Skip to main content
Log in

Eliminating life worth living’

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article argues for the elimination of the concept of life worth living from philosophical vocabulary on three complementary grounds. First, the basic components of this concept suffer from multiple ambiguities, which hamper attempts to ground informative evaluative and classificatory judgments about the worth of life. Second, the criteria proposed to track the extension of the concept of life worth living rest on unsupported axiological assumptions and fail to identify precise and plausible referents for this concept. And third, the concept of life worth living is not shown to serve any major evaluative or classificatory purpose besides those served by already available axiological concepts. By eliminating the concept of life worth living, philosophers will free themselves of the task of addressing ill-posed axiological questions and ground reflection about the worth of life on more rigorous conceptual foundations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Below I focus on lives taken as a whole (from birth to death) rather than lives in specific contexts or at a given moment, without taking a position on metaphysical issues such as the hypothetical existence of an afterlife. In particular, I use the term ‘life’ to indicate the life of a human person (as opposed to non-human animals, extraterrestrial organisms, etc.) because most debates about LWL focus on human persons’ lives. In doing so, I gloss over the debate concerning what conditions a life has to satisfy to be regarded as the life of a human person (see e.g. Finnis 1989; Gormally 1993), since my call to eliminate LWL does not directly rest on what position one advocates about such conditions.

  2. I employ the expression ‘proponents of LWL’ broadly to indicate both occasional users of LWL and those who deem LWL judgments to be meaningful and informative, where the expression ‘LWL judgments’ designates claims stating that specific lives (or lives in particular conditions) are (or are not) worth living. I expand in later sections on the conceptual and epistemic differences between various types of LWL judgments (see e.g. Sect. 4.4 on comparative and absolute LWL judgments).

  3. The three ambiguities I examine in this section highlight both definitional disagreements concerning the concept of LWL and substantive disagreements concerning what facts putatively determine whether specific lives are worth living. These two types of disagreements are often intertwined, but are conceptually distinct (see e.g. footnote no. 5). I discuss both types of disagreements since my critical evaluation targets not just the concept of LWL, but also LWL judgments.

  4. I speak of ‘goods’ and ‘experiences’ broadly to encompass the events and the states of affairs corresponding to persons’ obtaining such goods and living such experiences. Also, I focus primarily on the concept of life worth living rather than the concept of life worth continuing, i.e. a life whose remaining period is worth living (see e.g. Benatar 2006, ch. 2; Smuts 2013). The alleged fact that a person’s life is not worth continuing after a specific time does not imply that such life on the whole is not worth living for this person (as a putative example, think of a person who lives ninety years of amazing bliss and achievements but faces a final week of unbearable pain and loneliness). Conversely, the past period in a person’s life may conceivably include so much physical and psychological suffering that although the period ahead may be worth living, this person’s life may fail to be worth living on the whole.

  5. LWL judgments may vary remarkably also depending on whether one asks the persons whose lives are evaluated or some other persons. To give one example, LWL judgments about the lives of persons with disabilities frequently vary depending on whether one asks the persons whose lives are evaluated, healthcare providers or the general public (see e.g. Wilkinson 2006). Indeed, these variations occur not just interpersonally but also intertemporally for the same persons (see e.g. Kon 2008, on how various persons’ LWL judgments vary before and after these persons have to cope with a disability). These variations often make LWL judgments controversial, but do not directly reflect ambiguities inherent in the LWL concept itself.

  6. In this section, I examine the most prominent criteria proposed to track the extension of LWL, individually taken (for other critical evaluations of some criteria, see e.g. Baier 1988; Blumenfeld 2009; Smuts 2013). I lack the space here to consider hypothetical combinations of distinct criteria. For my purposes, it suffices to note that no detailed combinations of criteria have been developed, and that the profound tensions between distinct sets of criteria (see e.g. Sect. 2 on subjectivist versus objectivist criteria) hinder the development of such combinations.

  7. The quote in the text is not meant to imply that Singer endorses subjectivist criteria such as the Desire Criterion (see e.g. Sect. 3.2 on Singer’s claims in favour of objectivist criteria such as the Quality of Life Criterion). In this section, I use the term ‘desire’ broadly to cover a variety of pro-attitudes, including wishes, wants and intentions. I take my critique of the Desire Criterion to hold mutatis mutandis also for the Belief Criterion, according to which a person’s life is worth living iff this person believes that her life is worth living (see e.g. James 1912, 62), and the Resentment Criterion, which holds that a person’s life is worth living iff this person does not resent being born (see e.g. Smilansky 1997; Williams 1995, for discussion).

  8. The criterion assumes that the involved person would not remember her former life when repeating it, since remembering such life would prevent this person from re-living a qualitatively identical life.

  9. Even less plausible is the Nietzschean Eternal Recurrence Criterion, according to which a person’s life is worth living iff this person would prefer to live a qualitatively identical life over and over again for infinitely many times rather than never to exist. Indeed, it is questionable whether anyone’s life could be plausibly categorized as worth living under the extremely demanding evaluative standard imposed by such criterion (see e.g. Trisel 2007).

  10. The criterion assumes that the caretaker is benevolent to rule out cases where the caretaker regards a person merely as a means to achieve some of the caretaker’s own ends without taking this person’s good or interests into account.

  11. A proponent of LWL might hold that the Ideal Caretaker Criterion helps us to develop a theory of what makes life worth living by providing an epistemic indicator of when worth obtains (see e.g. Smuts 2013, 442 and 459). Even so, it is hard to see how exactly the criterion is supposed to serve this purpose. For the criterion provides no informative insight as to how all facts that putatively determine whether a person’s life is worth living combine to determine whether such life is worth living.

  12. One might object that the worth of a state of non-existence is zero (see e.g. Feldman 1991). Yet, it seems more plausible to hold that non-existence has no determinate worth, and having no determinate worth is not the same as having a determinate worth of zero (see e.g. Broome 1993). One might further object that LWL judgments refer to a state of nothingness (rather than non-existence) and that nothingness constitutes a well-defined state of affairs. The idea would be that “if a certain kind of life is [worth living], it is better than nothing. If it is [not worth living], it is worse than nothing” (Parfit 1984, 487). However, even assuming that nothingness constitutes a well-defined state of affairs, it is dubious that the worth of a state of nothingness can be meaningfully ascribed a determinate worth (see e.g. Fumagalli 2012).

References

  • Archard, D. (2004). Wrongful life. Philosophy, 79, 403–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arneson, R. J. (1999). Human flourishing versus desire satisfaction. Social Philosophy and Policy, 16, 113–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. (1997). Intrinsic value and moral obligation. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 35, 135–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. (2003). Intrinsic value and reasons for action. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 41, 30–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. (2005). Intrinsic value and meaningful life. Philosophical Papers, 34, 331–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A. J. (1990). The meaning of life. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baier, K. (1988). Threats of futility: Is life worth living? Free Inquiry, 8, 47–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, R. (2002). The sanctity of human life and its protection. Lanham: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benatar, D. (2006). Better never to have been: The harm of coming into existence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Blaser, A. (2013). Lives worth living: The great fight for disability rights. New Political Science, 35, 538–541.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blumenfeld, D. (2009). Living life over again. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79, 357–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, B. (2002). Is intrinsic value conditional? Philosophical Studies, 107, 23–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brock, D. (1993). Life and death: Philosophical essays in biomedical ethics. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (1993). Goodness is reducible to betterness: The evil of death is the value of life. In P. Koslowski & Y. Shionoya (Eds.), The good and the economical. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2004). Weighing lives. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2005). Should we value population? Journal of Political Philosophy, 13, 399–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2008). What is your life worth? Daedalus, 137, 49–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camus, A. (1955). The myth of Sisyphus and other essays. Trans. Justin O’Brien. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig, W. (2000). The absurdity of life without god. In E. Klemke (Ed.), The meaning of life (2nd ed., chap. 4). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Graaf, G., Buckley, F., & Skotko, B. (2015). Estimates of the live births, natural losses, and elective terminations with down syndrome in the United States. American Journal of Medical Genetics, 167A, 756–767.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farsides, B., & Dunlop, R. (2001). Measuring quality of life: Is there such a thing as a life not worth living? British Medical Journal, 322, 1481–1483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, F. (1991). Some puzzles about the evil of death. Philosophical Review, 50, 205–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, F. (1995). Justice, desert, and the repugnant conclusion. Utilitas, 7, 189–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferejohn, M. (2013). Formal causes. Definition, explanation, and primacy in Socratic and Aristotelian thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Finnis, J. (1989). Persons and their associations. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 63, 267–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis, J. (1993). The “value of human life” and “the right to death”: Some reflections on Cruzan and Ronald Dworkin. Southern Illinois University Law Journal, 17, 559–571.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis, J. (1997a). A philosophical case against euthanasia. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical and legal perspectives (pp. 23–35). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis, J. (1997b). The fragile case for euthanasia: A reply to John Harris. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical and legal perspectives (pp. 46–55). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fumagalli, R. (2012). On the alleged insignificance of the primordial existential question. Studia Leibnitiana, 44, 212–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fumagalli, R. (2013). The futile search for true utility. Economics and Philosophy, 29, 325–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fumagalli, R. (2016). Decision sciences and the new case for Paternalism: Three welfare-related justificatory challenges. Social Choice and Welfare, 47, 459–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallie, W. B. (1955). Essentially contested concepts. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56, 167–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garrard, E., & Wilkinson, S. (2006). Selecting disability and the welfare of the child. Monist, 89, 482–504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gormally, L. (1993). Definitions of personhood. Catholic medical quarterly, 44, 7–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grill, K. (2016). Asymmetric population axiology: Deliberative neutrality delivered. Philosophical Studies, 174, 219–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harries, K. (1991). Questioning the question of the worth of life. The Journal of Philosophy, 88, 684–690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. (1985). The value of life. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. (1997a). Euthanasia and the value of life. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical and legal perspectives (pp. 6–22). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. (1997b). The philosophical case against the philosophical case against euthanasia. In J. Keown (Ed.), Euthanasia examined: Ethical, clinical and legal perspectives (pp. 36–45). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyd, D. (1983). Is life worth reliving? Mind, 92, 21–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1947) [1779]. Dialogues concerning natural religion. New York: Smith.

  • Hurka, T. (1993). Perfectionism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, T. (1998). Two kinds of organic unity. The Journal of Ethics, 2, 299–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1895). Is life worth living? International Journal of Ethics, 6, 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1912). The will to believe and other essays in popular philosophy. New York: Longmans, Green and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (1992). The limits of well-being. Social Philosophy and Policy, 9, 169–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (1994). Me and my life. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 94, 309–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (1998). Rethinking intrinsic value. The Journal of Ethics, 2, 277–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, M. (1978). What is a life worth? Ethics, 89, 58–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kass, L. (2008). Defending human dignity. In Human dignity and bioethics (pp. 297–332). Washington, DC: President’s Council on Bioethics.

  • Kavka, G. S. (1982). The paradox of future individuals. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 11, 93–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, H. (2013). The uncomfortable truth about wrongful life cases. Philosophical Studies, 164, 623–641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kon, A. (2007). Neonatal euthanasia is unsupportable: The Groningen protocol should be abandoned. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 28, 453–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kon, A. (2008). We cannot accurately predict the extent of an infant’s future suffering: The Groningen Protocol is too dangerous to support. American Journal of Bioethics, 8, 27–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (1983). Two distinctions in goodness. Philosophical review, 92, 169–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhse, H. (1987). The sanctity of life doctrine in medicine: A critique. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhse, H. (1992). Quality of life and the death of ‘Baby M’. Bioethics, 6, 233–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhse, H., & Singer, P. (1985). Should the baby live? The problem of handicapped infants. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kymlicka, W. (1990). Contemporary political philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, J. (2004). Intrinsic value and the notion of a life. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 62, 319–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lulé, D., Zickler, C., Häcker, S., Bruno, M., Demertzi, A., Pellas, F., Laureys, S., & Kübler, A. (2009). Life can be worth living in locked-in syndrome. Progress in Brain Research, 177, 339–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mallon, R., Machery, E., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2009). Against arguments from reference. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79, 332–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCormick, R. (1974). To save or let die. The dilemma of modern medicine. Journal of the American Medical Association, 229, 172–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDermott, J. (1991). Why bother: Is life worth living? The Journal of Philosophy, 88, 677–683.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. (1981). Problems of population policy. Ethics, 92, 96–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. (1988). Death and the value of life. Ethics, 99, 32–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. (1995). The metaphysics of brain death. Bioethics, 9, 91–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. (1998). Wrongful life: Paradoxes in the morality of causing people to exist. In J. Coleman, C. Morris, & G. Kavka (Eds.), Rational commitment and social justice: Essays for Gregory Kavka (pp. 208–248). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. (2013). Causing people to exist and saving people’s lives. The Journal of Ethics, 17, 5–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2000). Could God’s purpose be the source of life’s meaning? Religious Studies, 36, 293–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2001). The concept of a meaningful life. American Philosophical Quarterly, 38, 137–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2002). Recent work on the meaning of life. Ethics, 112, 781–814.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2011). The good, the true and the beautiful: Toward a unified account of great meaning in life. Religious Studies, 47, 389–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2012). The meaningful and the worthwhile: Clarifying the relationships. Philosophical Forum, 43, 435–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2013). Meaning in life: An analytic study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2014). Life worth living. In A.C. Michalos (Ed.), Encyclopedia of quality of life and well-being research (pp. 3602–3605).

  • Metz, T. (2016). Is life’s meaning ultimately unthinkable? Guy Bennett-Hunter on the ineffable. Philosophia, 44, 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moorhead, H. (1988). The meaning of life. Chicago: Chicago Review Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. 1979. Death. In Mortal questions (chap. 1). Cambridge University Press.

  • Narveson, J. (1967). Utilitarianism and new generations. Mind, 76, 62–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Narveson, J. (1973). Moral problems of population. The Monist, 57, 62–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Natoli, J., Ackerman, D., McDermott, S., & Edwards, J. (2012). Prenatal diagnosis of down syndrome: A systematic review of termination rates (19952011). Prenatal Diagnosis, 32, 142–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nehamas, A. (2007). Only in the contemplation of beauty is human life worth living. European Journal of Philosophy, 15, 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1982). Future generations: Further problems. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 11, 113–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partridge, E. (1981). Posthumous interests and posthumous respect. Ethics, 91, 243–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paterson, C. (2003). A life not worth living? Studies in Christian Ethics, 16, 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrino, E. (2008). The lived experience of human dignity. In Human dignity and bioethics (pp. 513–540). Washington, DC: President’s Council on Bioethics.

  • Rachels, J. (1986). The end of life. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richman, R. J. (1962). Something common. The Journal of Philosophy, 59, 821–830.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosch, E., & Mervis, C. (1975). Family resemblances: Studies in the internal structure of categories. Cognitive Psychology, 7, 573–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, W. (1962). The fallacy of composition. Mind, 71, 87–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1913). On the notion of cause. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 13, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, A. (1969). The world as will and representation (Vol. 1). New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, M. A. (1969). When is a resemblance a family resemblance? Mind, 78, 408–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1993). Practical ethics (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1995). Straw men with broken legs: A response to Per Sundström. Journal of Medical Ethics, 21, 89–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smilansky, S. (1997). Preferring not to have been born. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 75, 241–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, W. (1998). Our discardable people. Human life review, 24, 78–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smuts, A. (2013). Five tests for what makes a life worth living. Journal of Value Inquiry, 47, 439–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smuts, A. (2014). To be or never to have been: Anti-Natalism and a life worth living. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 17, 711–729.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smuts, A. (2016). A life worth living. Retrieved online in April 2016 at: http://philpapers.org/rec/SMUALW.

  • Steinbock, B., & McClamrock, R. (1994). When is birth unfair to the child? Hastings Center Report, 24, 15–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sumner, L. W. (1996). Welfare, happiness, and ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sundström, P. (1995). Peter Singer and ‘lives not worth living’—comments on a flawed argument from analogy. Journal of Medical Ethics, 21, 35–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trisel, B. A. (2007). Judging life and its value. Sorites, 18, 60–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, D. (2006). Is it in the best interests of an intellectually disabled infant to die? Journal of Medical Ethics, 32, 454–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, D. (2011). A life worth giving? The threshold for permissible withdrawal of life support from disabled newborn infants. The American Journal of Bioethics, 11, 20–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1981). Moral luck. In Moral luck (chap. 2). Cambridge University Press.

  • Williams, B. (1995). Resenting one’s own existence. In Making sense of humanity (chap. 19). Cambridge University Press.

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Anscombe, G.E. Trans. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1965) [1929]. Lecture on ethics. The Philosophical Review, 74, 3–12.

  • Wolf, S. (1997). Happiness and meaning: Two aspects of the good life. Social Philosophy and Policy, 14, 207–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Luc Bovens, John Broome, Susanne Burri, Jeff McMahan, Thaddeus Metz, Attila Tanyi, Alex Voorhoeve and an anonymous referee for their detailed comments on former versions of this paper. I also thank audiences at the University of Bayreuth and Duke University for their helpful and thought-provoking feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roberto Fumagalli.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fumagalli, R. Eliminating life worth living’. Philos Stud 175, 769–792 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0892-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0892-7

Keywords

Navigation