Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Interdependence, Human Rights and Global Health Law

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Health Care Analysis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The connection between health and human rights continues to play a prominent role within global health law. In particular, a number of theorists rely on the claim that there is a relation of interdependence between health and human rights. The nature and extent of this relation, however, is rarely defined, developed or defended in a conceptually robust way. This paper seeks to explore the source, scope and strength of this putative relation and what role it might play in developing a global health law framework.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Sen [14].

  2. Gostin [5, 243ff.]. Gostin has a long association with the health and human rights movement, including being second author on the seminal article outlining and introducing the health and human rights approach in the launch of the eponymously named journal: Mann et al. [9].

  3. Mann et al. [11, 6].

  4. According to Mann et al. [11, 9]: ‘‘… the modern concept of health includes yet goes beyond health care to embrace the broader societal dimensions and context of individual and population well-being’’.

  5. It is also worth noting that one should not conflate the ideas of indivisibility and interdependence. Both the indivisibility and interdependence of human rights are often proclaimed together. For some theorists, such as Shue [15], the interdependence of human rights entails their indivisibility. Nickel [13] claims that indivisibility is a very strong form of interdependence. I shall not say anything here on the idea of indivisibility itself, nor the relation between indivisibility and interdependence. However, since many health and human rights theorists make claims about the indivisibility of human rights in their arguments, there are also implications for their view given how we should understand the idea of indivisibility.

  6. The term interdependence is also used by theorists in the areas of international relations and economics to describe the idea that there is a mutual dependency or responsibility between nations or international institutions, especially in the area of wealth and globalisation. This idea of interdependence is different from the one analysed here.

  7. See for instance, Mann [10, 445], Brundtland [1], Gruskin et al. [8, xiii], Gruskin and Tarantola [7], Iacopino [9].

  8. Mann et al. [12, 1].

  9. It does seem peculiar that, at least in the health and human rights literature I have read, the possibility of the relation of interdependence as one of sufficiency is not considered. On such an understanding, while the promotion of one of the relata could be sufficient for the promotion of the other, it need not always be the case. Moreover, since health and human rights theorists do not seem to take into the account the possibility of interdependence involving a relation of sufficiency, they also do not take into account the even stronger possibility that the relation between human rights and health might be both necessary and sufficient.

  10. See for instance, Gruskin and Tarantola [7]: “… respecting, protecting and fulfilling human rights as a necessary prerequisite for the health of individuals and populations’’. Also cf. Gruskin and Tarantola [7] and Mann et al. [12, 12, 13].

  11. For more on the infringement/violation distinction, see Thomson [16, 51] and [17, 122].

  12. See for instance, Gewirth [4]

  13. Gruskin et al. [8, xvi]: ‘‘… respect, protection and fulfillment of all human rights… is necessary primarily because they are critical to improving the health status of individuals and populations’’.

  14. Gruskin and Tarantola [7, 5, 28, 39].

  15. For understanding the distinction between the relation of interdependence being bi-directional or bi-conditional as being a matter of the relation being useful versus indispensable, see Nickel [13].

  16. See, for instance, Mann et al. [12, 19ff.]. Moreover, if it is the case that health and human rights theorists understand the relation of interdependence to have the characteristics of being, for example, necessary or correlative, then this would only strengthen the view that we should understand the relation as a bi-conditional.

  17. Similarly, according to the rule of bi-conditional elimination, one can infer a conditional from a bi-conditional: if (A ↔ B) is true, then one may infer one direction of the bi-conditional, (A → B) and (B → A). Thus, if it is true that Human Rights ↔ Health, we will not be able to deny that either direction of the relation: Human Rights → Health or Health → Human Rights.

  18. Here also cf. Cohen [2].

  19. Gruskin and Tarantola [7, 41].

  20. See Nickel [13].

  21. Cf. Easley et al. [3].

References

  1. Brundtland, G. H. (2005). The UDHR: Fifty years of synergy between health and human rights. In S. Gruskin, M. A. Grodin, G. J. Annas, & S. P. Marks (Eds.), Perspectives on health and human rights (pp. 62–65). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Cohen, J. (2004). Minimalism about human rights: The most we can hope for? Journal of Political Philosophy, 12, 190–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Easley, C. E., Marks, S. P., & Morgan, R. E. (2001). The challenge and place of international human rights in public health. American Journal of Public Health, 91, 1922–1925.

    Article  PubMed Central  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  4. Gewirth, A. (1981). Are there any absolute rights? The Philosophical Quarterly 31, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Gostin, L. O. (2014). Global health law. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  6. Gruskin, S. (2002). Ethics, human rights and public health. American Journal of Public Health, 92, 698.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  7. Gruskin, S., & Tarantola, D. (2005). Health and human rights. In S. Gruskin, M. A. Grodin, G. J. Annas, & S. P. Marks (Eds.), Perspectives on health and human rights (pp. 3–61). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Gruskin, S., Grodin, M. A., Annas, G. J., & Marks, S. P. (2005). Introduction: Approaches, methods and strategies in health and human rights. In S. Gruskin, M. A. Grodin, G. J. Annas, & S. P. Marks (Eds.), Perspectives on health and human rights (pp. xii–xix). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Iacopino, V. (2005). Teaching human rights in graduate health education. In S. Gruskin, M. A. Grodin, G. J. Annas, & S. P. Marks (Eds.), Perspectives on health and human rights (pp. 508–526). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Mann, J. M. (1999). Medicine and public health, ethics and human rights. In J. M. Mann, S. Gruskin, M. A. Grodin, & G. J. Annas (Eds.), Health and human rights: A reader (pp. 439–452). London: Routlege.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Mann, J., Gostin, L., Gruskin, S., Brennan, T., Lazzarini, Z., & Fineberg, H. V. (1994). Health and human rights. Health and Human Rights, 1, 6–93.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  12. Mann, J. M., Gruskin, S., Grodin, M. A., & Annas, G. J. (1999). Introduction. In J. M. Mann, S. Gruskin, M. A. Grodin, & G. J. Annas (Eds.), Health and human rights: A reader (pp. 1–4). London: Routlege.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Nickel, J. W. (2008). Rethinking indivisibility: Towards a theory of supporting relations between human rights. Human Rights Quarterly, 30, 984–1001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Sen, A. (2009). The idea of justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Shue, H. (1996). Basic rights: Subsistence, affluence, and U.S. foreign policy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Thomson, J. J. (1986). Some ruminations on rights. In W. Parent (Ed.), Rights, restitution, and risk: Essays in moral theory (pp. 49–65). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Thomson, J. J. (1990). The realm of rights. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  18. United Nations. (1985). Economic and social council, Siracusa principles on the limitation and derogation provisions in the international covenant on civil and political rights, U.N. Doc. E/CN.4/1985/4, Annex.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Angus Dawson, who first got me to start thinking more about human rights in the context of public and global health when he invited me to speak at a joint meeting of the International Association of Bioethics’ Public Health Ethics Network (InterPHEN) and the Philosophy and Bioethics Network in Singapore in 2010 that provided the basis for this paper. I would also like to thank Claire Lougarre for helpful comments on an earlier draft of the manuscript, and John Coggon for inviting me to participate in the special issue.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to A. M. Viens.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Viens, A.M. Interdependence, Human Rights and Global Health Law. Health Care Anal 23, 401–417 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-015-0302-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-015-0302-2

Keywords

Navigation