Skip to main content
Log in

One world, one beable

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Is the quantum state part of the furniture of the world? Einstein found such a position indigestible, but here I present a different understanding of the wavefunction that is easy to stomach. First, I develop the idea that the wavefunction is nomological in nature, showing how the quantum It or Bit debate gets subsumed by the corresponding It or Bit debate about laws of nature. Second, I motivate the nomological view by casting quantum mechanics in a “classical” formalism (Hamilton–Jacobi theory) and classical mechanics in a “quantum” formalism (Koopman–von Neumann theory) and then comparing and contrasting classical and quantum wave functions. I argue that Humeans about laws can treat classical and quantum wave functions on a par and that doing so yields many benefits.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Strictly speaking, because the particle configuration doesn’t affect the wavefunction, we have only one half of Descartes’ problem. The question here is more like the “causation” problem afflicting the mind–body epiphenomenalist.

  2. Another much more radical notion is doing without the wavefunction at all; that is, writing the theory directly in terms of an equation for the beables and nothing more. Suggestive models exist that suggest this path both for GRW-type theories (e.g., Dowker and Henson 2004) and for Bohm-like theories (e.g., Poirier 2010); however, since the latter model is committed to an actual infinite ensemble of “world” trajectories, it seems more like an Everettian theory.

  3. As Goldstein and Zanghì (2013) point out, effective wavefunctions therefore have quasi-nomological status. They are a function over what is nomological, \(\Psi _{t}\), and the contingent environment, \(Y_{t}\).

  4. Both theories can be “squashed” together into many abstract formulations, so one has many choices. I’ll choose two that I find enlightening, but of course there are many others, e.g., phase space formulations of both theories. I’ll count classical statistical mechanics as classical physics. This move is justified in the present context, I believe, by the fact that “beable” interpretations of quantum mechanics often regard quantum mechanics as a kind of statistical mechanics of beables (Dürr et al. 1992).

  5. Note that matters don’t work out as simply when we add spin and move away from the Schrödinger equation; see Holland (1993).

  6. Here I stress ’alone’ because of course linearity is related to entanglement which is related to the difference I’ll mention momentarily. My point is not to de-emphasize the above differences but rather just to point out that more premises are needed to get from these to the reification of the wavefunction. An argument is needed, and one is supplied below. Others based on different formal differences may be possible, but I suspect that they will only reproduce the essence of the ’causal agent’ argument below.

  7. See Brown and Wallace (2005), Deutsch (1996), Wallace (2008) and Zeh (1999).

References

  • Albert, D. (1996). Elementary quantum metaphysics. In J. T. Cushing, A. Fine, & S. Goldstein (Eds.), Bohmian mechanics and quantum theory: An appraisal (pp. 277–284). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Anandan, J., & Brown, H. (1995). On the reality of space–time geometry and the wavefunction. Foundations of Physics, 25(2), 349–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, J. S. (2004). Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics: Collected papers on quantum philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Belot, G. (2012). Quantum states for primitive ontologists. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2(1), 67–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, D. (1952). A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of “Hidden” variables. I. Physical Review, 85(2), 166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bracken, A. J. (2003). Quantum mechanics as an approximation to classical mechanics in Hilbert space. Journal of Physics A, 36, L329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H., Dewdney, C., & Horton, G. (1995). Bohm particles and their detection in the light of neutron interferometry. Foundations of Physics, 25, 329–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H., Elby, A., & Weingard, R. (1996). Cause and effect in the pilot-wave interpretation of quantum mechanics. In J. T. Cushing, et al. (Eds.), Bohmian mechanics and quantum theory: An appraisal (pp. 309–319). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H., & Wallace, D. (2005). Solving the measurement problem: De Broglie–Bohm loses out to Everett. Foundations of Physics, 35, 517–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brumer, P., & Gong, J. (2006). Born rule in quantum and classical mechanics. Physical Review A, 73(5).

  • Bondar, D., Cabrera, R., Lompay, R., Ivanov, M., & Rabitz, H. (2012). Operational dynamic modeling transcending quantum and classical mechanics. Physical Review Letters, 109(19), 190403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. (2001). Humean supervenience and rotating homogeneous matter. Mind, 110, 25–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C., & Weingard, R. (1994). A Bohmian model of quantum cosmology. Philosophy of Science, 1, S228–S237.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C., & Weingard, R. (1997). Trouble in paradise? Problems for Bohm’s theory. The monist, 80(1), 24–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, J. (2012). Laws of nature. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2012 edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2012/entries/laws-of-nature/.

  • Cohen, J., & Callender, C. (2009). The better best system theory of lawhood. Philosophical Studies, 145(1), 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deutsch, D. (1996). Comment on lockwood. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 47, 222–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowker, F., & Henson, J. 2004. Spontaneous collapse models on a lattice. Journal of Statistical Physics, 115, 1327–1339.

  • Dürr, Detlef, Goldstein, S., & Zanghì, N. (1992). Quantum equilibrium and the origin of absolute uncertainty. Journal of Statistical Physics, 67, 843–907.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., & Zanghì, N. (1997). Bohmian mechanics and the meaning of the wave function. In R. S. Cohen, M. Horne, & J. Stachel (Eds.), Experimental metaphysics—quantum mechanical studies for Abner Shimony; Boston studies in the philosophy of science 193 (pp. 25–38). Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Esfeld, M., Lazarovici, D., Hubert, M., & Dürr, D. (2013). The ontology of Bohmian mechanics. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

  • Everett, H. (1957). The ‘relative state’ formulation of quantum mechanics. Review of Modern Physics, 29, 454–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, S., & Teufel, S. (2001). Quantum spacetime without observers: Ontological clarity and the conceptual foundations of quantum gravity. In C. Callender & S. Teufel (Eds.), Physics meets philosophy at the Planck scale (pp. 275–289). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, S., & Zanghì, N. (2013). Reality and the role of the wave function in quantum theory. In D. Albert & A. Ney (Eds.), The wave function: Essays on the metaphysics of quantum mechanics (pp. 91–109). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Groenewold, H. (1946). On the principles of elementary quantum mechanics. Physica, 12, 405–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. Humean reductionism about laws of nature. Unpublished MS. http://philpapers.org/rec/HALHRA.

  • Hardy, L. (2012). Are quantum states real? arxiv.org/pdf/1205.1439.

  • Harrigan, R., & Spekkens, (2010). Einstein, incompleteness, and the epistemic view of quantum states. Foundations of Physics, 40, 125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holland, P. R. (1993). The quantum theory of motion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Howard, D. (1990). ‘Nicht Sein Kann Was Nicht Sein Darf’, or the prehistory of EPR, 1909–1935: Einstein’s early worries about the quantum mechanics of composite systems. In A. I. Miller (Ed.), Sixty-two years of uncertainty. New York: Plenum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huggett, N. (2006). The regularity account of relational spacetime. Mind, 115, 41–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jauslin, H. R., & Sugny, D. (2009). Dynamics of mixed classical-quantum systems, geometric quantization and coherent states (Review Vol.). Lecture Note Series. IMS, NUS, Singapore.

  • Koopman, B. O. (1931). Hamiltonian systems and transformations in Hilbert space. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 17(5), 315–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leifer, M. (2011) Can the quantum state be interpreted statistically? Web log post. http://mattleifer.info/2011/11/20/can-the-quantum-state-be-interpreted-statistically/.

  • Lewis, D. (1994). Humean supervenience debugged. Mind, 103(412), 473–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, P. (2007a). Empty waves in Bohmian quantum mechanics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58(4), 787–803.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, P. (2007b). How Bohm’s theory solves the measurement problem. Philosophy of Science, 74, 749–760.

  • Loewer, B. (1996). Humean supervenience. Philosophical Topics, 24, 101–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2013). The nature of the quantum state. In A. Ney & D. Albert (Eds.), The wave function: Essays on the metaphysics of quantum mechanics (pp. 126–153). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mauro, D. (2002). Topics in Koopman–von Neumann theory. PhD thesis, Università degli Studi di Trieste. arXiv:quant-ph/0301172 [quant-ph].

  • Miller, E. (2013). Quantum entanglement, bohmian mechanics, and humean supervenience. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 92, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ney, A., & Albert, D. (2013). The wave function: Essays on the metaphysics of quantum mechanics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Norsen, T. (2010). The theory of exclusively local beables. Foundations of Physics, 40, 1858.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poirier, W. (2010). Bohmian mechanics without pilot waves. In B. Poirier (Eds.), Dynamics of molecular systems, from quantum to classical dynamics. Chemical Physics, 370(1–3), 4–14.

  • Pusey, M., Barrett, J., & Rudolph, T. (2012). On the reality of the quantum state. Nature Physics, 8, 475–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, N. (1964). The relation between classical and quantum mechanics. American Journal of Physics, 32, 597–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiller, R. (1962). Quasi-classical theory of the non-spinning electron. Physical Review, 125, 1100–1108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schleich, W. P., Greenberger, D. M., Kobe, D. H., & Scully, M. O. (2013). Schrödinger equation revisited. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 110(14), 5374–5379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smolin, L. (2013). Time reborn. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Squires, E. (1994). Some comments on the de Broglie–Bohm picture by an admiring spectator. In A. van der Merwe & A. Garuccio (Eds.), Waves and particles in light and matter. New York: Plenum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valentini, A. (2012). De Broglie–Bohm pilot-wave theory: Many worlds in denial? In S. W. Saunders, et al. (Eds.), Many worlds? Everett, quantum theory and reality (pp. 476–509). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, J. (1932). Zur Operatorenmethode In Der Klassischen Mechanik. Annals of Mathematics, 33(3), 587–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (2008). Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics. In D. Rickles (Ed.), The Ashgate companion to contemporary philosophy of physics. Aldershot: Ashgate Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zeh, H. D. (1999). Why Bohm’s quantum theory? Foundations of Physics Letters, 12, 197–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Craig Callender.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Callender, C. One world, one beable. Synthese 192, 3153–3177 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0582-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0582-3

Keywords

Navigation