliser B (2011) Learning versus evolution: from biology to game theory. Biol Theory 6. doi:10.1007/s13752-012-0071-1

  • Walsh D (2012) Situated adaptationism. In: Kabasenche WP, O’Rourke M, Slater MH (eds) The environment: philosophy, science, and ethics. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 89–116

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M, Okasha S, Mäki U (2011) Modeling in biology and economics. Biol Philos 26:613–615

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiss KM, Buchanan AV, Lambert BW (2011) The red queen and her king: cooperation at all levels of life. Yearb Phys Anthropol 54:3–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhardt MJ (2003) Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Whyte LL (1965) Internal factors in evolution. George Braziller, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins JS, Stanyon C, Musgrave I (2012) Selection without replicators: the origin of genes, and the replicator/interactor distinction in etiobiology. Biol Philos 27:215–239

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson EO (1981) Epigenesis and the evolution of social systems. J Hered 72:70–77

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (2006) Generative entrenchment and an evolutionary developmental biology for culture. Behav Brain Sci 29:364–366

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (2003) The evolving economy: essays on the evolutionary approach to economics. Edgar Elgar, Cheltenham

    Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (2008) What is specific about evolutionary economics? J Evol Econ 18:547–575

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (2009) Propositions about novelty. J Econ Behav Organ 70:311–320

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (2011) Economic behavior and evolutionary versus behavioral perspectives. Biol Theory 6. doi:10.1007/s13752-012-0035-5

Download references

Acknowledgments

The ideas developed in this article were presented and discussed at the 22nd Altenberg Workshop in Theoretical Biology, “Models of Man for Evolutionary Economics,” KLI, Altenberg, September 2009; in a talk at the Institut d’Histoire et de Philosophie des Sciences et Techniques (IHPST), Paris, March 2011; in a session on “Darwin’s Conjecture: Discussing the Ontological Foundations of Evolutionary Economics” at the European Association for Evolutionary Political Economy (EAEPE) Conference on Schumpeter’s Heritage, “The Evolution of the Theory of Evolution,” Vienna, October 2011; and at the Ringberg Symposium, “Biological Determinants and Contingencies of Economic Behavior—Perspectives from Evolutionary Biology, Psychology, and Economics,” Tegernsee, August 2012. I would like to thank my audiences at these occasions, and in particular Kurt Dopfer, Jean Gayon, Geoff Hodgson, Michael Ghiselin, Dick Nelson, Jan-Willem Stoelhorst, Jack Vromen, Manuel Wäckerle, David Sloan Wilson, and Ulrich Witt, for very useful feedback. Error clause as usual.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Werner Callebaut.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Callebaut, W. Beyond Generalized Darwinism. II. More Things in Heaven and Earth. Biol Theory 6, 351–365 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-013-0087-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-013-0087-1

Keywords

Navigation