Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Reduction, Explanation, and the New Science of Religion

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this essay, we set out to survey and critically assess various attitudes and understandings of reductionism as it appears in discussions regarding the scientific study of religion. Our objective in the essay is twofold. First, we articulate what we will refer to as three ‘meta-interpretative’ frameworks, which summarize the distinct positions one can witness in response to the explanations coming out of research within the new science of religion. Second, and more importantly, we seek to demonstrate that under no sensible interpretation of the notion of ‘reduction’ do the explanations provide a basis for defending one of the meta-interpretative frameworks rather than another.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Much has been written about the history of explanation in religious studies. For more on the subject, see Preus (1987).  

  2. In Naturalism, Theism and the Cognitive Study of Religion, Aku Visala proposes three possible readings of the relationship between CSR and Theism: 1) The Falsity of Religious Belief Thesis; 2) the Religious Relevance Thesis; and 3) the Religious Agnosticism Thesis. He argues that reading 2 is the most reasonable because reading 1 presupposes a strict naturalism, which he has argued is not the only philosophical framework for CSR, and reading 3 seems to "go a bit too far" as there "are reasons to think that some CSR theories might challenge some claims associated with theism as well as have an impact on some arguments made for (and against) theism” (p. 159). The main thesis of Visala's work is to argue against the claim that a strict naturalist framework (i.e., physicalism) is necessary for CSR methodology or current theories in order to argue that CSR does not necessarily imply atheism. Visala is not trying to dismisss the viability or the findings of CSR as a research project, but rather argue that it is compatible with a “broad naturalism” grounded in a non-reductive materialism that denies the causal closure of the physical.  It should be noted that Visala's book is an attempt at working out of implications and findings of CSR that the current project argues is necessary prior to adoption of any one of the meta-interpretive framework. We thank an anonymous reviewer for referring us to this work.

  3. The emphasis we add here is to highlight that our project is intended to help clarify Proudfoot’s stated confusion about the term ‘reduction’.

  4. There are numerous discussions regarding these issues. For representative examples, one can look at the debate between Francisca Cho and Richard K. Squier and Edward Slingerland in the Journal of the American Academy of Religion (Cho & Squier 2008a, b, c; Slingerland 2008a, b, c) or the review symposium of Anne Taves’s Religious Experience Reconsidered in Religion (Stausberg et al. 2010).

  5. Proponents of the sui generis view might object to this claim. They might maintain that the HADD module DOES wrongfully minimize belief in supernatural beings, for it fails to account for the individual subject’s own sense of their commitment to those beings’ existence and activity. However, this response betrays a terrible misunderstanding of explanation in this context. The explanadum is not individuals’ own sense of their propositional commitment, it is the prevalence of individuals who have this type of commitment. All the response does, in short, isintroduce a new explanatory project, and surely an explanation cannot be faulted for failing to have explained something it does not set out to explain.

  6. This idea of ‘extra-logical factors’ is inspired by Willard V. O. Quine’s classic views on empirical underdetermination (1951) but even more by Longino’s (2001) social philosophy of science, wherein ‘non-cognitive values’ are an integral part of a satisfactory account of good scientific practice.6 This line of argument will no doubt prove unconvincing to many who insist that the final arbiter of successful epistemic practice is the truth, in its traditional objective, or correspondence, sense. These critics may contend that one should generally expect sound epistemic practice to converge on a single set of correct beliefs, and that the position we've adopted here fails in this regard. This criticism targets a fundamental philosophical issue that goes well beyond the scope of this essay; however, we would acknowledge that our views do commit us to rejecting this standard for successful epistemic practice. We thank an anonymous reviewer for encouraging us to think about this point. 

  7. This line of argument will no doubt prove unconvincing to many who insist that the final arbiter of successful epistemic practice is the truth, in its traditional objective, or correspondence, sense. These critics may contend that one should generally expect sound epistemic practice to converge on a single set of correct beliefs, and that the position we've adopted here fails in this regard. This criticism targets a fundamental philosophical issue that goes well beyond the scope of this essay; however, we would acknowledge that our views do commit us to rejecting this standard for successful epistemic practice. We thank an anonymous reviewer for encouraging us to think about this point.

References

  • Barrett, J. (2004). Why would anyone believe in God? Walnut Creek, CA: AltaMira.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2009). Looking down, around, and up: mechanistic explanation in psychology. Philosophical Psychology, 22, 543–564.

  • Bickle, J. (2003). Philosophy and neuroscience: a ruthlessly reductive account. Norwell, MA: Kluwer.

  • Boyer, P. (2002). Religion explained. New York, NY: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cho, F., & Squier, R. K. (2008a). He blinded me with science: science chauvinism in the study of religion. Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 76, 420–448.

  • Cho, F., & Squier, R. K. (2008b). Reductionism: be afraid, be very afraid. Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 76, 412–417.

  • Cho, F., & Squier, R. K. (2008c). Reply to Slingerland. Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 76, 455–456.

  • Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the Brain. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (2006). Breaking the spell: religion as a natural phenomenon. New York, NY: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (2001). The fate of knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCutcheon, R. (1997). Manufacturing religion: the discourse onsui generis religion and the politics of nostalgia New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

  • McCutcheon, R. (2001). Critics not caretakers: redescribing the public study of religion. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preus, J. S. (1987). Explaining Religion: criticism and theory from Bodin to Freud. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Proudfoot, W. (1985). Religious experience. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1951). Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review, 60, 20–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slingerland, E. (2008a). Reply to Cho and Squier. Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 76, 418–419.

  • Slingerland, E. (2008b). Response to Cho and Squier. Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 76, 449–454.

  • Slingerland, E. (2008c). Who’s afraid of reductionism? The study of religion in the age of cognitive science. Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 76, 375–411.

  • Stausberg, M., et al. (2010). Review symposium of Anne Taves’s religious experience reconsidered. Religion, 40, 279–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tremlin, T. (2010). Minds and Gods: the cognitive foundations of religion. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (2006). Reductionism and its heuristics: making methodological reductionism honest. Synthese, 151, 445–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christopher H. Pearson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pearson, C.H., Schunke, M.P. Reduction, Explanation, and the New Science of Religion. SOPHIA 54, 47–60 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-014-0438-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-014-0438-9

Keywords

Navigation