Skip to main content
Log in

Complexity and individual psychology

  • Published:
Mind & Society Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper we examine the question of whether complexity-like explanations can be applied to the psychology of individuals, and its implications for the scope of complexity explanations of social phenomena. We start by outlining two representational-cum-computational models of the mind—a symbolic model and a networks or connectionist one—and their pros and cons. Based on this we then outline a radical, non-representational and non-computational alternative model that has been gaining ground recently, and which has significant affinities with complexity explanations in social science. Deploying neo-Kantian considerations, we then argue that due to the discursivity, or conceptual dimension of our cognitive system, the radical alternative must be incorrect insofar as humans are concerned. Indeed, human psychology must involve, at least partly, a representational understanding of the sort provided by the symbolic model. Relatedly, we show how the discursiviry of human cognition complicates our psychology and makes it difficult to account for. Finally, we briefly address the question of how the complicated nature of individual psychology, implied by human discursivity, may affect complexity explanations of social behavior.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Allen C, Bekoff M (1997) Species of mind: the philosophy and biology of cognitive ethology. Bradford, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson ML (2003) Embodied cognition: a field guide. Artif Intell 149:91–130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Audi R (2006) Practical reasoning and ethical decision. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett L (2011) Beyond the brain: how body and environment shape animal and human minds. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W, Abrahamsen A (2002) Connectionism and the mind: parallel processing, dynamics, and evolution in networks, 2nd edn. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Beer RD (1995) A dynamical systems perspective on agent-environment interaction. Artif Intell 72:173–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beer RD (2000) Dynamical approaches to cognitive science. Trends Cognit Sci 4:91–99

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beer RD, Gallagher JC (1992) Evolving dynamical neural networks for adaptive behavior. Adapt Behav 1:91–122

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks R (1991) Intelligence without reason. Reprinted in Brooks R (1999) Cambrian intelligence: the early history of the new AI. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 133–186

  • Buchanan M (2007) Social atoms: why the rich get richer, cheaters get caught, and your neighbor usually looks like you. Bloomsbury, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero A (2009) Radical embodied cognitive science. Bradford, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1990) Connectionist minds. Proc Aristot Soc 90:83–102

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1994) Representational trajectories in connectionist learning. Mind Mach 4:317–332

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1997a) Being there: putting brain, body, and world together again. Bradford, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1997b) The dynamical challenge. Cognit Sci 21:461–481

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1999) An embodied cognitive science? Trends Cognit Sci 3:345–351

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2001) Mindware: an introduction the philosophy of cognitive science. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2002) The roots of ‘norm-hungriness’. In: Clapin H (ed) Philosophy of mental representation. Clarendon Press, New York, pp 37–43

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2008) Supersizing the mind: embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A, Grush R (1999) Towards a cognitive robotics. Adapt Behav 7:5–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A, Thornton C (1997) Trading spaces: computation, representation, and the limits of uninformed learning. Brain Behav Sci 20:57–66

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A, Toribio J (1994) Doing without representing? Synthese 101:401–431

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins S, Ruina A (2005) A bipedal walking robot with efficient and human-like gait. Proceedings of the 2005 IEEE, 1983–1988

  • Collins S, Ruina A, Tedrake R, Wisse M (2005) Efficient bipedal robots based on passive-dynamic walkers. Science 307:1082–1085

    Article  CAS  PubMed  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Crane T (2003) The mechanical mind: a philosophical introduction to minds, machines and mental representation, 2nd edn. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (1982) Rational animals. Reprinted in Davidson D (2001) Subjective, intersubjective, objective. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 95–105

  • Engel AK, Maye A, Kurthen M, König P (2013) Where’s the action? The pragmatic turn in cognitive science. Trends Cognit Sci 17:202–209

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans G (1982) The varieties of reference. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor JA (1985) Fodor’s guide to mental representation: the intelligent auntie’s vade-mecum. Mind 94:76–100

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor JA (1987) Psychosemantics: the problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor JA, Pylyshyn ZW (1988) Connectionism and cognitive architecture: a critical analysis. Cognition 28:3–71

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Grush R (2004a) The emulation theory of representation: motor control, imagery, and perception. Brain Behav Sci 27:377–396

    Google Scholar 

  • Grush R (2004b) Further explorations of the empirical and theoretical aspects of the emulation theory. Brain Behav Sci 27:425–442

    Google Scholar 

  • Hallam J, Malcolm CA (1994) Behavior, perception, action and intelligence: the view from situated robots. Philos Trans R Soc A 349:29–42

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland J (ed) (1981) Mind design. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland J (1985) Artificial intelligence: the very idea. Bradford, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland J (1991) Representational genera. Reprinted in Haugeland J (1998) Having thought: Essays in the metaphysics of mind. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 171–206

  • Haugeland J (2002) Andy Clark on cognition and representation. In: Clapin H (ed) Philosophy of mental representation. Clarendon Press, New York, pp 24–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1998) Critique of pure reason (trans: Guyer P, Wood AW). Cambridge University Press, New York

  • Levin Y, Aharon I (2014) Emotion, utility maximization, and ecological rationality. Mind Soc 13:227–245

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luntley M (1999) Contemporary philosophy of thought. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr D (2010) Vision: a computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell J (1996) Mind and world. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell J (2009) Having the world in view: essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • McGeer T (1990) Passive dynamic walking. Int J Robot Res 9:62–82

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë A (2004) Action in perception. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • North DC (1994) Economic performance through time. Am Econ Rev 84:359–368

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfeifer R, Fumiya L, Lungarella M (2014) Cognition from the bottom up: on biological inspiration, body morphology, and soft materials. Trends Cognit Sci 18:404–413

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn ZW (2003) Seeing and visualizing: it’s not what you think. Bradford, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey W, Stitch S, Garon J (1991) Connectionism, eliminitivism, and the future of folk psychology. In: Ramsey W, Rumelhart DE, Stich SP (eds) Philosophy and connectionist theory. Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, pp 199–228

    Google Scholar 

  • Rayner K, Pollatsek A (2013) Basic processes in reading. In: Reisberg D (ed) The Oxford handbook of cognitive psychology. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 442–461

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumelhart D, Smolensky P, McClelland J, Hinton G (1986) Schemata and sequential thought processes in PDP models. In: McClelland J, Rummelhart D, the PDP Research Group (eds) Parallel distributed processing: explorations in the microstructure of cognition, vol 2. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 7–57

    Google Scholar 

  • Satz D, Ferejohn J (1994) Rational choice and social theory. J Philos 91:71–87

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars W (1997) Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro L (2011) Embodied cognition. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Sreterlny K (1990) The representational theory of mind: an introduction. Basil Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Stitch S (1979) Do animals have beliefs? Australas J Philos 57:15–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder T (1991) What is the “D” in “PDP”? A survey of the concept of distribution. In: Ramsey W, Stich S, Rumelhart DE (eds) Philosophy and connectionist theory. Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, pp 33–59

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder T (1995) What might cognition be, if not computation? J Philos 92:345–381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder T (1998) The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science. Behav Brain Sci 21:615–628

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder T (1999) Dynamic approaches to cognition. In: Wilson R, Keil F (eds) The MIT encyclopedia of cognitive sciences. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 244–246

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder T, Port RF (1995) It’s about time: an overview of the dynamical approach to cognition. In: Port RF, van Gelder T (eds) Mind as motion. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 1–43

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler M (2005) Reconstructing the cognitive world: the next step. Bradford, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson AD, Golonka S (2013) Embodied cognition is not what you think it is. Front Psychol 4:1–13

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

An early version of this paper was presented at a workshop on rationality models and economic crises organized by the Jean Nicod Institute in Paris. We would like to thank the participants in this workshop for their helpful comments. We are also grateful to Andy Clark, Oron Shagrir, and Larry Shapiro for their helpful comments on earlier versions of the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yakir Levin.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Levin, Y., Aharon, I. Complexity and individual psychology. Mind Soc 14, 203–219 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11299-015-0171-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11299-015-0171-2

Keywords

Navigation