Skip to main content

Saving Proof from Paradox: Gödel’s Paradox and the Inconsistency of Informal Mathematics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Logical Studies of Paraconsistent Reasoning in Science and Mathematics

Part of the book series: Trends in Logic ((TREN,volume 45))

Abstract

In this paper I shall consider two related avenues of argument that have been used to make the case for the inconsistency of mathematics: firstly, Gödel’s paradox which leads to a contradiction within mathematics and, secondly, the incompatibility of completeness and consistency established by Gödel’s incompleteness theorems. By bringing in considerations from the philosophy of mathematical practice on informal proofs, I suggest that we should add to the two axes of completeness and consistency a third axis of formality and informality. I use this perspective to respond to the arguments for the inconsistency of mathematics made by Beall and Priest, presenting problems with the assumptions needed concerning formalisation, the unity of informal mathematics and the relation between the formal and informal.

This work was supported by the Caroline Elder Scholarship and a St Andrews/Stirling Philosophy Scholarship. Many thanks to two anonymous referees, Aaron Cotnoir, Benedikt Löwe, Noah Friedman-Biglin, Jc Beall, Graham Priest, Alex Yates, Ryo Ito, Morgan Thomas, Brian King and audiences in St Andrews, Cambridge and Munich.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    A terminological note: while I speak of ‘informal proofs’ and ‘formal proofs’, some of the literature on this subject instead speaks of ‘proofs’ and ‘derivations’ to get at the same distinction. In [15], Priest also uses the term ‘naïve proof’ to refer to the informal proofs.

  2. 2.

    In [15], Priest argues that these conditions will be met. I believe that the flawed step in the argument is the earlier one of formalisation (as will be covered in Sect. 5), so I will not actively engage in a discussion about whether this formalisation will have an effective calculus etc.

  3. 3.

    At this point we are only concerned with the informal version of the paradox. Later I take on the formal results of Gödel’s theorems.

  4. 4.

    A final note on Beall: although the argument I am criticising is from an older paper, the response offered here would fit well with Beall’s more recent work in Beal [4]. The suggestion I have made may be appropriated to make the case that informal proof should join truth in the category of useful devices, which when introduced bring ‘merely’ semantic paradoxes as by-products or ‘spandrels’ without thereby rendering the base language (in this case, that of mathematics) inconsistent.

  5. 5.

    As the target of his argument, Priest needs to explain what he takes naïve or informal mathematics to be exactly. He says:

    Proof, as understood by mathematicians (not logicians), is that process of deductive argumentation by which we establish certain mathematical claims to be true. [15, p. 40]

    His distinction is, in effect, the same as the distinction between formal and informal mathematics as found in Sect. 2.

  6. 6.

    The matter is somewhat more complicated than this suggests, of course. Milne discusses in [12] the many ways that Gödel sentences can be constructed and what exactly they ‘say’.

  7. 7.

    Not just this, though, since Priest takes it that the theory given by the formalisation of informal mathematics can prove its own soundness and hence must be able to give its own semantics. From here he takes it to follow that it must be able to prove the T-scheme for this theory inside the theory, giving him all of the paradoxes he describes as semantic (as opposed to set-theoretic paradoxes). For example, he lists the liar, Grelling’s paradox, Berry’s paradox, Richard’s paradox and Koenig’s paradox as falling under the umbrella of semantic paradoxes. In fact, then, Priest argues that “Our naive theory is semantically closed and inconsistent. By contrast, any consistent theory cannot be semantically closed.” [15, p. 47].

  8. 8.

    The ‘many’ here is due to the fact that it might end up being case that multiple informal proofs are mapped to the same formal proof.

  9. 9.

    I use the terms ‘super-theory’ and ‘super-system’ throughout this paper. I do not intend anything of the ‘super-’ prefix besides that it is all-encompassing of mathematics in the way described.

  10. 10.

    An anonymous referee suggests that we may be able to distinguish between a plurality of results which are equivalent under translation and those which genuinely disagree. I believe, however, that this will not save the argument. In a critical discussion of Azzouni’s formalist account of proofs [20], I have previously argued that such a move is not going to deliver the substantial kind of formalisation required for the argument to proceed.

  11. 11.

    An anonymous referee proposes an additional argument against Priest based on this section: that the translation on the many-many case is not effective means that informal proof can therefore not meet the minimum requirements for falling under Gödel’s theorems. Grist to the mill!

  12. 12.

    And we are well used to theories being incomplete for more reasons than Gödel theorem. For instance, Peano arithmetic also has examples like Goodstein’s theorem and the Paris-Harrington theorem.

  13. 13.

    Note that this cannot be avoided by insisting that the Gödel sentence must be part of naïve arithmetic without running afoul of the distinction of Sect. 3.

  14. 14.

    I take it that, as mathematicians, we don’t need to commit ourselves to the truth, in some philosophical sense, of the mathematics that is being carried out.

  15. 15.

    Or, at least, to see incomplete and inconsistent systems as both serving purposes which may be justified by key pragmatic principles.

References

  1. Azzouni, J. (2004). The derivation-indicator view of mathematical practice. Philosophia Mathematica (III), 12, 81–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Azzouni, J. (2005). How to nominalize formalism. Philosophia Mathematica (III), 13, 135–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Beall, J. (1999). From full blooded platonism to really full blooded platonism. Philosophia Mathematica (III), 7, 322–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Beall, J. (2009). Spandrels of Truth. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  5. Benacerraf, P. (1965). What numbers could not be. The Philosophical Review, 74, 47–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Carnap, R. (1945). The two concepts of probability. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 5, 513–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Dutilh Novaes, C. (2011). The different ways in which logic is (said to be) formal. History and Philosophy of Logic, 32, 303–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Hersh, R. (1997). Prove–once more and again. Philosophia Mathematica (III), 5, 153–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Larvor, B. (2012). How to think about informal proofs. Synthese, 187, 715–730.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Leitgeb, H. (2009). “On Formal and Informal Provability”. In O. Bueno, Ø. Linnebo(Eds.), (2009): New Waves in Philosophy of Mathematics, Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 263–299.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Marfori, M. A. (2010). Informal proofs and mathematical rigour. Studia Logica, 96, 261–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Milne, P. (2007). On Gödel sentences and what they say. Philosophia Mathematica (III), 15, 193–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Nelsen, R. B. (1993). Proofs Without Words: Exercises in Visual Thinking. Washington: The Mathematical Association of America.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Nelsen, R. B. (2000). Proofs Without Words II: More Exercises in Visual Thinking. Washington: The Mathematical Association of America.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Priest, G. (1987). In Contradiction: A Study of the Transconsistent. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  16. Priest, G. (2012). “Mathematical Pluralism”, Logic Journal of the IGPL, pp. 4–13.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Rav, Y. (1999). Why do we prove theorems? Philosophia Mathematica (III), 7, 5–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Rav, Y. (2007). “A critique of a formalist-mechanist version of the justification of arguments in mathematicians’ proof practices”, Philosophia Mathematica (III) 15, pp. 291-320.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Robinson, J.A. (1991). “Formal and Informal Proofs” In R.S. Boyer (Ed.),: Automated Reasoning, pp. 267–282. Berlin: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Tanswell, F.S. (2015). “A Problem with the Dependence of Informal Proofs on Formal Proofs”, Philosophia Mathematica (III), Vol. 23(3), currently available through advance access.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Fenner Stanley Tanswell .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Tanswell, F.S. (2016). Saving Proof from Paradox: Gödel’s Paradox and the Inconsistency of Informal Mathematics. In: Andreas, H., Verdée, P. (eds) Logical Studies of Paraconsistent Reasoning in Science and Mathematics. Trends in Logic, vol 45. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-40220-8_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics