Skip to main content
Log in

Brain-Computer Interfaces and the Translation of Thought into Action

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Neuroethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A brain-computer interface (BCI) designed to restore motor function detects neural activity related to intended movement and thereby enables a person to control an external device, for example, a robotic limb, or even their own body. It would seem legitimate, therefore, to describe a BCI as a system that translates thought into action. This paper argues that present BCI-mediated behavior fails to meet the conditions of intentional physical action as proposed by causal and non-causal theories of action. First, according to the causal theory of action physical actions are bodily movements that are causally related to a person’s intentions. It can be argued, however, that the proximate cause of action in present BCI-mediated behavior is not the person’s intention, and that the behavior fails to meet the conditions of reliability, sensitivity and difference-making. Second, BCI-mediated behavior can be accommodated by a Volitionist account of action if we can equate imagining movement with trying to move. The argument presented is that the novelty, and limited functionality and sensory feedback of present BCIs challenges this equation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. Bates, M. 2018. Converting thoughts into action. BrainFacts.org. Accessed 22 Sept 2019.

  2. Vidal, G.W., et al. 2016. Review of brain-machine interfaces used in neural prosthetics with new perspective on somatosensory feedback through method of signal breakdown. Scientifica. https://doi.org/10.1155/2016/8956432.

  3. Clark, A. 2003. Natural born cyborgs. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Rainey, S., et al. 2019. Neuroprosthetics speech: The ethical significance of accuracy, control, and pragmatics. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 28 (4): 657–670.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Gilbert, F. 2015. A threat to autonomy? The intrusion of predictive brain implants. AJOB Neuroscience 6 (4): 4–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Gilbert, F., et al. 2019. Embodiment and estrangement: Results from a first-in-human “intelligent BCI” trial. Science and Engineering Ethics 25: 83–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Kellymeyer, P., et al. 2016. The effects of closed-loop medical devices on the autonomy and accountability of persons and systems. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 25: 623–633.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Clausen, J. 2010. Ethical brain stimulation – Neuroethics of deep brain stimulation in research and clinical practice. European Journal of Neuroscience 32: 1152–1162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Donoghue, J.P. 2008. Bridging the brain to the world: A perspective on neural interface systems. Neuron 60 (3): 511–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Carmena, J.M. 2003 et al. Learning to control a brain-machine interface for reaching and grasping by primates. PLoS Biology. 1(2) doi:https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.0000042.

  11. Lebedev, M.A., and M.A.L. Nicolelis. 2006. Brain-machine interfaces: Past, present, and future. Trends in Neurosciences 29 (9): 536–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Aflalo, T., et al. 2015. Decoding motor imagery for the posterior parietal cortex of a tetraplegic human being. Science 348 (6237): 906–910.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Tankus, A., et al. 2014. Cognitive-motor brain-machine interfaces. Journal of Physiology, Paris 108 (1): 38–44. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jphysparis.2013.05.005.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Andersen, R. 2019. The intention machine. Scientific American 320 (4): 24–41.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Collinger, J.L., et al. 2013. High-performance neuroprosthetic control by an individual with tetraplegia. The Lancet 381 (9866): 557–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Davidson, D. 1980. Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Aguilar, J.H., and A.A. Buckareff. 2010. Causing human actions: New perspectives on the causal theory of action. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  18. Peacocke, C. 1979. Holistic explanation: Action, space, interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Aquilar, J.H. 2010. Agential systems, causal deviance, and reliability. In Causing human actions: New perspectives on the causal theory of action, ed. J.H. Aquilar and A.A. Buckareff, 85–101. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  20. Bishop, J. 1989. Natural agency: An essay on the causal theory of action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Bensmaia, S.J. 2015. Biological and bionic hands: Natural neural coding and artificial perception. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 370: 20140209. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2014.0209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Bensmair, S.J., and L.E. Miller. 2014. Restoring sensorimotor function through intracortical interfaces: Progress and looming challenges. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 15: 313–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Steinert, S., et al. 2018. Doing things with thoughts: Brain-computer interfaces and disembodied agency. Philosophy and Technology. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-018-0308-4.

  24. Vargas-Irwin, et al. 2018. Watch, imagine, attempt: Motor cortex single-unit activity reveals context dependent movement encoding in humans with tetraplegia. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2018.00450.

  25. Woodward, J.F. 2008. Mental causation and neural mechanisms. In Being reduced: New essay on reductive explanation and special science causation, ed. J. Hohwy and J. Kallestrup, 218–263. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  26. Pernu, T.K. 2018. Mental causation via neuroprosthetics? A critical analysis. Synthese 195: 5159–5174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Hornsby, J. 2004. Agency and actions. In Agency and action, ed. H. Steward and J. Hyman, 1–23. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Wong, H.Y. 2018. Embodied agency. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 97 (3): 584–612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Clark, A., and D. Chalmers. 1998. The extended mind. Analysis 58: 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tom Buller.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Buller, T. Brain-Computer Interfaces and the Translation of Thought into Action. Neuroethics 14, 155–165 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-020-09433-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-020-09433-9

Keywords

Navigation