Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Precision Livestock Farming and Farmers’ Duties to Livestock

  • Articles
  • Published:
Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Precision livestock farming (PLF) promises to allow modern, large-scale farms to replicate, at scale, caring farmers who know their animals. PLF refers to a suite of technologies, some only speculative. The goal is to use networked devices to continuously monitor individual animals on large farms, to compare this information to expected norms, and to use algorithms to manage individual animals (e.g. via changes in climate, feeding, or reproductive decisions) automatically. Supporters say this could not only create an artificial version of the partially mythologized image of the good steward caring for his or her animals, but to also improve on it. As one paper in favor of PLF has said, “We can not only replace the farmer’s ‘eyes and ears’ to each individual animal as in the past, but several other variables (infections, physiological variables, stress, etc.) will soon be measurable in practice” (Berckmans, in: Geers, Madec (eds) Livestock production and society, Wageningen Academic Publishers, Wageningen, pp 287–292, 2006). Yet these methods of monitoring and control raise a host of ethical issues, including alienation of laborers, further consolidation of farms, and further cover for meat consumption (a possibly independent ethical problem depending on one’s views of eating meat). In this paper, I will address these ethical issues, and suggest a different, under-examined concern: namely, that though PLF may indeed improve the lives of livestock, and the sustainability of livestock operations, it is possible that it will do so at the cost of a loss of identity and relationships for farmers, as well as for the animals in their charge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this paper, I will focus on livestock farming. There are other kinds of precision farming, but the arguments for how that technology, plants, and farmers interact are different from how PLF, livestock, and farmers do.

  2. Except when drawing a distinction between humans and other animals, I will mostly refer to non-human animals in this paper as “animals,” or even “livestock,” but this is for ease of reading and to maintain congruity with the literature, rather than a reflection of some metaphysical commitment. Though it reads better, it is worth being aware of, and acknowledging, the category error in contrasting humans and animals.

  3. For some examples of PLF in practice, see Berckmans (2014) and Vranken and Berckmans (2017).

  4. For a sample of this debate see Sagoff (1984); but compare Varner (1998).

  5. For a discussion of the different conceptions of animal welfare, see Thompson (2015, 137–142).

  6. For discussions of this problem particularly looking at PLF, see Wathes et al. (2008) and Lehr (2014).

  7. For an early discussion of this extensive discourse, see Heffernan (1972).

  8. For different perspectives on this question, see Cole (2011), Haynes (2012) and Thompson (2015, 130–158).

  9. The case of our responsibilities toward wild animals is more vexed, and beyond the scope of this paper. For a look at it within this framework, see Palmer (2007, 2010)).

  10. Note that this is true regardless of whether one thinks those animals should have been brought into existence in the first place.

  11. Note that this responsibility on the part of farmers could be justified by animals possessing particular rights, or it could be justified by non-rights-based welfare considerations such as some inherent value of the animals, an inherent disvalue of pain, etc. It could also be partly justified by various virtues we want farmers to have, such as careful stewardship. One advantage of this framework, in fact, is its flexibility or over-determination of justification.

  12. One may well wonder at this point—do farmers almost invariably fail in their duties in this analogy because they send their charges off to be slaughtered? Relatedly, do farmers almost invariably fail in their duties in this analogy because they conceive of these animals as “livestock”? Presumably we would think that parents or pet owners were wildly derelict in their responsibilities if they needlessly sent their charges off to be killed and thought of them in these terms. I am quite sympathetic to this line of argument, though there are those such as Portman (2017) who explores farmer responsibility toward animals in the presence of their possession and incorporation. A full exploration of whether these responsibilities require veganism or vegetarianism is beyond the scope of this paper; instead, if the farmer/parent or farmer/pet owner analogy holds, one should say that farmers at least have responsibilities of care to their animals while those animals are alive.

  13. For a discussion with a different emphasis, but which shares the worry here of a potential distortion of animal welfare via PLF, see Wathes et al. (2008).

  14. See Jensen (2004) for a discussion of the phenomenon of denying our communication with other animals and our intuitive opinions about their mental states.

  15. For some background on tacit knowledge and the difficulty of maintaining it through technocratic innovation, (see, e.g., Bresnen et al. 2003; Gertler 2003; Polanyi 1966).

  16. One way to understand the harm of not listening to animals, over and above the ways in which it may directly reduce their welfare, would be to see it as a kind of “epistemic violence” in silencing them. If silencing is defined as refusing to take up the testimony of others by reliably ignoring them as a source of testimony, it is surely the case that, as Dotson (2011) points out, this ignorance is sometimes justified, as when a three-year-old is not allowed to vote. Sometimes our ignoring non-human animals as speakers is justified in this way. However, the analysis of whether ignoring is pernicious requires context-sensitive understandings of power relationships and harms (ibid.). When we do not listen to animals expressing dissatisfaction or pain because it would be inconvenient to respond to it, it is difficult to see this as anything other than epistemic violence.

  17. They presumably still keep their individual identity as recognized by their conspecifics, though in considering that question, it is worth thinking about the loss of individuality those animals experience when in much larger groups than they would maintain if left to their own devices.

References

  • Berckmans, D. (2006). Automatic on-line monitoring of animals by precision livestock farming. In R. Geers & F. Madec (Eds.), Livestock production and society (pp. 287–292). Wageningen: Wageningen Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berckmans, D. (2014). Precision livestock farming technologies for welfare management in intensive livestock systems. Scientific and Technical Review of the Office International des Epizooties, 33(1), 189–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berckmans, D. (2017). General introduction to precision livestock farming. Animal Frontiers, 7(1), 6–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bresnen, M., Edelman, L., Newell, S., Scarbrough, H., & Swan, J. (2003). Social practices and the management of knowledge in project environments. International Journal of Project Management, 21(3), 157–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burgess-Jackson, K. (1998). Doing right by our animal companions. The Journal of Ethics, 2(2), 159–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • CEMA-AGRI.org. (n.d.) Precision Livestock Farming, http://www.cema-agri.org/page/5-precision-livestock-farming. Accessed December 10, 2017.

  • Cole, M. (2011). From “animal machines” to “happy meat”? Foucault’s ideas of disciplinary and pastoral power applied to ‘animal-centred’ welfare discourse. Animals, 1(1), 83–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dotson, K. (2011). Tracking epistemic violence, tracking practices of silencing. Hypatia, 26(2), 236–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farm Animal Welfare Committee (FAWC). (2016). Sustainable agriculture and farm animal welfare. Special Report by the Farm Animal Welfare Committee, Department for Environment, Food and Rural Affairs (Defra) UK, London.

  • Francis, L. P., & Norman, R. (1978). Some animals are more equal than others. Philosophy, 53(206), 507–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frost, A. R., Parsons, D. J., Stacey, K. F., Robertson, A. P., Welch, S. K., Filmer, D., et al. (2003). Progress towards the development of an integrated management system for broiler chicken production. Computers and Electronics in Agriculture, 39(3), 227–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gertler, M. S. (2003). Tacit knowledge and the economic geography of context, or the undefinable tacitness of being (there). Journal of Economic Geography, 3(1), 75–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. (1985). Protecting the vulnerable. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harlow, H. F., & Zimmerman, R. R. (1959). Affectional responses in the infant monkey. Science, 130(3373), 421–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haynes, R. P. (2012). The myth of happy meat. In D. Kaplan (Ed.), The philosophy of food (pp. 161–168). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heffernan, W. D. (1972). Sociological dimensions of agricultural structures in the United States. Sociologia Ruralis, 12(2), 481–499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, D. (2004). A language older than words. White River Junction, VT: Chelsea Green Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehr, H. (2014). Recent advances in precision livestock farming. International Animal Health Journal, 2(1), 44–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCune, J. C. (1998). The technology treadmill. Management Review, 87(11), 10–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munksgaard, L., Depasille, A. M., Rushen, J., Herskin, M. S., & Kristensen, A. M. (2001). Dairy cows’ fear of people: Social learning, milk yield and behaviour at milking. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 73(1), 15–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nowak, P. (1997). A sociological analysis of site-specific management. In F. J. Pierce & E. J. Sadler (Eds.), The State of Site-Specific Management for Agriculture (pp. 397–422). Madison: American Society of Agronomy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, C. (2007). Rethinking animal ethics in appropriate context: How Rolston’s work can help. In C. J. Preston & W. Ouderkirk (Eds.), Nature, value, duty. The international library of environmental, agricultural and food ethics (Vol. 8, pp. 183–201). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, C. (2010). Animal ethics in context. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1966). The tacit dimension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pomar, C., Hauschild, L., Zhang, G. H., Pomar, J., & Lovatto, P. A. (2009). Applying precision feeding techniques in growing-finishing pig operations. Revista Brasileira de Zootecnia, 38, 226–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pomar, C., Hauschild, L., Zhang, G. H., Pomar, J., & Lovatto, P. A. (2011). Precision feeding can significantly reduce feeding cost and nutrient excretion in growing animals. In D. Sauvant, J. van Milgen, P. Faverdin, & N. Friggens (Eds.), Modelling nutrient digestion and utilisation in farm animals (pp. 327–334). Wageningen: Wageningen Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Portman, A. (2017). Agriculture, equality, and the problem of incorporation. In I. Werkheiser & Z. Piso (Eds.), Food justice in US and global contexts: bringing theory and practice together. The international library of environmental, agricultural, and food ethics (Vol. 24, pp. 267–283). Cham: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Röling, N. (2009). Pathways for impact: scientists’ different perspectives on agricultural innovation. International Journal of Agricultural Sustainability, 7(2), 83–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sagoff, M. (1984). Animal liberation and environmental ethics: Bad marriage, quick divorce. Osgoode Hall Law Journal, 22(2), 297–307.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stuart, D., Schewe, R. L., & Gunderson, R. (2013). Extending social theory to farm animals: Addressing alienation in the dairy sector. Sociologia Ruralis, 53(2), 201–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suarez, S. D., & Gallup, G. G. (1982). Open-field behavior in chickens: The experimenter is a predator. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 96(3), 432–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. B. (1988). Ethical dilemmas in agriculture: The need for recognition and resolution. Agriculture and Human Values, 5(4), 4–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. B. (2010). The agrarian vision: Sustainability and environmental ethics. Lexington: University of Kentucky Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. B. (2015). From field to fork: Food ethics for everyone. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. B. (2017). The spirit of the soil: Agriculture and environmental ethics. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varner, G. E. (1998). In nature’s interests? Interests, animal rights, and environmental ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vranken, E., & Berckmans, D. (2017). Precision livestock farming for pigs. Animal Frontiers, 7(1), 32–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waiblinger, S., Menke, C., Korff, J., & Bucher, A. (2004). Previous handling and gentle interactions affect behaviour and heart rate of dairy cows during a veterinary procedure. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 85(1), 31–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wathes, C. M., Kristensen, H. H., Aerts, J. M., & Berckmans, D. (2008). Is precision livestock farming an engineer’s daydream or nightmare, an animal’s friend or foe, and a farmer’s panacea or pitfall? Computers and Electronics in Agriculture, 64(1), 2–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ian Werkheiser.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Werkheiser, I. Precision Livestock Farming and Farmers’ Duties to Livestock. J Agric Environ Ethics 31, 181–195 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-018-9720-0

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-018-9720-0

Keywords

Navigation