Skip to main content
Log in

Levels of organization: a deflationary account

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The idea of levels of organization plays a central role in the philosophy of the life sciences. In this article, I first examine the explanatory goals that have motivated accounts of levels of organization. I then show that the most state-of-the-art and scientifically plausible account of levels of organization, the account of levels of mechanism proposed by Bechtel and Craver, is fundamentally problematic. Finally, I argue that the explanatory goals can be reached by adopting a deflationary approach, where levels of organization give way to more well-defined and fundamental notions, such as scale and composition.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Heil (2003) has forcefully argued against ontological levels of being, but these are different from levels of organization, as they are not defined in terms of composition, and involve stronger metaphysical assumptions.

  2. Bechtel and Craver have developed their accounts of levels independently, but they are very similar. I will point out the differences where they are relevant. Bechtel and Craver also discuss levels in one joint article (Craver and Bechtel 2007).

  3. This does not imply any non-reductive view of levels or higher-level properties. The fact that levels capture features of the organization of nature does not mean that those features are irreducible. The account of Oppenheim and Putnam is ontologically reductive: “Any whole which possesses a decomposition into parts all of which are on a given level, will be counted as belonging to that level. Thus each level includes all higher levels. However, the highest level to which a thing belongs will be considered the “proper” level of that thing” (Oppenheim and Putnam 1958, 9–10).

  4. Levels also often appear in the context of theories of emergence, but I take this to fall under goals G1, G2 and G4. Alternatively, one could add to the list “understanding emergence” as a further goal—the list is not intended to be exhaustive. In any case, emergence is not a topic of this article.

  5. A full-text search for the phrase “cellular level” for the period January 2004–January 2014 found the phrase in 572 articles. The total number of papers involved in the search was around 16,500 (the journal publishes roughly 50 issues per year, and there are usually at least 30 papers per issue). This means that the phrase appeared in <3.5 % of the papers. The results for “molecular level” and “behavioral level” were even lower (269 and 212 respectively).

  6. In some fields of the life sciences, such as the study of protein structure, ecology, or systems biology, talk of levels (of organization) may be more common. However, also in these fields the talk of levels can mostly be understood in terms of more fundamental notions, such as scale and composition. See Love (2012) for a discussion of levels of organization in proteins; Potochnik and McGill (2012) for a critical account of levels in ecology; and Richardson and Stephan (2007) for an interesting discussion of levels in systems biology.

  7. This problem is briefly introduced in Eronen (2013).

  8. Craver (personal communication) has pointed out that he no longer believes we need a criterion for being at the same level—what is important is determining when things are at different levels.

  9. To be exact, in Craver’s (2007) framework we should not simply talk of components, but always include the activity the component is engaged in (X’s Φ-ing, S’s Ψ-ing, etc.). However, for the sake of readability I have left out the variables denoting the activities, and mostly just talk of components. Nothing crucial turns on this, and it should be noted that Craver himself switches back and forth between talk of components and acting entities.

  10. Bechtel’s criterion for being at the same level leads to the same conclusion when combined with the mutual manipulability criterion.

  11. The distinction between components and direct components is briefly introduced in Eronen (2013).

  12. As pointed out in Footnote 4, this appears to be the approach Craver himself now favors.

  13. Wimsatt (1994/2007, 221–240) also explicitly states that levels of organization do not apply in many domains of the life sciences, where neat compositional relations break down and it is more appropriate to talk of “perspectives” or “causal thickets”. It should also be noted that Wimsatt’s idea that at some scales we find peaks of regularity and predictability is entirely compatible with my deflationary approach.

  14. Potochnik and McGill (2012) have proposed an approach to levels that comes close my deflationary view. Focusing on ecology, they argue that the idea of (universal) hierarchical levels of organization is deeply problematic, and suggest replacing levels with scales or “quasi-levels” that are derived from scales. The idea is that in a particular context or domain under study we may find that causal processes cluster at a given scale, and therefore it makes sense to talk of a quasi-level at that scale.

  15. I am indebted to McCauley (2009) for this idea. He develops a similar approach, but his account is not deflationary, since he aims at defending (something like) the traditional idea of levels of organization.

References

  • Alexander S (1920) Space, time, and deity, vol II. Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W (1994) Levels of descriptions and explanation in cognitive science. Mind Mach 4:1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W (2008) Mental mechanisms. Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle J (1998) Psychoneural reduction: the new wave. MIT Press, Cambridge

  • Broad CD (1925) The mind and its place in nature. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell DT (1974) “Downward Causation” in hierarchically organised biological systems. In: Ayala F, Dobzhansky T (eds) Studies in the philosophy of biology. University of California Press, Berkeley, pp 179–186

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland PS, Sejnowski TJ (1992) The computational brain. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Couch MB (2011) Mechanisms and constitutive relevance. Synthese 183:375–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver CF (2002) Interlevel experiments and multilevel mechanisms in the neuroscience of memory. Philos Sci 69:S83–S97

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver CF (2007) Explaining the brain. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver CF, Bechtel W (2007) Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biol Philos 20:715–734

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver CF, Darden L (2013) In search of mechanisms: discoveries across the life sciences. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Emmeche C, Køppe S, Stjernfelt F (2000) Levels, emergence, and three versions of downward causation. In: Andersen PB, Emmeche C, Finnemann NO, Christiansen PV (eds) Downward causation minds, bodies and matter. Aarhus University Press, Århus, pp 13–34

    Google Scholar 

  • Eronen MI (2013) No levels, no problems: downward causation in neuroscience. Philos Sci 80:1042–1052

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fazekas P, Kertész G (2011) Causation at different levels: tracking the commitments of mechanistic explanations. Biol Philos 26:365–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan S (2010) Mechanisms, causes, and the layered model of the world. Philos Phenomenol Res 81:362–381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heil J (2003) From an ontological point of view. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker CA (1981a) Towards a general theory of reduction. Part I: historical and scientific setting. Dialogue 20:38–59

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker CA (1981b) Towards a general theory of reduction. Part II: identity in reduction. Dialogue 20:201–236

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker CA (1981c) Towards a general theory of reduction. Part III: cross-categorial reduction. Dialogue 20:496–529

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kandel ER, Schwartz JH, Jessell T (2000) Principles of neural science, 4th edn. McGraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (1992) ‘Downward causation’ in emergentism and nonreductive physicalism. In: Beckermann A, Flohr H, Kim J (eds) Emergence or reduction? Essays on the prospects of nonreductive physicalism. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 119–138

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (1998) Mind in a physical world. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (2002) The layered model: metaphysical considerations. Philos Explor 5:2–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (2003) Blocking causal drainage and other maintenance chores with mental causation. Philos Phenomenol Res 67:151–176

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (2005) Physicalism, or something near enough. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman J, Ross D (2007) Every thing must go: metaphysics naturalised. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Love AC (2012) Hierarchy, causation and explanation: ubiquity, locality and pluralism. Interface Focus 2:115–125

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malenka RC, Bear MF (2004) LTP and LTD: an embarrassment of riches. Neuron 44:5–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCauley RN (2009) Time is of the essence: explanatory pluralism and accommodating theories about long-term processes. Philos Psychol 22:611–635

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGaugh JL (2000) Memory—a century of consolidation. Science 287:248–251

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel E (1961) The structure of science. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheim P, Putnam H (1958) Unity of science as a working hypothesis. Minn Stud Philos Sci 2:3–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik A, McGill B (2012) The limitations of hierarchical organization. Philos Sci 79:120–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Purves D, Augustine G, Fitzpatrick D, Hall W, LaMantia A-S, McNamara J, White LE (eds) (2008) Neuroscience. Sinauer, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson RC, Stephan A (2007) Mechanism and mechanical explanation in systems biology. In: Boogerd FC, Bruggeman FJ, Hofmeyr JS, Westerhoff HV (eds) Systems biology: philosophical foundations. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 123–144

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rueger A, McGivern P (2010) Hierarchies and levels of reality. Synthese 176:379–397

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner K (1993) Discovery and explanation in biology and medicine. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1962) The architecture of complexity. Proc Am Philos Soc 106:467–482

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (1994/2007). The ontology of complex systems: levels of organization, perspectives, and causal thickets. In Wimsatt WC (2007) Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings. Piecewise approximations to reality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 193–240. Originally published in Can J Philos S20, 207–274

  • Wright C, Bechtel W (2007) Mechanisms and psychological explanation. In: Thagard P (ed) Philosophy of psychology and cognitive science (volume 4 of the handbook of the philosophy of science). Elsevier, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank the following individuals for their helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper and related presentations: Luca Barlassina, Laura Bringmann, Dan Brooks, Carl Craver, Bob Richardson, Raphael van Riel, and an anonymous referee of this journal. I also thank the Research Foundation—Flanders (FWO) for financially supporting the research that resulted in this publication.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Markus I. Eronen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Eronen, M.I. Levels of organization: a deflationary account. Biol Philos 30, 39–58 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-014-9461-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-014-9461-z

Keywords

Navigation