Skip to main content
Log in

Pluralizing Darwin: Making Counter-Factual History of Science Significant

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the wake of recent attempts at alternate history (Bowler 2013), this paper suggests several avenues for a pluralistic approach to Charles Darwin and his role in the history of evolutionary theory. We examine in what sense Darwin could be described as a major driver of theoretical change in the history of biology. First, this paper examines how Darwin influenced the future of biological science: not merely by stating the fact of evolution or by bringing evidence for it; but by discovering natural selection, and giving it pre-eminence over any other mechanism for evolution; and also by proposing a masterful and quite unique synthesis of many scientific fields. Contrasting Darwin’s views with those of A.R. Wallace, I conclude that “natural selection” is clearly an original contribution, that it had no forerunners or co-discoverers, and could barely have appeared after Darwin conceived of it. This specificity of Darwin’s contribution is an invitation to be strongly presentist (Loison 2016) and to adopt only weak counter-factuals. In contrast, there are possible ways to use strong counter-factuals as attempts to “pluralize” the history of biological theory: i.e. imagine new possible avenues for the development of evolutionary biology. The idea that evolution was a theory “in the air” suggests that evolutionary theory could have developed in a world without Darwin, especially if we accept to delete not only “Darwin” but “England”. France and Germany are examined as possible countries where evolutionary ideas would have thrived even with no contribution from the English scientists. Finally, the paper suggests another counter-factual hypothesis: deleting not Darwin and his Origin but the Darwin Industry itself. This may allow us to read the Origin of Species with fresh eyes and to discover Darwin’s life-long interest in variation and its laws, as many of his early readers did.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Beatty, J. (2006). Replaying life’s tape. Journal of Philosophy, 103–7, 336–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernard, C. (1865). Introduction à l’étude de la médecine expérimentale. Paris: Baillière.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bock, W. J. (2009). The Darwin-Wallace myth of 1858. Proceedings of the Zoological Society, 62–1, 1–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowler, P. J. (1983). The eclipse of Darwinism. London-Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowler, P. J. (1988). The non-Darwinian revolution: Reinterpreting a historical myth. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowler, P. J. (2013). Darwin deleted Imagining a world without Darwin. Chicago/London: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, R. (1844). Vestiges of the natural history of creation (10th ed., p. 1853). London: John Churchill.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2004). Inventing temperature: Measurement and scientific progress. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2012). Is water H20? Evidence, realism and pluralism. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, J. T. (1959). The philosophy of science and the history of science. In M. Clagett (Ed.), Critical problems in the history of science (pp. 103–140). Madison (WI): The University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conry, Y. (1974). L’introduction du darwinisme en France. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cope, E. D. (1887). The origin of the fittest. essays on evolution. New York: Appleton.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Corsi, P. (1978). The importance of French transformist ideas for the second volume of Lyell’s principles of geology. British Journal for the History of Science., 11(39), 221–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corsi, P. (1988a). Science and religion Baden Powell and the Anglican debate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corsi, P. (1988b). The age of Lamarck: evolutionary theories in France, 1790–1830. Berkeley: University of California Press. (Translated by Jonathan Mandelbaum).

    Google Scholar 

  • Corsi, Pietro (2017). “Systèmes de la nature” and theories of life. Bridging the eighteenth and the nineteenth centuries. Arcade. Literature, Humanities and the World. [online]

  • Darwin, C. (1859). On the origin of species by means of natural selection. London: Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1868). The variation of animals and plants under domestication. London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Desmond, A. (1984). Robert E. Grant : The social predicament of a pre-Darwinian transmutationist. Journal of the History of Biology, 17–2, 189–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dick, P. K. (1962). The man in the high castle. New York: Putnam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eiseley, Loren. (1959). Darwin’s century evolution and the men who discovered it. London: V. Gollancz.

  • Gayon, Jean. (2009). Darwin et Wallace: un débat constitutif pour la théorie de l’évolution par sélection naturelle. In L’évolution aujourdhui à la croisée de la biologie et des sciences humaines. Actes du colloque des 29, 30 et 31 janvier 2009 à l’Académie royale de Belgique. Bruxelles: Académie royale de Belgique, pp. 89–122.

  • Gayon, J. (1998). Darwinism’s struggle for survival heredity and the hypothesis of natural selection. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Translation Matthew Cobb).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gliboff, S. (2008). H.G. Bronn, Ernst Haeckel and the origins of German Darwinism: A study in translation and transformation. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glick, T. F. (1974). The comparative reception of Darwinism. Austin: University of Texas Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1989). Wonderful life: the Burgess shale and the nature of history. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, M. J. S. (1977). The structure and strategy of Darwin’s ‘long argument.’ British Journal for the History of Science, 10, 237–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, M. J. S. (2009). Capitalist contexts for Darwinian theory: Land, finance, industry and empire. Journal of the History of Biology, 42, 399–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoquet, T. (2010). Spectres de Telliamed: Maillet dans l’histoire de l’évolution. Corpus, Revue de Philosophie, 59, 153–186.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoquet, T. (2013). Translating natural selection: True concept, but false term? In H. Fangerau et al., Classification and evolution in biology, linguistics and the history of science (pp. 67–95). Stuttgart: Steiner.

  • Hoquet, T., & Levandowsky, M. (2015). Utility vs Beauty: Darwin, Wallace and the subsequent history of the debate on sexual selection. Current perspectives on sexual selection (pp. 19–44). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1973). Darwin and his critics: The reception of Darwin’s theory of evolution by the scientific community. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, J. (1942). Evolution: The modern synthesis. London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, T. H. (1893). Darwiniana, in collected essays. London: Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, C. N. (2007). The preface to Darwin’s origin of species: The curious history of the historical Sketch. Journal of the History of Biology, 40, 529–556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joravsky, D. (1959). Soviet marxism and biology before lysenko. Journal of the History of Ideas, 20–1, 85–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kellert, S. H., Longino, H. E., & Kenneth Waters, C. (Eds.). (2006). Scientific pluralism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lefèvre, W. (2009). Die Entstehung der biologischen Evolutionstheorie. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lightman, B. (Ed.). (2016). Global spencerism: The communication and appropriation of a British evolutionist. Leiden and Boston: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loison, L. (2010a). La statue de Lamarck. Cahiers François Viète, 2(2), 15–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loison, L. (2010b). Qu’est-ce que le néolamarckisme? Les biologistes français et la question de l’évolution des espèces, 1870–1940. Paris: Vuibert.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loison, L. (2016). Forms of presentism in the history of science. rethinking the project of historical epistemology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 60, 29–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (Ed.). (1966). On the origin of species: A fac-simile of the first edition [1859], with an introduction by Ernst Mayr. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pancaldi, G. (1991). Darwin in Italy: science across cultural frontiers. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Provine, W. B. (1971). The origins of theoretical population genetics. Chicago-London: The University of Chicago press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radick, G. (2008). Why what if? Isis, 99, 547–551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radick, G. (2009). Is the theory of natural selection independent of its history? The cambridge companion to Darwin (2nd ed., pp. 147–172). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Raf, D. B. (2007). A serpent without teeth. The conservative transformism of Jean-Baptiste d’Omalius d’Halloy (1783–1875). Centaurus, 49, 114–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. J. (2002). The romantic conception of Life: Science and philosophy in the age of Goethe. Chicago-London: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, K. (1968). Pavane. Doubleday: Garden City, N.Y.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1979). The Darwinian revolution. science red in tooth and claw. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1996). Monad to man: The concept of progress in evolutionary biology. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (2005). Was there a Darwinian revolution? Annals of the History and Philosophy of Biology, 10, 173–187.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (2009). The Darwinian revolution: Rethinking its meaning and significance. PNAS, 106(Supplement 1), 10040–10047.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Secord, J. A. (2000). Victorian sensation: The extraordinary publication, reception, and secret authorship of vestiges of the natural history of creation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Seidlitz, G. (1871). Die Darwins’che Theorie, elf Vorlesungen über die Entstehung der Thiere und Pflanzen durch Naturzüchtung. Dorpat: E. Mattiese.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (1982). Why Lamarck did not discover the principle of natural selection. Journal of the History of Biology, 15–3, 443–465.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, H. (1891). Essays: Scientific, political, and speculative. London-Edinburgh: Williams & Norgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Todes, D. P. (1989). Darwin without Malthus: The struggle for existence in Russian evolutionary thought. Oxford-New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S., & Goodfield, J. (1965). The discovery of time. London: Hutchinson and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, D. D. (2011). Gould’s replay revisited. Biology and Philosophy, 26, 65–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vuillemin, J. (1984). Nécessité ou contingence. L’aporie de Diodore et les systèmes philosophiques. Paris: Minuit et Fondation Singer-Polignac.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, R. (1985). Darwin’s metaphor: Nature’s place in Victorian culture. Cambridge: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I want to thank two anonymous reviewers and the editors of this special issue. This research was funded by the Institut de recherches philosophiques (IRePh) at Paris Nanterre University, France.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thierry Hoquet.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hoquet, T. Pluralizing Darwin: Making Counter-Factual History of Science Significant. J Gen Philos Sci 52, 115–134 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-020-09528-0

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-020-09528-0

Keywords

Navigation